Psuche as Substantial Form

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Psuche as Substantial Form"

Transcription

1 Psuche as Substantial Form March 24,

2 After mentioning and discussing previous accounts of the soul, Aristotle states in De Anima II.1 his intention to begin his own definition of the soul: "Τὰ μἐν ὑπὸ τῶν πρότερον παραδεδομένα περὶ ψθχῆς εἰρησθω πάλιν δ' ὥσπερ ἐξ ὑπαρχῆς ἐπανίωμεν, πειρώμενοι διορίσαι τί ἐστι ψυχὴ καὶ τίς ἂν εἴη κοινότατος λόγος αὐτῆς." 1 Keeping his word, Aristotle begins to give a general definition of the soul. By the close of the chapter, he seems to have achieved his goal as he states: "τύπῳ μὲν οὖν ταύτῃ διωρίσθω καὶ ὑπογεγράφθω περὶ ψυχῆς" (413a9-10). 2 Having given a general definition, Aristotle is ready to begin a closer and more specific examination of the soul. In his essay "Aristotle's Definitions of "Psuche,'" 3 however, J. L. Ackrill asserts that the account Aristotle gives in De Anima II.1 is problematic. In Aristotle's application of his standard hylomorphic account to the body-soul composite, Ackrill argues that his account of the soul becomes "unintelligible" 4 in light of the homonymy principle. This difficulty Ackrill raises has spurred much discussion. Among the responses, Jennifer Whiting in her essay "Living Bodies" 5 claims to offer a solution. In this paper, I will first present Ackrill's articulation of the difficulty and his refutation of possible solutions. Then, I will present Whiting's response and her 1 Aristotle, De Anima, ed. W. D. Ross (New York: Oxford UP, 1959), 25: 412a3-6. For the rest of the paper, I will use in-text citation for this text, providing my translation in footnotes. "So then, the opinions concerning the soul handed down by those who came before have been recorded. Again, just as from the beginning, let us return to the point, attempting to define what the soul is and what might be its most general definition." 2 "So then, by this account let "soul" be defined and sketched out in outline." 3 J. L. Ackrill, "Aristotle's Definition of "Psuche,'" Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 73 ( ): Ibid, Jennifer Whiting, "Living Bodies," in Essays on Aristotle's De Anima, ed. Martha C. Nussbaum and Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (New York: Oxford UP, 2003),

3 furthering of the discussion. Finally, I will present St. Thomas Aquinas' commentary on the text as providing a solution to the difficulty as well as my own evaluation and reflection. I Ackrill picks out three formulae that Aristotle offers for the definition of the soul in De Anima II.1: "(a) 'the form of a natural body that has life potentially'; (b) 'the first actuality of a natural body that has life potentially'; and (c) 'the first actuality of a natural body that has organs'." 6 In such formulae, Aristotle is relying upon the hylomorphic account of what a thing is that distinguishes three elements: matter, form, and the composite of these two. 7 Such an account, Ackrill claims, puts to use the "is" of constitution, so that: "An item designated under (1) is (constitutes) an item under (3) if it has the form (shape, character, power) indicated under (2). Under (1) will normally be found material- or stuff-words; under (3), sortals; and under (2), names or descriptions of properties, structures, powers, and the like." 8 Aristotle regularly makes use of the hylomorphic account and applies it to a range of various things. An axe, for instance is explained as wood and iron (matter) that possess the power to chop (form) and so constitute an axe (composite). Similarly, potentialities and actualities fit the same account. Thus, an orchestra's ability to perform a symphony (matter) can be actualized (form) and so constitute a performance (composite). It becomes clear, then, that in De Anima II.1, Aristotle is merely taking his familiar hylomorphic account and applying it to living things. Yet, Ackrill calls attention to a critical difficulty in transferring such an account to living things. In applying the hylomorphic account to 6 Ackrill, 119. My translation does not differ from Ackrill's significantly. 7 The hylomorphic account is fundamental to Aristotelean metaphysics. He relies upon hylomorphism in explaining what things are and it is crucial for his explanation of change. 8 Ackrill,

4 non-living things, there is a common trait: the matter is something that is able to be picked out. Wood and iron, for example, can be picked out as the matter of the composite axe; one can imagine the wood and iron before they became part of an axe and recognize that they need not have become an axe. Similarly, it is possible, in most cases, for the wood and iron to remain should the axe be destroyed. The same applies to potentialities and actualities. From this observation, Ackrill concludes that the hylomorphic account: "depend(s) upon the idea that something that is actually the case might not have been: this stuff might not have been so arranged, the capacity being now displayed might have remained undisplayed." 9 Yet, having established this requirement, the application of the hylomorphic account to living things becomes impossible, Ackrill argues, due to what is referred to as Aristotle's "homonymy principle." 10 According to this principle, something ensouled or functionally defined does not, properly speaking, exist prior to or after being ensouled or having the capacity to perform its function. Such a principle, Ackrill asserts, forces Aristotle's account of the bodysoul-composite to be "unintelligible." 11 For, according to the the hylomorphic account, the body of a living thing must be able to be picked out as that which might not have been the case. Yet, according to the homonymy principle, such a body could not possibly have been the case prior to being ensouled. Thus, Ackrill's "complaint" is that Aristotle's position: "commits him to something that he cannot allow to be possible in the case of living beings, namely that what has form might have lacked it that the same matter both has and might not have had the form." 12 In order to save Aristotle's account of the soul, Ackrill proposes three possible solutions. First, one could disregard the homonymy principle altogether. In doing so, one could point to 9 Ibid. 10 Ibid, Ibid, Ibid,

