A PARADOX OF EXPRESSION : MERLEAU-PONTY AND THE INTERTWINING NATURE OF BRECHT S NOT BUT PROCEDURE

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "A PARADOX OF EXPRESSION : MERLEAU-PONTY AND THE INTERTWINING NATURE OF BRECHT S NOT BUT PROCEDURE"

Transcription

1 PERFORMANCE PHILOSOPHY A PARADOX OF EXPRESSION : MERLEAU-PONTY AND THE INTERTWINING NATURE OF BRECHT S NOT BUT PROCEDURE COHEN AMBROSE COMMUNITY COLLEGE OF BALTIMORE COUNTY [F]or the first time, through the other body, I see that, in its coupling with the flesh of the world, the body contributes more than it receives, adding to the world that I see the treasure necessary for what the other body sees. For the first time, the body no longer couples itself up with the world, it clasps another body, applying itself to it carefully with its whole extension, forming tirelessly with its hands the strange statue which in its turn gives everything it receives; the body is lost outside of the world and its goals, fascinated by the unique occupation of floating in Being with another life, of making itself the outside of its inside and the inside of its outside. And henceforth movement, touch, vision, applying themselves to the other and to themselves, return toward their source and, in the patient and silent labor of desire, begin the paradox of expression. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, The Visible and The Invisible (1968, ) In one of his last writings before his death in 1961, Maurice Merleau-Ponty makes the case that one s flesh is the vanishing point of the distinction between subject and object, self and other, and the individual and the world. He argues that to look at oneself through the eyes of another necessarily blends the divide between one body and another and, by applying one s senses to another s, one engages in a paradox of expression, or a double-agency between both oneself and another. I borrow Merleau-Ponty s phrase as my title because it is particularly apt regarding a performance technique that German playwright, director, theorist, and co-founder of the Berliner Ensemble, Bertolt Brecht, called the procedure of fixing the not but, which produces a Verfremdungseffekt. 1 The Verfremdungseffekt creates a sense of defamiliarization in the spectator s PERFORMANCE PHILOSOPHY VOL 3, NO 1 (2017): DOI: ISSN

2 consideration of a character. I use Merleau-Ponty s paradox of expression as a way of considering Brecht s call for the co-presence of the actor and their character in a stage performance. I borrow Nick Crossley s approach to phenomenological intersubjectivity and consider the apparent theoretical implications in the performance of the not but procedure. I argue that in order for the actor to successfully perform Brecht s not but procedure in performance, the actor must play into their character while occasionally playing out of the character employing what I call a reflective block in an alternative attitude so the spectator will notice their comment on their character. In his essay A Short Description for a New Technique of Acting Which Produces an Alienation Effect, first written as a prefatory note in 1940, Brecht states that the aim of this technique was to make the spectator adopt an attitude of inquiry and criticism in his approach to the incident [t]he actor must invest what he has to show (Brecht 1964, 136). There are many techniques for creating Verfremdungseffekte in the theatre that are achieved with music, technical, staging, and design choices. I will remain focused, however, on the actor s role in creating the effect. One Berliner Ensemble member, Ekkehard Schall, asserts that although other stage devices can aid in creating Verfremdungseffekte, the best means of Verfremdung remain those which pull the contradiction out of a performance s unity (2015, 65 66). Brecht argues that the actor s intent and opinion is as important as their portrayal of the character s psychophysical experience. I argue, however, that this critical reproduction cannot exist as a seamless, simultaneous series of actions, but rather as an interconnected double helix: first performing toward a complete transformation, and then stepping out of the character s psychophysical experience and showing the character performing a contradictory act something they would not do. By picking up Brecht s line, I too have explored the process of working with actors to produce distancing effects in their acting in a 2012 performance project, The Galileo Experiment, some results of which I chronicle here. Brecht was not suggesting a completely new type or form of acting. He was arguing for a kind of doubleagency: a perception of character that leaves room for the presence of the actor whose consciousness and opinions surface, disappear, and reappear throughout the performance. Brecht wanted the actor to not only perform the role of the character, but to be dexterous enough to show the audience that he is showing them an alternative action to that action which the character actually performs in the play. To further his illustration, Brecht addresses the not but procedure. This idea was central to my query when entering the first rehearsals for The Galileo Experiment. What does it look like, I wondered, for an actor to imagine his character behaving in one attitude, but instead perform in an alternative attitude? When he appears on the stage, besides what he is actually doing he will at all essential points discover, specify, imply what he is not doing; that is to say he will act in such a way that the alternative emerges as clearly as possible, that his acting allows the other possibilities to be inferred and only represents one out of the possible variants. Whatever he doesn t do must be contained and conserved in what he does. In this way every sentence and every gesture signifies a decision; the character remains under observation and is tested. The technical term for this procedure is fixing the not but. (Brecht 1964, 137) 200