5 Aristotle's lack of precision in his setting down of the principle as he is not clear in saying how strict the principle holds. For example, it is quite clear that Aristotle considers an axe that is no longer capable of chopping as an axe only in name. It is not so clear, however, if he would thereby consider an axe that has merely become blunt, and still capable of being re-sharpened, also as an axe only in name. 13 Indeed, it seems more reasonable that he would not. If, then, the homonymy principle would not apply in such cases, it seems it could also be argued as inapplicable to the body of a living thing if one considers the body as capable of being reanimated. Such a case would then allow for the body to be that which might not have been ensouled and that which will survive the loss of the soul. Though such thought experiments are increasingly credible with modern advancements in technology and medicine, Ackrill ultimately disregards this possibility. Not only is it foreign to Aristotle's thought, but it also fails to get at the root of the difficulty. 14 The second possibility Ackrill presents is for the homoiomerous parts, 15 such as flesh, bones, and blood, to serve as the matter of a living thing as opposed to the body. This proposal would apparently solve the difficulty. Yet, while granting that Aristotle often draws distinctions between the homoiomerous parts and the functionally defined parts, Ackrill denies that the former provides a solution to the original difficulty. For, in several texts, Aristotle attributes functions to the homoiomerous parts just as he does to the body and its organs. Thus, the homoiomerous parts, too, fall subject to the same charge laid against the body. Namely, the homoiomerous parts as such are necessarily alive In a footnote to his commentary on the text, Ronald M. Polanksy denies this argument by Ackrill. Rather, Aristotle is, in fact, aware of such considerations in which things are temporarily incapable of performing their functions. See Aristotle's De Anima: a critical commentary (New York: Cambridge UP, 2007), Ackrill, As the term suggests, a homoiomerous part is such that all its parts are similar to one another and to itself. It is a simple and uniform mixture. 16 Ibid,

6 The third and final possibility Ackrill proposes is for the four elements to be the matter of a living thing. The elements, unlike the homoiomerous parts, are not functionally defined and are thereby not necessarily alive. Further, Aristotle holds that any material is ultimately composed out of the elements and even refers, at times, to the elements as the 'matter' of man. 17 Despite such accounts, Ackrill shows that other texts make clear that Aristotle would not consider the elements as the material of man or that the elements could even be said to be potentially a man, 18 for Aristotle regards them as too remote. Thus, the elements also fail to serve as as an alternative for the matter of a living thing. 19 So, having exhausted the possibilities, Ackrill concludes that the hylomorphic account is inadequate in explaining what the soul of a living thing is. 20 II Accepting the difficulty Ackrill raises, Whiting responds by asserting that it rests upon two assumptions: (a) that the homoiomerous parts are the ultimate matter of a living thing to the exclusion of the four elements, and (b) that the homoiomerous parts, being functionally defined, cannot survive the loss of the soul. 21 Whiting, however, cites two instances within the very passage of De Anima II.1 where Aristotle lays down the homonymy principle which both seem to indicate that something of the living thing does survive the loss of the soul. First, in applying the principle to the eye, Aristotle says: "ἧς ἀπολει πούσης οὐκέτ' ὀφθαλμός, πλὴν 17 Ibid, Ibid. 19 Ibid, Ackrill does not think that living things are the only things that pose difficulties for Aristotle's hylomorphism. He mentions chemical mixtures as similarly resisting fitting the mold. For instance, in the example he gives, the ingredients that go into a cake cannot be picked out once the cake has been baked, see Whiting, 78. 6

7 ὁμωνύμως" 22 (412b21). Highlighting οὐκέτ', Whiting asserts that something is no longer an eye. 23 Likewise, in applying the principle to the whole body, Aristotle says: "ἔστι δὲ οὐ τὸ ἀποβεβληκὸς τὴν ψυχὴν τὸ δυνάμει ὂν ὥστε ζῆν, ἀλλὰ τὸ ἔχον" 24 (412b25-6). Highlighting Aristotle's use of the perfect participle ἀποβεβληκὸς, Whiting concludes that something is no longer a potentially living thing. 25 Thus, in both cases, there is something of the living thing that survives the loss of the soul. To allow something to survive the loss of the soul, Whiting must address the two assumptions she introduces, and she starts with the second. Though most, including Ackrill, disregard the possibility of the homoiomerous parts surviving the loss of the soul, as they are functionally defined just as the body and organs are, Whiting argues to the contrary, citing a passage from the Metaphysics. 26 In this passage, Aristotle admits that it is not clear when the flesh and blood of a living thing perishes. 27 If, however, the flesh and blood are functionally defined strictly and rely upon the soul to persist, Aristotle's admission must be explained. Whiting's answer is to pick out two distinct accounts of flesh that Aristotle gives throughout his works, namely, functional flesh and compositional flesh. 28 The former is defined by its relation to the other functionally defined parts of the body. Thus, if this relation is destroyed, for instance, by the loss of the soul, it cannot survive; it looses its ability to function and is not the same flesh strictly. 22 "Which, if it (the power to see) is taken away, there is no longer an eye, except equivocally." 23 Ibid, "And that which has lost its soul is not which is potentially alive, but that which has a soul." 25 Whiting, Metaphysics, Whiting, Ibid. 7

8 Yet, Aristotle also discusses flesh as the various proportions of the elements that constitute the material of the functional parts. These proportions are casually necessary, though not sufficient, for the flesh or body of a living thing. 29 In this sense, flesh is not functionally defined, being purely material, and thus: "is only homonymous with functional flesh and so can survive the loss of the soul." 30 As the compositional flesh makes up the functional flesh of a living thing and can survive the loss of the soul even though the functional cannot, Whiting concludes that the compositional flesh is the matter that can allow for continuity between a living thing and its corpse. 31 Such a solution, however, relies upon the elements, albeit it in specific proportions, to serve as the matter of a living thing. Thus, in arguing against the second assumption, Whiting also argues against the first, namely, that the elements cannot be the matter of a living thing. The standard objections to such a solution rely upon two texts from the Metaphysics. Whiting claims that both, however, are misread. In the first, 32 Aristotle says that the elements should not be named as the material of man as they are too remote. Though Aristotle is seeking the most proximate (ἐγγύτατα) cause of man, Whiting denies that the elements are thereby incapable of being the matter of man whatsoever. Rather, the very use of the superlative displays that there are other, more remote causes of man. 33 Thus, though perhaps irrelevant to the specific task at hand, the elements are nevertheless part of the material of a living thing. 29 Whiting, Ibid, Ibid. 32 Metaphysics, 1044b Whiting, 81. 8