3 Performing the not but procedure is the performance process at the heart of my argument and will remain my central example of producing a Verfremdungseffekt in acting. In December 2012, I staged four scenes of Brecht s Life of Galileo in a 200-seat black-box space on the University of Montana s Missoula campus. I pared the script down to nineteen pages and eight characters. I worked with five actors, a stage manager, a costume designer, a composer, and a vocalist. A public audience of about eighty people witnessed the performance on Fig. 1. Floor plan for The Galileo Experiment. December 10, The actors performed in a twenty-foot diameter white chalk circle drawn on the black stage floor. Chairs were arranged around the circle leaving four aisles for entrances and exits (fig. 1). The pianist played at an upright piano set at the end of one aisle just outside the circle. Galileo s table sat in the center of the circle for scenes one and four. This essay seeks not only to investigate the practical applications of the not but procedure, but also to interrogate the philosophy such a process inherently performs. Although Brecht s desired outcomes of inspiring a conscious experience in the theatre, the illumination of the power structures that distort our perceptions of the world, and a generally Marxist philosophy that is deeply embedded in the text of his plays themselves are deeply relevant to my aims, in this essay, I am admittedly interested in focusing singly on the phenomenological nature of the Verfremdungseffekt, an issue with which I doubt Brecht himself was particularly concerned. Moreover, David Barnett argues, [i]f practitioners use the innovations without reference to the reasons why Brecht developed them, they will ignore the political starting point and offer performance that no longer provides insights into the workings of the world in favour of mere theatrical effects (5). While it is not my aim to divorce Brecht s political philosophy from his (or my) practice as a theatre-maker, I feel it permissible to explore other philosophical underpinnings of Brecht s practice without devoted reference to his Marxism because, as Barnett later makes it clear, Brecht s contributions do not exist in a vacuum; rather, they ongoingly present newly relevant findings within evolving contexts. Furthermore, if Brecht s political philosophy led him to develop a theatrical aesthetic that encourages spectators to pick out contradictions in society and seek new ways of reconciling them (Barnett, 4), which I agree did indeed, then an in-depth examination of the phenomenological contradictions inherent in performing the not but procedure seems like a valid and important contribution not to mere theatrical effects, but to a piece of the very political and philosophical project to which Brecht was so devoted. Finally, this essay seeks to chronicle my journey as a practitioner in quest of a deeper understanding of precisely how to capture contradiction in an actor s performance, and the reader will find that by the end of my 201

4 journey, I arrive at a discovery different from that of my hypotheses, one that I think fits nicely into both Merleau-Ponty s and Brecht s deeply holistic and context-specific philosophies. In Intersubjectivity: The Fabric of Social Becoming (1996), Nick Crossley defines two contrasting phenomenological perspectives on intersubjective relationships: egological and radical. In a reading of Edmund Husserl s Cartesian Meditations (1931), Crossley articulates that egological intersubjectivity involves an empathic intentionality which experiences otherness by way of an imaginative transposition of self into the position of the other (1996, 23). In this mode, the self intellectually distinguishes self from other and subject from object in order to assess their own position in relation to the world and others. In a reading of Merleau-Ponty s Phenomenology of Perception (1945), Crossley clearly illustrates the departure Merleau-Ponty took from Husserl s assertion that (egological) intersubjectivity is reflective, self-aware, and experiential. Crossley suggests that radical intersubjectivity, in contrast, involves a lack of self awareness and a communicative openness toward the other, which is unconditional. Self engages with other in this modality but has no experience of them as such (1996, 23). In this modality, Merleau-Ponty is not arguing for an a posteriori demonstration of the facts, but rather a simple acceptance that the world is merely available to the subject to be lived in reflectively or otherwise. This article takes the approach of two articulations of phenomenological intersubjectivity between self and other. I do not argue or imply that the actor engages in an intersubjective relationship with their character. Such an argument would be impossible because the actor and character share a physical body and the character is itself a conceptual construct of the actor s conscious mind. Both modes of intersubjective perception and relation between actor and character exist co-presently and the not but procedure is simply a moment of reflective clarity in which the actor steps beyond their character and takes stock of their present experience. The sensible and the sentient aspects of experience are neither mutually exclusive nor one and the same. Both radical and egological intersubjectivity are, in fact, reliant upon one another. In order to perform the not but procedure, the actor must break away from the radical mode in which the actor s perception of their character is pre-reflective, and consciously sense the character which shares a body with and was conceived by the actor in the egological mode. To contain and conserve what he does not do in what he does, the actor must perform in both the radical and egological modes of intersubjectivity. It is, like Merleau-Ponty s project, a holistic process that is by its very nature paradoxical. By breaking away from the radical mode in which the actor s perception of their character is eventually pre-reflective, and considering an egological mode in which the actor s perception of their character is conscious and reflective, I argue that phenomenological intersubjectivity be it the radical or egological mode is an ongoing, fluid process of uniting subject and object, actor and character. 202

5 Radical Intersubjectivity: Towards a Phenomenology of Brechtian Acting? Merleau-Ponty s phenomenology posited a pre-reflective, ongoing, interactional relationship between subject and object. In order for the actor to show an alternative, unexpected attitude of the character, the actor must first build a character and play into the character until they can perform their character in a pre-reflective manner. This kind of intuitive, instinct-driven performance of character requires actors to open themselves to all available influences in the world around them. Human subjectivity is not a private affair. In order to have a basic understanding of their ontology, individuals must engage with the world and others in order to be reflected back onto their consciousness. In the radical mode of intersubjectivity, human consciousness is simply an opening onto otherness. Crossley argues that for Merleau-Ponty, the self is 1) unaware, 2) communicates with and responds to others on the basis of their perceivable actions, and 3) that perception is pre-reflective (1996). Because the actor has a body, they are in constant sensuous, embodied engagement with the character with whom they share that body. The character is, of course, a conceptual construct of the actor s conscious mind; therefore, the character has no autonomous agency as such because whatever the character does, the actor does as well. Radical intersubjectivity, Crossley writes, can be conceptualized as an irreducible interworld of shared meanings (1996, 24). In other words, whatever phenomena are available to the individual as a sensing being are available to be engaged with. Whatever the means of engagement, the intersubjective connection is sub-conscious. Like the subject s pre-reflective experience of objects and others, the actor s perception of their character too is public and, therefore, intersubjective. The radical mode of intersubjectivity is an a priori given state that, as individuals in the world, we take for granted. In the radical mode, actors do not take conscious stock of the literal, physical images of the goings-on in the world around them. Their perception of the images skips directly to meaning and, subsequently, actions and reactions. The character s world is neither contemplated nor observed. It is participated in (Crossley 1996, 28). However, an actor must first contemplate and observe the facts and literal images in order to put the pieces back together to form the character s whole world. Only after locating the source of the meaning of the images in the character s world can the actor let go of their reflective, conscious awareness and engage in a prereflective, radically intersubjective interplay with their character. In order for the actor to also imply what he is not doing, as Brecht insists, the actor must first be able to perform the character in the radical mode. In The Galileo Experiment, we took a physical approach to building a character and finding a way into a character s psychophysical experience. Before the actor can begin to successfully develop and build their character s physical bearing, they need to become consciously aware of their own comportment. An individual s comportment is more than just their physical gait, but an outward, physicalized expression of their inner state. In other words, the word comportment is a concise label for a person s entire psychophysical process. In order to fully explore this phenomenon, I developed a rehearsal workshop titled Becoming Aware of Comportment

6 The workshop included a series of walking exercises in which actors observed one another s movements, took notes on their comportments, and held short discussions. There were many discoveries in the workshop, including one actor who noticed another actor who vigorously swung her arms tightly to her sides. The actor responded to her spectator s note by admitting that she was conscious of her weight. She articulated that perhaps her unconscious tendency was to walk quickly and swing her arms close to her sides in order to make herself appear more slender. In a journal entry about the workshop, another actor wrote, [t]he exploration of my physicality strips layers from me and shoves me into a state of vulnerability. From this state, I am able to analyze myself more freely and mostly without attaching imagined meaning to my own perceptions of my physical self (Hodgson 2012). This simple experience of looking at their own bodies and asking why they move the way they do seemed to help make room for the actor to build their character s comportment. Making the actors conscious of their own comportments and why they move the way they do was an important first step because rather than assigning imagined meaning as they would for their characters they uncovered actual possible meanings behind their own comportments. This step gave them the tools with which they would build their characters comportments. Just as the actors had deconstructed their own comportment and articulated some of the reasons why they may carry themselves the way they do, in another workshop, I asked the actors to work the same way in reverse for their characters. Based on their characters social circumstances, I challenged the actors to move around the space experimenting with making specific physical choices that seemed right for their characters. Each actor was working with a wide range of character traits and social circumstances: Galileo, a financially struggling scientist; Young Andrea Sarti, Galileo s landlady s son, a boy of about ten who Galileo schools in order to help pay his rent; Virginia, Galileo s daughter who, later in the play becomes a nun and spends her life taking care of Galileo under house arrest; Ludovico, a wealthy young man sent to study with Galileo because science is a popular conversation topic; and Federzoni, the poor, illiterate lens-grinder who assists Galileo with his experiments. All of these characters offered the actors multiple possibilities to comport their characters with a range of qualities that demonstrated their social class and circumstance. In rehearsals, we explored a number of exercises to gather ideas for the characters comportments. Throughout, the actors honed and crafted their character s comportment, including their walking gait, repeated gestures, the qualities of those gestures, and the specific ways in which they engaged with objects. After having specifically and consciously built the comportment of their character, each actor was now in dexterous control of two distinct comportments. Fig. 2. Stephen Hodgeson as Galileo 204

7 This image of two distinct beings sharing the same body harkens to a remark Brecht makes in The Messingkauf Dialogues. Brecht s Philosopher says, In future you actors can depict your characters so that one can imagine them behaving differently from the way they do. You can set about outlining your characters much as when a bolder and more experienced engineer comes along and corrects his predecessor s drawings by superimposing new lines on old ones. (2012, 53) An actor cannot completely extinguish his or her own personal comportment to make room for an entirely new psychophysical bearing. In Brecht s image, the actor/engineer makes changes sometimes vast to the original comportment, but the old lines remain, fixed upon the paper s memory like a line that cannot be completely erased. The old lines in juxtaposition with the new are another example of the actor s and the character s social circumstances and behaviors remaining exposed and interlacing throughout the performance. Even though the actor can never completely erase his or her own comportment, which is neither necessary nor ideal, the character s comportment is as fully detailed and justified as the actor s. In the radical mode of intersubjectivity, the actor/character dialectic is a phenomenologically interactional relationship that occurs prior to any cognitive distinctions between an actor and their character. The performance is pre-reflective and the actor develops their character based on physical representations of the character s potential inner states. The performance is in a constant state of pre-reflective communion between the actor and their character. Sometimes the spectator is witnessing more of the actor, sometimes more of the character, but always a combination of both. Because the character is the actor s construct and because the actor and character share the same body, Merleau-Ponty s phenomenology of the flesh functions as a useful way of thinking about the inherent mutability of the actor/character relationship. The first step in Brecht s not but procedure is a pre-reflective, interactional relationship between the actor and their character. On the one hand, the actor must perform the character in the radical, pre-reflective mode; meanwhile, on the other hand, the actor must find ways of allowing an alternative attitude to emerge. Like Brecht s drawing analogy, some of the old lines emerge more clearly than the new and some of the new lines read more clearly than the old. The two sets of lines are not simply those of one character who changes its mind back and forth. Brecht is writing about the relationship between actors onstage with their characters. He writes, [w]hen reading his part the actor s attitude should be one of a man who is astounded and contradicts The conduct of the man he is playing, as he experiences it, must be weighed up by him (1964, 137). Brecht is arguing that the actor himself must do the weighing up of the man he is playing. In his description of fixing the not but, Brecht writes, [w]hatever he doesn t do must be contained and conserved in what he does. (1964, 137). In the analogy, the old lines represent what the character does not do and the new lines represent what the character does. Thomas Baldwin makes it clear that, although it was not yet a fully developed idea in Phenomenology of Perception, Merleau-Ponty was pointing to the flesh as the point at which subject 205