9 In the second passage, 34 Aristotle states that the seed, not earth or any other element, is that which is potentially a man. 35 Yet, Whiting draws attention to Aristotle's use of temporal adverbs. 36 Aristotle says that the elements are not potentially a man or any living thing yet. Once present in a seed in the right conditions, however, then they are potentially the body of a living thing. 37 Thus, having addressed both passages, Whiting concludes that the elements can constitute the compositional matter of a living thing. Having established this, Whiting moves to elucidate the relation between functional flesh and compositional flesh in order to allow for the matter of a living thing to be both accidentally and contingently ensouled. To do so, she cites a different text, one from Aristotle's De Partibus Animalium In this passage, Aristotle describes a mixture of earth and water and picks out certain relations and characteristics. One, despite becoming part of the mixture and assuming a liquid character, the earth is capable of being separated from the mixture. Should it be separated, the earth would return to being dry. Two, the earth is only accidentally liquid when it is part of the mixture. 39 As flesh and the other homoiomerous parts of a living thing are mixtures of the elements, Whiting applies the above characteristics to the body-soul composite. Just as the earth survives its mixture with water, so the elements, survive their mixture with the soul. As the earth takes on the liquid character of the mixture accidentally, so the elements are accidentally and not 34 Metaphysics, 1049a Aristotle mentions this same idea briefly in De Anima II.1 412b25-7: "ἔστι δὲ οὐ τὸ ἀποβεβληκὸς τὴν ψυχὴν τὸ δυνάμει ὂν ὥστε ζῆν, ἀλλὰ τὸ ἔχον τὸ δὲ σπέρμα καὶ ὁ καρπὸς τὸ δυνάμει τοιονδὶ σῶμα." "And that which has lost its soul is not which is potentially alive, but that which has a soul. The seed and the fruit are potentially such a body." 36 Whiting, Ibid, Ibid. 39 Ibid. Whiting actually discusses a third in addition to the two above. The third is Aristotle's comment that the water is both potentially and actually liquid. This point, too, bears on the discussion of the body-soul relation, but it is not specifically relevant to my paper. 9

10 essentially ensouled. Thus, Whiting concludes, when the body loses its soul and the composite dissolves, the elements, which comprise the compositional flesh, survive for they are not essentially ensouled. 40 That the elements are accidentally and not essentially ensouled, Whiting emphasizes, is key. Aristotle understands the elements as constituting the material that make up different things at different times. Though they underly all material, of animate and inanimate things alike, the elements do not, in cases of generation and destruction simpliciter, undergo a mere rearrangement. 41 Unlike artificial things, the change from a living body to a corpse is not fully explained by a change in its composition. To make this distinction clear, Whiting proposes a precise articulation of the relation between the elements and the things they make up. Rather than stating that earth becomes flesh and then becomes a pot, one should say the flesh that was earthen was destroyed and the pot that is earthen comes to be. 42 The latter articulation makes clear that the matter merely predicates the different subjects: "the matter is now the matter of a different subject." 43 Living things, however, are an "intrinsic unity"; their form is the form of their specific matter and their matter is the matter of their specific form. 44 In this way, Whiting concludes, the functional body is essentially ensouled even though the compositional body, made up of the elements, is only accidentally ensouled. Thus, Whiting demonstrates how the body-soul composite can fit the hylomorphic account: the compositional body provides the matter that might not have been ensouled. As a final remark, Whiting explains why Aristotle opts to use the examples of an axe and an eye in his 40 Ibid, Ibid, Ibid, Ibid. 44 Ibid,

11 discussion of the body and soul of a living thing. 45 She posits that Aristotle uses the two examples to draw out a distinction. In order to actualize its power to chop, the axe requires an external agent to move it. Similarly, the eye, on its own, is unable to see apart from its relation to the rest of the body. Thus, neither possess an internal principle of movement, 46 and yet, Aristotle asks that one hypothesize as if they did. In doing so, Aristotle draws out the distinct character of the body-soul composite, namely, that the soul is the internal agent of the body. The body does not, like the axe, rely upon an external agent or, like the eye, upon a relation in order to perform its activity. Rather, its actuality is the source of its own movement. Thus Whiting concludes: "A natural body is potentially alive only given the presence of an internal efficient cause of its being alive, that is, only in presence of its soul." 47 III In response to the presumed difficulty of De Anima II.1, I propose an examination of St. Thomas Aquinas' commentary on the text. From the very onset, Aquinas provides guidance in reading and understanding the passage by calling attention to Aristotle's distinction in his Metaphysics between defining substance and defining accidents. 48 In defining substance, Aquinas reviews, nothing extrinsic to the substance is included in its definition as a substance is complete and wholly defined by giving only its matter and form. In defining accidents, however, something extrinsic must be referenced to as accidents exist only in relation to a substance. 45 Ibid, Aristotle calls attention to this himself in De Anima II.1 412b15-7: ""οὐ γὰρ τοιούτου σώματος τὸ τί ἦν εἶναι καὶ ὁ λόγος ἡ ψυχή, ἀλλὰ φυσικοῦ τοιουδί, ἔχοντος ἀρχὴν κινήσεως καὶ στάσεως ἐν ἑαυτῷ." "Yet, the soul is not the essence and definition of such a body, but of a natural body, as having a principle of motion and rest in itself." 47 Whiting, Thomas Aquinas, Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima, ed. and trans. Kenelm Foster, O.P. and Silvester Humphries, O.P. (Notre Dame, IN: Dumb Ox Books, 1994),