8 and object are no longer distinct. In his analysis of the final, unfinished chapter of The Visible and the Invisible, The Intertwining The Chiasm, Baldwin argues that the relationship is reversible: the hand that touches can be felt as touched, and vice-versa, though never both at the same time, and it is this reversibility that [Merleau-Ponty] picks out as the essence of flesh. It shows us the ambiguous status of our bodies as both subject and object (2003, 248). The flesh of the actor s body upon which the audience fixes its gaze is in fact a kind of vanishing point the actor/character dialectic is the ambiguous status of the actor s body as both actor and character. Borrowing the image of the Greek letter x (chi), Merleau-Ponty developed a new concept of the body that he called the chiasm, the crossing-over and combination of subjective experience and objective existence. The flesh, Merleau-Ponty argues, provides access to both perspectives. He argues that our experience is both that of the touching subject and as the tangible object. The body is lost outside of the world and its goals, fascinated by the unique occupation of floating in Being with another life, of making itself the outside of its inside and the inside of its outside. And henceforth movement, touch, vision, applying themselves to the other and to themselves, return toward their source and, in the patient and silent labor of desire, begin the paradox of expression. (1968, 144) Since the actor s body is inhabited by and under the influence of two sets of social circumstances, when performing with a definite gest of showing (Brecht 1964, 136), there is necessarily a continuous conversation between what the actor is doing, what the character is not doing, what the actor is not doing, and what the character is doing. Remember the metaphor of the engineer s drawing: at certain points the old set of lines seem to emerge as the bolder of the two. To perform in two opposing attitudes back and forth, from the perspective of the character to an alternative perspective of the character, as imagined by the actor, and back again, would seem to create a paradox, not necessarily a diametrical paradox, but as Merleau-Ponty suggests, a paradox that takes as its point of departure the flesh of the same body. In this way, the actor and their character co-exist in oneness with each other and their real and imagined worlds. [F]or the first time, I appear to myself completely turned inside out before my own eyes (Merleau-Ponty 1968, 143). Although he is talking more generally about one s own body in engagement with another separate body, I am adapting Merleau-Ponty s concept of a body revealing itself to itself via the observation of another body s observation of that original body. The case of Brecht s not but procedure is similar: in one instance, the character s attitude is absent and the actor s present, whereas in another instance the opposite is the case. Another way of imagining it might be that an actor/character braid (or chiasm) is drawn before our view and as one disappears beneath, the other arises from below. For the first time, the body clasps another body, applying itself to it carefully with its whole extension, forming tirelessly with its hands the strange statue which in its turn gives everything it receives (Merleau-Ponty 1968, 144). This communion between bodies coming together to form a strange statue, I argue, is what Brecht is effectively asking of the actor in his not but procedure. He asks the actor to share a body with a character and to be able to show when the audience is to hear from the character or from himself. 206

9 The relationship that is developed by the joint actor/character Being is inherently corporeal because in order to show either side of the coin, the coin itself must be physically turned over just as the actor must physically turn himself over from the character s body and into his own or into another comportment in order to show both perspectives. Although the character cannot be released from its containment within the perceived illusion, it maintains only one half of the relationship the spectator witnesses onstage. Egological Intersubjectivity: Bracketing Out Another Perspective Rather than engaging in a pre-reflective, ongoing interactional relationship with their character as in the radical mode of intersubjectivity, the actor also has the option to rely on their imagination to theoretically put them in the shoes of their character. In this way, the actor is not inextricably bound to the character simply because they share a body. From this perspective, rather, the actor can go through the same process as described in the previous section, but maintain a poised readiness to detach themselves from their character and perform the final step in Brecht s not but procedure. In Crossley s terms, this is egological intersubjectivity. I argue that the actor can foreground the reflective aspects of the egological mode in order to discover, specify, imply what he is not doing (Brecht 1964, 137). Through imagination, Crossley writes, we are able to detach ourselves, in part, from the world of shared perceptions and thus to (partially) escape the intersubjective world (1996, 47). Although he qualifies this use of imagination as a partial detachment because it is impossible to remove oneself from the world s phenomena, Crossley is suggesting that by imagining ourselves in the shoes of another (even a fictional character), we can put ourselves in their position via a series of mental operations. Embodied simulation is conceived of as a basic functional mechanism of our brain, enabling not only a direct bodily access to the actions, emotions and sensations of others, but also the possibility to imagine similar self- and other-related contents (Gallese and Wojciehowski 2011, 14). In other words, we are not bound to the world and others just because we have a body whose senses mediate one hundred percent of our experience. There is, however, a private space an egological space, which is theoretical, not real in which the self can create and maintain an intellectual distance from the world and others. Another difference between this mode and the radical mode might be to say that in the radical mode, the self feels the other and their mutual world; while, in the egological mode, the self seeks to understand the other in order to know how to engage with them in their world. Merleau-Ponty illustrates this point by describing a number of observations regarding imitation in early childhood. He argues that when young children imitate adults, they are imitating the results of the actions or gestures the adult is performing rather than the action or gesture itself. He cites an observation where a child is able to hold a hairbrush to his head and brush his own hair, but is later unable to imitate the gesture of lifting his hand to his head without a brush (Merleau-Ponty 1979). He writes, [the child] is still unreceptive to the nonconcrete and aimless gesture (35). In the acquisition of skills, the child is performing an egological moment a transposition of themselves into the experience of the adult in order to gain an understanding of his own perceptual experience of the world. For Crossley, this phenomenon is significant for two reasons. First, it means the child is 207

10 oriented to and responds to the meaning (qua purpose) to the gesture as a whole, rather than to the empirical extension of the adult s body through space (1979, 52). The child imitates the gesture in a quest to understand why the adult performs the gesture and is therefore oriented to the meaning of the action. Second, it makes a strong case for the notion of a lived sense of corporeal equivalence between body-subjects. It suggests an innate intercorporeality (1979, 52). This intercorporeality is a useful way of thinking about the ways in which humans step back and take stock of their surroundings in order to make logical sense of the world. In the egological mode, the actor is not so much feeling the character as they are viewing and thinking about them from various perspectives in order to understand the possibilities for how and why they do what they do. The actor consciously constructs not only the mental concept of their character, but embodies their character s experience in an innate intercorporeal relationship. In the radical mode, the actor is in a deep, immersive, pre-reflective engagement with their character, but when in the egological mode, the actor is stepping away for another vantage point. From the egological perspective, we reduce the other to the consciousness that we have of them. Consciousness, therefore, is the subject of perception as opposed to basic bodily existence as it is for Merleau-Ponty. Throughout another chapter, Crossley argues that the other, in the egological modality, is experienced as 1) a psychophysical object, 2) a subject who experiences and knows us, and 3) an intersubject who sees the world as we do. Notice here that in the egological mode of intersubjectivity, the other is given the same qualities and abilities as the self, but there is not yet any talk of a recursive feedback loop between the two subjects. If I have a body that senses, you must have a body that senses. If I can see you, you must be able to see me. If I see the grass as green, you must also see green grass. This is different from the radical mode because it is a conscious acknowledgement of the other as different from the self, which, in return means that the self is an individually perceiving self. My imagination allows me to draw these conclusions because I imagine myself as you in order to know you as separate from me. By recognizing the other as distinct from myself, I therefore recognize that I too am distinct from them. This theoretical awareness of self as distinct from other comes later in the child s development than the radical mode, with which they are born (Crossley 1996, 50). From the egological aspect, the self s relationship with the other is less immediate than the radical approach. In fact the whole dichotomy of self and other is a conscious, theoretical concept. [S]elf and other are objects of our experience, Crossley writes, and the more reflective and reflexive aspects of our being more generally (49). In order to understand the other, the relationship is mediated by the self s anticipations and self-conscious performance of the attitude of the other. The self perceives the other as different and, using empathy and simulation, tries to imagine what it is like to be that person by adopting and performing in the attitude of the other. Once this initial step is experienced, the self can step back and look at the other in a new light. In other words, after thoroughly developing the character, the actor is able to experience their character as a psychophysical object: a conceptual other in need of being consciously interpreted, analyzed, and adjusted

11 Performing the not but Procedure in The Galileo Experiment In order to successfully perform the not but procedure, the actor must first choose moments in the text where their character behaves in a strange, surprising, remarkable, or contradictory manner. When designing our rehearsal process, I took clues from Brecht: Before memorizing the words [the actor] must memorize what he felt astounded at and where he felt impelled to contradict. The actor should refrain from living himself into the part prematurely in any way, and should go on functioning as long as possible as a reader. Given this absence of total transformation in the acting there are three aids which may help to alienate the actions and remarks of the characters being portrayed: 1. Transposition into the third person. 2. Transposition into the past. 3. Speaking the stage directions aloud. (1964, 137 8) By choosing specific moments to step back from the character and make their commentary visible, the actor is not under pressure to impulsively maneuver between the radical and egological modes. Rather, they have identified specific moments in the play s text that are appropriate signposts for the actor to abandon their pre-reflective immersion in their character and reflect on their character s behavior. With strangeness or contradiction in mind, I asked the actors to freeze a scene by raising a hand and narrating their character s behavior or attitude in the third-person as if in a novel. Speaking the stage directions out loud in the third person, Brecht continues, results in a clash between the two tones of voice, alienating the second of them, the text proper (1964, 138). In this exercise, the actor is automatically distanced from their character (and, subsequently, the text itself) simply by shifting into the third-person singular and past tense. The actors became narrators for their characters actions and behaviors. Without much specificity, I simply asked the actors after you speak, if you sense a remarkable or contradictory moment in the text, raise your hand, break character, and describe the quality of the character s action. For example, the actor playing Andrea raised his hand at one point following one of his own lines and said, he said patronizingly (Swibold 2012). I encouraged them to keep the scene moving as quickly as possible despite these interruptions, which helped to give the actors a sense of dexterity when it came to flexing between the radical and the egological modes. The exercise also allowed the actors to impulsively rediscover and announce their previously found moments of contradiction. These moments of strange, contradictory behavior varied. For example, actor Katie Norcross: Virginia is a mess of contradictions. It s this weird twofold relationship where she wants to both explode at her father and hug him at the same time. These feelings lead to contradictions that manifest physically. She has moments that are both docile and strong willed. One second she s being a good daughter and the next she s standing up to Galileo and challenging him. (Norcross 2012) In a sense, it became a diegetic commentary on their character s behavior not via narrative language, but via physical performance. In another particularly effective example, Hodgson found 209