12 Forms, like accidents, are incomplete in of themselves and require that their proper subject be referred to in definition. Thus, it becomes clear that Aristotle's definition of the soul as form will thereby require a reference to and explanation of the soul's proper subject, namely, the body. Further in his commentary, Aquinas builds upon the distinction between substance and accident in discussing the distinction between substantial and accidental forms. 49 An accidental form does not cause a substance to be, rather, it only qualifies its existence. Thus, musical does not cause a musical man to be, rather, it qualifies the existence of man. Substantial forms, on the other hand, do give simple existence to their matter. Thus, the matter or proper subject of a substantial form cannot exist apart from that form. Throughout his commentary, Aquinas emphasizes that Aristotle understands the soul to be the form of the body as a substantial form. Where an accidental form presupposes an actually existing subject that it may qualify, the soul, as a substantial form, presupposes only: "a potentiality to existence, i.e. bare matter." 50 From this understanding of the soul as substantial form, the "difficulty" that Ackrill raises and Whiting accepts dissolves. To properly define the soul which is a form, Aristotle must refer to its proper subject. Yet, the soul is not only a form, but a substantial form. Thus, the proper subject or matter of the soul cannot exist as such apart from the soul. The soul, as its substantial form, gives such a body its basic existence. The body, therefore, which is the proper subject of the soul only exists in union with the soul its substantial form. Thus, in demanding that the matter of a living thing might not have been the case and can be picked out of the composite, Ackrill misguidedly limits the hylomorphic account. 51 In doing so, he misses the distinction between accidental and substantial forms and wrongly excludes such 49 Ibid, Ibid. 51 Polansky agrees,

13 a distinction from the hylomorphic account. Following this error, he then fails to understand the significance of the homonymy principle. In explaining the proper subject of a substantial form, the homonymy principle is crucial in making clear the intrinsic relation between the two. Once the matter loses its substantial form, it no longer exists in the same way. Rather, the matter of the living thing undergoes a substantial change. Its body is no longer the proper subject of the soul. Instead, what remains is a corpse, a different substance altogether, for: "When the soul leaves the body, another substantial form takes its place; for a passing-away always involves a concomitant coming-to-be." 52 Ackrill's hasty judgment of the hylomorphic account prevents his understanding the significance of Aristotle's appeal to the the homonymy principle. Aristotle does not claim that either the axe or the eye offers a perfect analogy to a living thing. In fact, Aristotle's repeated use of εἴ, ἂν, and the imperfect tense makes clear he is speaking hypothetically, for instance: "καθάπερ εἴ τι τῶν ὀργάνων φυσικὸν ἧν σῶμα, οἷον πέλεκυς ἧν μὲν γὰρ ἂν τὸ πελέκει εἶναι ἡ οὐσία αὐτοῦ, καὶ ἡ ψυχὴ τοῦτο" (412b11-3), 53 and: "εἰ γὰρ ἦν ὁ ὀφυαλμὸς ζῷον, ψυχὴ ἄν ἦν αὐτοῦ ἡ ὄψις" (412b18-9). 54 As Aquinas rightly notes, Aristotle uses both the axe and eye in order to draw out the soul's distinction as a substantial form. 55 In artificial bodies, such as the axe, the relation of the form to the matter is more evident and easier to grasp than that of the soul to the body. As more evident, the example helps one conceptualize the meaning of the soul as the substantial form of the body. Yet, unlike living things, when artifacts, such as the axe, 52 Aquinas, "Just as if some instrument were a natural body, for example an axe, its essence would be its being an axe, and this would be its soul." 54 "For if the eye were a living thing, the power to see would be its soul." 55 Aquinas,

14 lose their ability to perform their function, they still exist substantially as: "the substance of artificial things is their matter which remains when the artificial form and, with this artificial form, the actuality of the artificial body as such, is removed." 56 Living things, however, are not substances by virtue of their matter. Rather, they rely upon the union of the soul with its proper subject. Loss of either destroys the substance and what remains is only referred to as the same thing equivocally. The eye is a closer analogy to a living thing. It, too, along with the other functionally defined parts of a living thing, relies upon its form to exist as such. It is not, like artificial things, a substance simply by virtue of its matter. Rather, it relies upon its form, the power of sight as: "sight is the essential form of the eye." 57 Having grasped the dependence of the eye on its power to see, Aristotle invites one to grasp the relation of a living thing to its soul, moving from part to whole (412b21-5). 58 The example of the eye makes it easier to grasp the way in which the soul is the form of the body of a living thing, for, the function of a living thing is much more complex than that of an eye. Having grasped how the power to see is intrinsically related to the eye, it becomes clearer how the soul is related to a living thing. As her very acceptance of Ackrill's difficulty reveals, Whiting also fails to understand the soul as the substantial form of a living thing. It is worth noting that the concepts are understandably difficult to grasp. Yet, precisely for this reason, Aristotle offers the example of the axe and eye to help one reach a difficult understanding through more evident things. 56 Ibid, Ibid. 58 "δεῖ δὴ λαβεῖν τὸ ἐπὶ μέρους ἐφ' ὅλου τοῦ ζῶντος σώματος ἀνάλογον γὰρ ἔχει ὡς τὸ μέρος πρὸς τὸ μέρος, οὕτως ἡ ὅλη αἴσθησις πρὸς τὸ ὅλον σῶμα τὸ αἰσθητικόν, ᾗ τοιοῦτον." "Certainly we ought to apply what belongs to the part to that of the whole living body. For, an analogy holds: just as part of the sensitive power is to part of the body, so the entire sensitive power is to the entire sensitive body, as such." 14