12 a moment of Galileo s behavior that he had found remarkable because it happened to strike a chord with him personally. The Curator (Hugh Bickley) is trying to convince Galileo to develop something useful for the city, but Galileo wants money for his astronomical research: CURATOR: We realize you are a great man. A great, but dissatisfied man, if I may say so. GALILEO: You re right, I am dissatisfied. I m forty-six years old and I ve achieved nothing that satisfies me. CURATOR: I won t disturb you any longer. Up until this point in the play, Galileo is all arrogance and bravado. His contradictory statement is striking because it is the last thing we expect him to say to the Curator. When Hodgson spoke the line You re right, I am dissatisfied. I m forty-six years old and I ve achieved nothing that satisfies me, he dropped Galileo s comportment entirely, sat back in his chair, and with a sigh, recited the line in a distanced manner, suggesting that Hodgson himself was speaking the line as it applied to his own life. It was a moment of distanced reflection and simultaneous heartache because it was real not only for the character but also, at least in some aspect, for the actor (Video 00:28 00:45). This kind of narration from outside the physical comportment of the character gave way to the sense of the outward expression for which Brecht argues. Brecht argued, however, that the attitude of showing must be an ongoing feature of the actor s performance, not just certain moments here and there. In another rehearsal, I asked the actors to bring a personal object from their everyday life to rehearsal that had significance in the actor s life and that was small enough to fit in a pocket (a small stone, a lucky pen, a keychain). When they approached the moments in the scene that they had deemed strange, surprising, remarkable, or contradictory and in which they had previously frozen the scene to narrate I asked them to take hold of their object and imagine it as a point of connection with their own lives. When they took hold of their object, I asked them to physically release themselves from the comportment of their character and return to their own. Although they still spoke the lines, they left the comportment and world of their character for a brief moment and showed the other half. They switched from the perceived to the perceiver in order to offer the audience a glimpse into what they, the actor, thought was important about this character in this moment and to take note of it. After the moment had passed, they reentered the character s Excerpts from The Galileo Experiment: comportment and continued the scene (figs. 3 5 and Video 00:07 00:13, 00:19 00:26, and 00:28 00:45). 210

13 Fig. 3. Actor Katie Norcross in the character s comportment. Fig. 4. Norcross shifts into her own comportment. Fig. 5. Norcross shifts back into the character s comportment. Brecht used a similar process with English actor Charles Laughton who helped translate a later version of the play and first played Galileo for the American premiers in Los Angeles in August of 1947 and New York in December that same year. Both avid cigar smokers, Brecht writes about Laughton s work in his 1948 manifesto A Short Organum for the Theatre : [w]e find a gesture that expresses one-half of his attitude that of showing if we make him smoke a cigar and then imagine him laying it down now and again in order to show us some further characteristic attitude of the figure in the play (Brecht 1964, 194). Galileo does not smoke, but Laughton does. The actor holds the object while showing a different, unexpected perspective, and lies it down in order to perform the character s expected behaviors and attitudes. The essence of the personal object (Laughton s cigar or an actor s keychain) has the power to become a critical and emotional link between actor and character. Perhaps the moment of contact between the hand and the object is the phenomenological fulcrum that mediates the shift between the comportments of actor and character. Perhaps the object, in its interaction with the flesh, which the actor and character share, is the fulcrum between the radical and egological modes. These moments of stepping out of character, however, were not effective as performance choices because they were not obvious enough for a spectator to notice; whereas the moments of stifled decisions carried an energy of something not being said/done that a spectator could feel. Perhaps stepping out of the character s comportment and using personal objects to aid in the psychology of doing so are only useful as rehearsal exercises. In any case, the actors became agile enough to navigate the transitions from within their character, into themselves or a different, unexpected attitude, and back again. This experience gets at the heart of my argument that the actor can successfully perform Brecht s not but procedure by performing in both the radical and egological intersubjective modes. 211

14 Brecht s not but and Crossley s reflective block Brecht s not but procedure is akin to the process of what Crossley calls the reflective block, where all pre-reflective experiences of another are suddenly brought to the forefront of reflective consciousness. Crossley describes the swing between the two modes: Sometimes we are deeply engrossed with others, too engaged to be aware of either ourselves or of them. At other times, and rapidly, we can become sharply aware of both, constituting them as reflective and reflexive aspects of experience. All spontaneous actions can be stultified by a reflective block, only to be undermined later by a genuine and spontaneous communication which collapses the reflective barrier of self and other. (1996, 71, emphasis mine) In terms of performance, the reflective block is the moment in which an actor suddenly and intentionally becomes aware of their work on the character. At points, actors should allow themselves to be in deep, pre-reflective engagement in their character s experience and given circumstances. However, when considering the not but, this removal of the illusion of the actor as character is the moment when the actor becomes sharply aware of both the radical mode of immersion in the character and the egological mode of taking a reflective step away from the character. In effect, the reflective block that stultifies the actor s fluid, spontaneous co-existence with their character is the alternative attitude for which Brecht calls when performing the not but procedure. This swinging back and forth between radical and egological intersubjectivity that Crossley describes perhaps reads as an exaggeration of what really happens. Merleau-Ponty makes this argument in The Intertwining The Chiasm, as do contemporary cognitive scientists and philosophers (see Edleman 2005). The stark shifts between the actor s and their character s comportments that the actors in The Galileo Experiment made were perhaps also an exaggeration of what Brecht was calling for in his description of the not but procedure. It should be added that the egological attitude always necessarily entails the radical attitude as an underlying function (Crossley 1996, 71). The radical, pre-reflective mode of experiencing the world and others is a given. It is an a priori state of being. The egological mode pops up every once in a while and our metacognitive faculties suddenly come to life and make us reflect on our ontology. The actor once able to perform their character with deep, pre-reflective engagement is then able to determine when the reflective mode is going to emerge and generate an alternative attitude to their character s perspective. The actor cannot completely leave the character s bodily experience, as I had assumed in our rehearsal process, and still be performing the possibility of an alternative to their character s actions. Whenever we are reflectively aware of the other we are still, always, necessarily responsive to their moves at an unreflective level. We are always affected by what they do and say, by their movements and gestures (Crossley 1996, 71). The actor has to remain in some kind of touch with their character in order to perform an alternative action or possibility. Neither the reflective block nor the not but procedure are a complete stepping out of character to make 212

15 commentary on behalf of the actor. Rather, the actor must consciously choose to do something the spectator would not expect the character to do. The actor s choice to show their process of showing their character performing in an unexpected manner is the reflective block. When the actor chooses to allow their character to perform in a manner more consistent with the spectator s expectations of the character, the block is undermined, reestablishing the radical mode. Conclusion: The Sensible-Sentient and the not but Procedure I created The Galileo Experiment because I wanted to know what kind of toolkit the Brechtian actor needs in order to perform the not but procedure. I had assumed that the actor would need to create a definitive split between themselves and their character in order to show the spectator their social criticisms of the character while performing onstage. I found that not only was Brecht asking for something much more complex and dynamic, but that the actors in The Galileo Experiment discovered various ways of pointing to their characters behavior while performing them onstage. I began this research wondering how the actor performs in one attitude while simultaneously performing with the potential for an alternative attitude to emerge. My theoretical investigation constructed a fairly traditional dialectical framework of two seemingly opposing modes of phenomenological intersubjectivity radical and egological as defined by Crossley. However, I admit that, to some extent, Crossley s categories try too hard to simplify Merleau- Ponty s inherently holistic project. I want to conclude, therefore, with a return to Merleau-Ponty and offer a more holistic, interactional, and dynamic transference of reflective awareness and prereflective engagement. I conclude that performing Brecht s not but procedure is not a stark switching back and forth between radical and egological intersubjectivity, but a leaning to one side in order show an alternative attitude of the character. Perhaps there are more than two sides of a character s potential for contradictory or remarkable behavior. Perhaps there are many ways of fixing the not but. Merleau-Ponty conceptualizes the human body s relationship with itself and others in two primary ways. He argues that the body can, on the one hand, be a sensible object one that actively senses itself and others. On the other hand, the body can be passively sentient, or phenomenal a body that is sensed by itself and others. Remembering the example I examined earlier from Phenomenology of Perception, in The Intertwining The Chiasm, Merleau-Ponty describes the ways in which his right hand can perform the touching of another object, while his left hand simultaneously touches his right hand. In this way, he argues, the right hand is both touched and doing the touching it is a sensible-sentient, or a sensing phenomenon. However, this twofold experience, he argues in his final work, cannot share the stage so to speak; moreover, the experience of touching and being touched cannot be experienced with an equal intensity simultaneously: If these experiences never exactly overlap, if they slip away at the very moment they are about to rejoin, if there is always a shift, a spread, between them, this is precisely because my two hands are part of the same body, because it moves itself in the world, because I hear myself both from within and from without. I 213

16 experience and as often as I wish the transition and the metamorphosis of the one experience into the other. (1968, 148) If I forge this understanding of the human body s experience of itself and others into a lens through which to examine Brecht s not but procedure, I argue that the reflective block is the actor performing the transition and metamorphosis from sentient character being sensed by the spectator, to the sensible actor touching and commenting on the character. Merleau-Ponty s procedure of performing both the overlapping sensible and the sentient aspects of experience suggests that they are neither mutually exclusive nor one and the same. They are, in fact, reliant upon one another. In order to sense its own body, that same body must be sentient and in order to be sentient, that body must be sensed. In much the same way, in order to perform the not but procedure, the actor must consciously sense the character, which lest we forget shares a body with and was conceived, at least in part, by the actor. This theoretical examination of both the sensible-sentient that Merleau-Ponty describes and Brecht s not but procedure does not necessarily divide the actor into a sensing subject and the character into an objective, sentient phenomenon. The relationship is an ongoing, fluid process uniting actor and character as a sensible-sentient being that is merely highlighting contradictory aspects of its shared sets of behaviors. Brecht s not but procedure requires the actor to become well aware of the intertwining dual nature of human perception and presence. To contain and conserve what he does not do in what he does, the actor is performing in both the radical and egological modes of intersubjectivity. The reflective block produces a brief Verfremdungseffekt. It is not necessarily a complete removal from character, but a choice to twist the character around to see what is on the other side, then twisting it back again to further explore the more familiar. Egological intersubjectivity, Crossley concludes, is only a relative reflective distancing. It is never absolute (1996, 71). As in our conscious lives when we have moments of reflection or moments where we question our choices based on the perceptions of our experiences, so the actor has the agency to choose when to consciously show a character s opposite possibilities. Echoing Schall, Mumford argues that the not but, is a procedure Brecht explored in order to create each character as an unstable unity of opposites to show that humans are ever-changing entities, constantly shaped by and contributing to the flux of their physical and social environments (2009, 116). In The Galileo Experiment, we explored a handful of these techniques in order to discern what worked and what did not. Some were most effective as rehearsal tools for discovering possibilities, but the most effective performance techniques were those where the actor remained in the character s comportment, stifled the impulse to do what the character wants to do, and instead made a contradicting choice. Choosing which action to allow the character to play into in a given moment of the text, and then contradicting that action and showing their conscious choice to do something else is the phenomenological experience of performing in both the radical and egological modes of intersubjectivity. It is fixing the not but. It is the paradox of expression. 214

A 'PARADOX OF EXPRESSION': BERTOLT BRECHT'S VERFREMDUNGSEFFEKT IN PERFORMANCE

A 'PARADOX OF EXPRESSION': BERTOLT BRECHT'S VERFREMDUNGSEFFEKT IN PERFORMANCE University of Montana ScholarWorks at University of Montana Graduate Student Theses, Dissertations, & Professional Papers Graduate School 2015 A 'PARADOX OF EXPRESSION': BERTOLT BRECHT'S VERFREMDUNGSEFFEKT

More information

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017 The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017 Chapter 1: The Ecology of Magic In the first chapter of The Spell of the Sensuous David Abram sets the context of his thesis.