15 Further, although Whiting takes Aristotle's use of οὐκέτ' and ἀποβεβληκὸς to indicate that something survives the loss of the soul, it is rather the most obvious and, perhaps only, way for Aristotle to convey what he is trying to explain. Similarly, though Whiting's account of compositional flesh and functional flesh is compelling, it again displays her failure to grasp the soul as substantial form. Though she very nearly hits upon this distinction in her discussion of the elements comprising compositional flesh as being accidentally ensouled as opposed to functional flesh, Whiting fails to articulate the soul as substantial form as accounting for such differences. Similarly, in explaining the Aristotle's requirement of essentially living bodies as allowing for generation and destruction simpliciter, Whiting displays an understanding of the body-soul composite as an intrinsic unity. She fails, however, to understand this distinction as a result of the soul being a substantial form. Whiting again displays her good instincts in her refection on why Aristotle compares the body and soul to the axe and the eye. She intuits that Aristotle is drawing out a distinction. Whiting's conclusion, however, that they serve to show the distinction between external and internal efficient causes, although a true observation, does not get at the heart of the matter. Thus, the presumed "difficulty" that Ackrill and Whiting center their discussions on De Anima II.1 reveal a fundamental misunderstanding of Aristotle's intention. Thus, both fail to grasp the meaning of the text. Understanding that the soul is the substantial form of the body is the key to a correct reading of the text and Aquinas is correct in his drawing out this distinction throughout his commentary. Thus, though Aristotle's account of the soul is still, as he says, in outline (τύπῳ), it is not one that presents insurmountable difficulties. 15

16 Bibliography Ackrill, J. L. "Aristotle's Definitions of "Psuche'," Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, New Series, 73 ( ): Aquinas, Thomas. Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima, edited and translated by Kenlem Foster, O.P. and Silvester Humphries, O.P. Notre Dame, IN: Dumb Ox Books, Aristotle. De Anima, edited by W. D. Ross. New York: Oxford University Press, Gendlin, Eugene T. Line by Line Commentary on Aristotle's De Anima. Spring Valley: Focusing Institute, Hicks, R. D. Aristotle: De Anima. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Polansky, Ronald M. Aristotle's De Anima: a critical commentary. New York: Cambridge University Press, Ross, David. Aristotle: De Anima. New York: Oxford University Press, Whiting, Jennifer. "Living Bodies." In Essays on Aristotle's De Anima. New York: Oxford University Press,

Aristotle s Naïve Somatism

Aristotle s Naïve Somatism Western University Scholarship@Western Electronic Thesis and Dissertation Repository April 2011 Aristotle s Naïve Somatism Alain E. Ducharme The University of Western Ontario Supervisor Dr. John Thorp

More information

Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5

Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5 Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5 Alan Code (I) An Alleged Difficulty for Aristotle s Conception of Matter Aristotle s Metaphysics employs a conception of matter for generated items

More information

Substantial Generation in Physics I 5-7

Substantial Generation in Physics I 5-7 Western University From the SelectedWorks of Devin Henry 2015 Substantial Generation in Physics I 5-7 Devin Henry, The University of Western Ontario Available at: https://works.bepress.com/devinhenry/24/

More information

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Z.13: Substances and Universals Summary of Zeta so far Z.13: Substances and Universals Let us now take stock of what we seem to have learned so far about substances in Metaphysics Z (with some additional ideas about essences from APst.

More information

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable, ARISTOTELIAN COLORS AS CAUSES Festschrift for Julius Moravcsik, edd., D.Follesdall, J. Woods, College Publications (London:2008), pages 235-242 For Aristotle the study of living things, speaking quite

More information

Aristotle's Metaphysics of Living Bodies. Thomas Gemelli B.A., Vassar College, 2006

Aristotle's Metaphysics of Living Bodies. Thomas Gemelli B.A., Vassar College, 2006 Aristotle's Metaphysics of Living Bodies by Thomas Gemelli B.A., Vassar College, 2006 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of

More information

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima Caleb Cohoe Caleb Cohoe 2 I. Introduction What is it to truly understand something? What do the activities of understanding that we engage

More information

Unity in Aristotle s Metaphysics H 6

Unity in Aristotle s Metaphysics H 6 Unity in Aristotle s Metaphysics H 6 EVAN KEELING Corcoran Department of Philosophy University of Virginia Abstract In this essay I argue that the central problem of Aristotle s Metaphysics H (VIII) 6

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] Like David Charles, I am puzzled about the relationship between Aristotle

More information

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles Patrick Maher Scientific Thought I Fall 2009 Introduction We ve seen that according to Aristotle: One way to understand something is by having a demonstration

More information

From Blood to Flesh: Homonymy, Unity, and Ways of Being in Aristotle

From Blood to Flesh: Homonymy, Unity, and Ways of Being in Aristotle Ancient Philosophy 35 (2015) Mathesis Publications 1 From Blood to Flesh: Homonymy, Unity, and Ways of Being in Aristotle Christopher Frey My topic is the fundamental Aristotelian division between the

More information

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code The aim of this paper is to explore and elaborate a puzzle about definition that Aristotle raises in a variety of forms in APo. II.6,

More information

Aristotle s Metaphysics

Aristotle s Metaphysics Aristotle s Metaphysics Book Γ: the study of being qua being First Philosophy Aristotle often describes the topic of the Metaphysics as first philosophy. In Book IV.1 (Γ.1) he calls it a science that studies

More information

Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms. Robert Pasnau

Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms. Robert Pasnau Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms Robert Pasnau Stephen Dumont has given us a masterful reconstruction of a fascinating fourteenth-century debate that lies at the boundary of metaphysics

More information

Saussurean Delimitation and Plato s Cratylus. In Ferdinand de Saussure s seminal Course in General Linguistics, a word is defined as a

Saussurean Delimitation and Plato s Cratylus. In Ferdinand de Saussure s seminal Course in General Linguistics, a word is defined as a Margheim!1 Stephen Margheim 10-8-12 Materials and Methods Paper on Language for Dr. Struck Saussurean Delimitation and Plato s Cratylus In Ferdinand de Saussure s seminal Course in General Linguistics,

More information

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology Massimiliano Carrara Assistant Professor Department of Philosophy University of Padova, P.zza Capitaniato 3, 35139

More information

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts Normativity and Purposiveness What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts of a triangle and the colour green, and our cognition of birch trees and horseshoe crabs

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

COURSE SYLLABUS. He psuche ta onta pos esti panta. Aristotle, De Anima 431 b21

COURSE SYLLABUS. He psuche ta onta pos esti panta. Aristotle, De Anima 431 b21 1 COURSE SYLLABUS COURSE TITLE: Aristotle s De Anima: A Phenomenological Reading COURSE/SECTION: PHL 415/101 CAMPUS/TERM: LPC, Fall 2017 LOCATION/TIME: McGowan South 204, TH 3:00-6:15pm INSTRUCTOR: Will

More information

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala 1 Forms and Causality in the Phaedo Michael Wiitala Abstract: In Socrates account of his second sailing in the Phaedo, he relates how his search for the causes (αἰτίαι) of why things come to be, pass away,

More information

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD 1 ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD Luboš Rojka Introduction Analogy was crucial to Aquinas s philosophical theology, in that it helped the inability of human reason to understand God. Human

More information

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy By Wesley Spears For Samford University, UFWT 102, Dr. Jason Wallace, on May 6, 2010 A Happy Ending The matters of philosophy

More information

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2) 1/9 Descartes on Simple Ideas (2) Last time we began looking at Descartes Rules for the Direction of the Mind and found in the first set of rules a description of a key contrast between intuition and deduction.

More information

of perception, elaborated in his De Anima as an isomorphic motion of the soul. It will begin by

of perception, elaborated in his De Anima as an isomorphic motion of the soul. It will begin by This paper will aim to establish that the proper interpretation of Aristotle's epistemology is one of direct realism, rather than representationalism, by way of exploring Aristotle's doctrine of perception,

More information

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. The Republic is intended by Plato to answer two questions: (1) What IS justice? and (2) Is it better to

More information

Plato s Absolute and Relative Categories at Sophist 255c14

Plato s Absolute and Relative Categories at Sophist 255c14 Plato s Absolute and Relative Categories at Sophist 255c14 Beginning at Sophist 255c9 1 the Eleatic Stranger attempts a proof that being (τὸ ὄν) and other (τὸ θάτερον) are different very great kinds. The

More information

Categories and Schemata

Categories and Schemata Res Cogitans Volume 1 Issue 1 Article 10 7-26-2010 Categories and Schemata Anthony Schlimgen Creighton University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Part of the

More information

ARISTOTLE S THEOLOGY AND ITS RELATION TO THE SCIENCE OF BEING QUA BEING. Shane Duarte

ARISTOTLE S THEOLOGY AND ITS RELATION TO THE SCIENCE OF BEING QUA BEING. Shane Duarte ARISTOTLE S THEOLOGY AND ITS RELATION TO THE SCIENCE OF BEING QUA BEING Shane Duarte I Introduction The aim of this paper is to develop and defend an answer to a longstanding interpretive problem confronted

More information

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 45, 2015 On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me IRENA CRONIN University of California, Los Angeles, USA G. E.

More information

Giuseppe Feola phantasìa, imagination, noûs: on the relation between phantàsmata and noēmata in Aristotle's psychology

Giuseppe Feola phantasìa, imagination, noûs: on the relation between phantàsmata and noēmata in Aristotle's psychology Giuseppe Feola phantasìa, imagination, noûs: on the relation between phantàsmata and noēmata in Aristotle's psychology Analytica posterior II 19 treats the problem of how we can reach the àmesai archài

More information

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason THE A PRIORI GROUNDS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE THAT a concept, although itself neither contained in the concept of possible experience nor consisting of elements

More information

1/9. The B-Deduction

1/9. The B-Deduction 1/9 The B-Deduction The transcendental deduction is one of the sections of the Critique that is considerably altered between the two editions of the work. In a work published between the two editions of

More information

ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME. Irena Cronin

ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME. Irena Cronin ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME Irena Cronin Abstract G. E. L. Owen, in his influential article Inherence, talks of vink, a name he has created for

More information

When and Why Understanding Needs Phantasmata:

When and Why Understanding Needs Phantasmata: When and Why Understanding Needs Phantasmata: A Moderate Interpretation of Aristotle s De Memoria and De Anima on the Role of Images in Intellectual Activities Abstract I examine the passages where Aristotle

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas Rachel Singpurwalla It is well known that Plato sketches, through his similes of the sun, line and cave, an account of the good

More information

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment First Moment: The Judgement of Taste is Disinterested. The Aesthetic Aspect Kant begins the first moment 1 of the Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment with the claim that

More information

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology Markku Keinänen University of Tampere [Draft, please do not quote without permission] ABSTRACT. According to Lowe s Four-Category

More information

Restoring Aristotle s Evaluative Theory of Deliberation

Restoring Aristotle s Evaluative Theory of Deliberation Restoring Aristotle s Evaluative Theory of Deliberation 1 Recent years have witnessed a revival of interest in Aristotle s theory of deliberation. Common to a number of these studies is the thesis that

More information

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford Published in in Real Metaphysics, ed. by H. Lillehammer and G. Rodriguez-Pereyra, Routledge, 2003, pp. 184-195. WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College,

More information

ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE

ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE AN EXAMINATION OF ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE By HORATIO ION BOT, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies

More information

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications One and Many in Aristotle s Metaphysics: Books Alpha-Delta. By Edward C. Halper. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing, 2009. Pp. xli + 578. $48.00 (hardback). ISBN: 978-1-930972-6. Julie K. Ward Halper s volume

More information

ORGANIC UNITY AND THE MATTER OF MAN

ORGANIC UNITY AND THE MATTER OF MAN Created on 30 November 2006 at 17.10 hours page 167 ORGANIC UNITY AND THE MATTER OF MAN CHRISTOPHER FREY 1. Introduction if we assume, as many have, that Aristotle s discussions of artefacts provide us

More information

Aristotle on the Human Good

Aristotle on the Human Good 24.200: Aristotle Prof. Sally Haslanger November 15, 2004 Aristotle on the Human Good Aristotle believes that in order to live a well-ordered life, that life must be organized around an ultimate or supreme

More information

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Anca-Gabriela Ghimpu Phd. Candidate UBB, Cluj-Napoca Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Paper contents Introduction: motivation

More information

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics REVIEW A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics Kristin Gjesdal: Gadamer and the Legacy of German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. xvii + 235 pp. ISBN 978-0-521-50964-0

More information

Kent Academic Repository

Kent Academic Repository Kent Academic Repository Full text document (pdf) Citation for published version Sayers, Sean (1995) The Value of Community. Radical Philosophy (69). pp. 2-4. ISSN 0300-211X. DOI Link to record in KAR

More information

Aristotle, Vision, and Communicable Change

Aristotle, Vision, and Communicable Change Aristotle, Vision, and Communicable Change Micah Bailey University of Kansas 1. Introduction In De Anima, Aristotle states: one must understand that the sense is that which is receptive of the sensible

More information

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION Submitted by Jessica Murski Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University

More information

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5 PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5 We officially started the class by discussing the fact/opinion distinction and reviewing some important philosophical tools. A critical look at the fact/opinion

More information

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction Introduction Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] As Kant emphasized, famously, there s a difference between

More information

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography Dawn M. Phillips 1 Introduction In his 1983 article, Photography and Representation, Roger Scruton presented a powerful and provocative sceptical position. For most people interested in the aesthetics

More information

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education Marilyn Zurmuehlen Working Papers in Art Education ISSN: 2326-7070 (Print) ISSN: 2326-7062 (Online) Volume 2 Issue 1 (1983) pps. 56-60 Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

More information

Chapter 1. The Power of Names NAMING IS NOT LIKE COUNTING

Chapter 1. The Power of Names NAMING IS NOT LIKE COUNTING Chapter 1 The Power of Names One of the primary sources of sophistical reasoning is the equivocation between different significations of the same word or phrase within an argument. Aristotle believes that

More information

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts Tim Black California State University, Northridge Spring 2004 I. PRELIMINARIES a. Last time, we were

More information

Monadology and Music 2: Leibniz s Demon

Monadology and Music 2: Leibniz s Demon Monadology and Music 2: Leibniz s Demon Soshichi Uchii (Kyoto University, Emeritus) Abstract Drawing on my previous paper Monadology and Music (Uchii 2015), I will further pursue the analogy between Monadology

More information

CLASSICAL GREEK. H044/01 Language. Summer 2017 examination series AS LEVEL. Exemplar Candidate Work. H044 For first teaching in 2016

CLASSICAL GREEK. H044/01 Language. Summer 2017 examination series AS LEVEL. Exemplar Candidate Work. H044 For first teaching in 2016 Qualification Accredited AS LEVEL CLASSICAL GREEK H044 For first teaching in 2016 H044/01 Language Summer 2017 examination series Version 1 www.ocr.org.uk/classics Contents Introduction 3 Question 1 4

More information

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Book Review Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Nate Jackson Hugh P. McDonald, Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values. New York: Rodopi, 2011. xxvi + 361 pages. ISBN 978-90-420-3253-8.

More information

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 5 September 16 th, 2015 Malevich, Kasimir. (1916) Suprematist Composition. Gaut on Identifying Art Last class, we considered Noël Carroll s narrative approach to identifying

More information

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Introduction Naïve realism regards the sensory experiences that subjects enjoy when perceiving (hereafter perceptual experiences) as being, in some

More information

Thomas Reid's Notion of Exertion

Thomas Reid's Notion of Exertion Thomas Reid's Notion of Exertion Hoffman, Paul David, 1952- Journal of the History of Philosophy, Volume 44, Number 3, July 2006, pp. 431-447 (Article) Published by The Johns Hopkins University Press DOI:

More information

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN: Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, 2013. Pp X -336. $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN: 978-0674724549. Lucas Angioni The aim of Malink s book is to provide a consistent

More information

QUESTION 7. The Circumstances of Human Acts

QUESTION 7. The Circumstances of Human Acts QUESTION 7 The Circumstances of Human Acts Next, we have to consider the circumstances of human acts. On this topic there are four questions: (1) What is a circumstance? (2) Should a theologian take into

More information

ARISTOTLE S ACCOUNT OF AKRASIA. Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi University College London Mphil Stud

ARISTOTLE S ACCOUNT OF AKRASIA. Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi University College London Mphil Stud ARISTOTLE S ACCOUNT OF AKRASIA Elena Cagnoli Fiecconi University College London Mphil Stud I hereby declare that the work presented in this thesis is my own and the work of other persons is appropriately

More information

Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being

Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being Aristotle: Movement and the Structure of Being Author: Mark Sentesy Persistent link: http://hdl.handle.net/2345/2926 This work is posted on escholarship@bc, Boston College University Libraries. Boston

More information

Processes as pleasures in EN vii 11-14: a new approach Joachim Aufderheide

Processes as pleasures in EN vii 11-14: a new approach Joachim Aufderheide Processes as pleasures in EN vii 11-14: a new approach Joachim Aufderheide 1 Introduction Philosophers and scholars interested in Aristotle s thoughts about pleasure usually leave aside EN vii 11-14 and

More information

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts) Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle Translated by W. D. Ross Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts) 1. Virtue, then, being of two kinds, intellectual and moral, intellectual virtue in the main owes both its birth and

More information

On Happiness Aristotle

On Happiness Aristotle On Happiness 1 On Happiness Aristotle It may be said that every individual man and all men in common aim at a certain end which determines what they choose and what they avoid. This end, to sum it up briefly,

More information

Unity and Primary Substance for Aristotle

Unity and Primary Substance for Aristotle Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association Volume 77 Issue 0 / 2003 Catherine Jack Deavel Unity and Primary Substance for Aristotle Abstract: Primary substance for Aristotle is either

More information

Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's <em>the Muses</em>

Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's <em>the Muses</em> bepress From the SelectedWorks of Ann Connolly 2006 Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's the Muses Ann Taylor, bepress Available at: https://works.bepress.com/ann_taylor/15/ Ann Taylor IAPL

More information

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy METAPHYSICS UNIVERSALS - NOMINALISM LECTURE PROFESSOR JULIE YOO Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy Primitivism Primitivist

More information

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete Bernard Linsky Philosophy Department University of Alberta and Edward N. Zalta Center for the Study of Language and Information Stanford University In Actualism

More information

Objective Interpretation and the Metaphysics of Meaning

Objective Interpretation and the Metaphysics of Meaning Objective Interpretation and the Metaphysics of Meaning Maria E. Reicher, Aachen 1. Introduction The term interpretation is used in a variety of senses. To start with, I would like to exclude some of them

More information

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic'

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic' Res Cogitans Volume 2 Issue 1 Article 22 7-30-2011 The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic' Levi Tenen Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

AP English Literature 1999 Scoring Guidelines

AP English Literature 1999 Scoring Guidelines AP English Literature 1999 Scoring Guidelines The materials included in these files are intended for non-commercial use by AP teachers for course and exam preparation; permission for any other use must

More information

Aristotle's Psychology First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version)

Aristotle's Psychology First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version) Page 1 of 11 First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version) Aristotle (384 322 BC) was born in Macedon, in what is now northern

More information

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18 Università della Svizzera italiana Faculty of Communication Sciences Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18 Philosophy. The Master in Philosophy at USI is a research master with a special focus on theoretical

More information

Practical Intuition and Deliberation in the Ethics of Aristotle. Word Count: 3,962 (With Notes, Header, and Abstract: 5,111)

Practical Intuition and Deliberation in the Ethics of Aristotle. Word Count: 3,962 (With Notes, Header, and Abstract: 5,111) Practical Intuition and Deliberation in the Ethics of Aristotle Word Count: 3,962 (With Notes, Header, and Abstract: 5,111) Abstract According to Aristotle, moral virtue is a stable disposition to decide

More information

Homonymy in Aristotle

Homonymy in Aristotle Homonymy in Aristotle Hallvard Markus Stette MA Thesis in Philosophy at IFIKK, HF Supervisor: Eyjólfur Kjalar Emilsson UNIVERSITY OF OSLO Spring 2011 i ii Acknowledgements I want to thank my supervisor

More information

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction 1/10 Berkeley on Abstraction In order to assess the account George Berkeley gives of abstraction we need to distinguish first, the types of abstraction he distinguishes, second, the ways distinct abstract

More information

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-29-1985 The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae Edward Halper University of

More information

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1) CHAPTER: 1 PLATO (428-347BC) PHILOSOPHY The Western philosophy begins with Greek period, which supposed to be from 600 B.C. 400 A.D. This period also can be classified

More information

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Commentary Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Laura M. Castelli laura.castelli@exeter.ox.ac.uk Verity Harte s book 1 proposes a reading of a series of interesting passages

More information

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments. Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring 2014 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #3 - Plato s Platonism Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

Metaphysics, 9.8, 1050a30 b4: The Identity of Soul and Energeia

Metaphysics, 9.8, 1050a30 b4: The Identity of Soul and Energeia Metaphysics, 9.8, 1050a30 b4: The Identity of Soul and Energeia David A. Shikiar I argue that 1050a30 b3 contains an argument in which a series of analogies treating the in relation are deployed to constrain

More information

The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate

The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate by Rich Cameron Department of Philosophy University of Colorado, Boulder Boulder, Colorado 80309-0232 Richard.J.Cameron@Colorado.EDU Despite evolutionary

More information

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic 1 Reply to Stalnaker Timothy Williamson In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic as Metaphysics between contingentism in modal metaphysics and the use of

More information

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a Comments on Mariska Leunissen s Aristotle s Syllogistic Model of Knowledge and the Biological Sciences: Demonstrating Natural Processes Allan Gotthelf Introduction In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere)

More information

Separation and its language in Plato

Separation and its language in Plato Filosofia Unisinos Unisinos Journal of Philosophy 18(3):184-188, sep/dec 2017 Unisinos doi: 10.4013/fsu.2017.183.09 PHILOSOPHY SOUTH Separation and its language in Plato Renato Matoso 1 ABSTRACT In this

More information

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE Jonathan Martinez Abstract: One of the best responses to the controversial revolutionary paradigm-shift theory

More information

What s Teleology Got To Do With It? A Reinterpretation of Aristotle s Generation of Animals V*

What s Teleology Got To Do With It? A Reinterpretation of Aristotle s Generation of Animals V* Phronesis 55 (2010) 325-356 brill.nl/phro What s Teleology Got To Do With It? A Reinterpretation of Aristotle s Generation of Animals V* Mariska Leunissen a and Allan Gotthelf b a) Department of Philosophy,

More information

Issue 5, Summer Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Issue 5, Summer Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society Issue 5, Summer 2018 Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society Is there any successful definition of art? Sophie Timmins (University of Nottingham) Introduction In order to define

More information

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver Truth and Tropes by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver Trope theory has been focused on the metaphysics of a theory of tropes that eliminates the need for appeal to universals or properties. This has naturally

More information

Aristotle on mind. University of Central Florida. Rachel R. Adams University of Central Florida. Open Access HIM

Aristotle on mind. University of Central Florida. Rachel R. Adams University of Central Florida. Open Access HIM University of Central Florida HIM 1990-2015 Open Access Aristotle on mind 2011 Rachel R. Adams University of Central Florida Find similar works at: http://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses1990-2015 University

More information

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato Aristotle Aristotle Lived 384-323 BC. He was a student of Plato. Was the tutor of Alexander the Great. Founded his own school: The Lyceum. He wrote treatises on physics, cosmology, biology, psychology,

More information

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception 1/6 The Anticipations of Perception The Anticipations of Perception treats the schematization of the category of quality and is the second of Kant s mathematical principles. As with the Axioms of Intuition,

More information

Lecture 13 Aristotle on Change

Lecture 13 Aristotle on Change Lecture 13 Aristotle on Change Patrick Maher Scientific Thought I Fall 2009 Introduction This lecture discusses parts of Aristotle s book Physics. The word physics come from Greek phusis, which means nature.

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Karin de Boer Angelica Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant

More information