More information

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage. Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage. An English Summary Anne Ring Petersen Although much has been written about the origins and diversity of installation art as well as its individual

More information

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press. Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (4) 640-642, December 2006 Michael

More information

Phenomenology Glossary

Phenomenology Glossary Phenomenology Glossary Phenomenology: Phenomenology is the science of phenomena: of the way things show up, appear, or are given to a subject in their conscious experience. Phenomenology tries to describe

More information

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden Seven remarks on artistic research Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden 11 th ELIA Biennial Conference Nantes 2010 Seven remarks on artistic research Creativity is similar

More information

Title Body and the Understanding of Other Phenomenology of Language Author(s) Okui, Haruka Citation Finding Meaning, Cultures Across Bo Dialogue between Philosophy and Psy Issue Date 2011-03-31 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/143047

More information

Characterization Imaginary Body and Center. Inspired Acting. Body Psycho-physical Exercises

Characterization Imaginary Body and Center. Inspired Acting. Body Psycho-physical Exercises Characterization Imaginary Body and Center Atmosphere Composition Focal Point Objective Psychological Gesture Style Truth Ensemble Improvisation Jewelry Radiating Receiving Imagination Inspired Acting

More information

2015 Arizona Arts Standards. Theatre Standards K - High School

2015 Arizona Arts Standards. Theatre Standards K - High School 2015 Arizona Arts Standards Theatre Standards K - High School These Arizona theatre standards serve as a framework to guide the development of a well-rounded theatre curriculum that is tailored to the

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

1. What is Phenomenology?

1. What is Phenomenology? 1. What is Phenomenology? Introduction Course Outline The Phenomenology of Perception Husserl and Phenomenology Merleau-Ponty Neurophenomenology Email: ka519@york.ac.uk Web: http://www-users.york.ac.uk/~ka519

More information

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment Misc Fiction 1. is the prevailing atmosphere or emotional aura of a work. Setting, tone, and events can affect the mood. In this usage, mood is similar to tone and atmosphere. 2. is the choice and use

More information

c. MP claims that this is one s primary knowledge of the world and as it is not conscious as is evident in the case of the phantom limb patient

c. MP claims that this is one s primary knowledge of the world and as it is not conscious as is evident in the case of the phantom limb patient Dualism 1. Intro 2. The dualism between physiological and psychological a. The physiological explanations of the phantom limb do not work accounts for it as the suppression of the stimuli that should cause

More information

A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY. James Bartell

A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY. James Bartell A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY James Bartell I. The Purpose of Literary Analysis Literary analysis serves two purposes: (1) It is a means whereby a reader clarifies his own responses

More information

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet,

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet, Tom Wendt Copywrite 2011 Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet, especially on Hamlet s relationship to the women

More information

2 Unified Reality Theory

2 Unified Reality Theory INTRODUCTION In 1859, Charles Darwin published a book titled On the Origin of Species. In that book, Darwin proposed a theory of natural selection or survival of the fittest to explain how organisms evolve

More information

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes 15-Craig-45179.qxd 3/9/2007 3:39 PM Page 217 UNIT V INTRODUCTION THE PHENOMENOLOGICAL TRADITION The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes communication as dialogue or the experience of otherness. Although

More information

Embodied music cognition and mediation technology

Embodied music cognition and mediation technology Embodied music cognition and mediation technology Briefly, what it is all about: Embodied music cognition = Experiencing music in relation to our bodies, specifically in relation to body movements, both

More information

Audience/Performer Chemistry

Audience/Performer Chemistry Audience/Performer Chemistry Theatre is: LIVE In person Taking place in the presence of the spectator A does B for C at D OUR PRESENCE It doesn t just mean that we are in the personal presence of performers.

More information

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education Marilyn Zurmuehlen Working Papers in Art Education ISSN: 2326-7070 (Print) ISSN: 2326-7062 (Online) Volume 2 Issue 1 (1983) pps. 56-60 Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

More information

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK 2.1 Poetry Poetry is an adapted word from Greek which its literal meaning is making. The art made up of poems, texts with charged, compressed language (Drury, 2006, p. 216).

More information

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

Existential Cause & Individual Experience Existential Cause & Individual Experience 226 Article Steven E. Kaufman * ABSTRACT The idea that what we experience as physical-material reality is what's actually there is the flat Earth idea of our time.

More information

Chapter. Arts Education

Chapter. Arts Education Chapter 8 205 206 Chapter 8 These subjects enable students to express their own reality and vision of the world and they help them to communicate their inner images through the creation and interpretation

More information

Musical Immersion What does it amount to?

Musical Immersion What does it amount to? Musical Immersion What does it amount to? Nikolaj Lund Simon Høffding The problem and the project There are many examples of literature to do with a phenomenology of music. There is no literature to do

More information

1 Amanda Harvey THEA251 Ben Lambert October 2, 2014

1 Amanda Harvey THEA251 Ben Lambert October 2, 2014 1 Konstantin Stanislavki is perhaps the most influential acting teacher who ever lived. With a career spanning over half a century, Stanislavski taught, worked with, and influenced many of the great actors

More information

Literary and non literary aspects

Literary and non literary aspects THE PLAYWRIGHT The playwright -most central and most peripheral figure in the theatrical event -provides point of origin for production (the script) -in earlier periods playwrights acted as directors -today

More information

Week 25 Deconstruction

Week 25 Deconstruction Theoretical & Critical Perspectives Week 25 Key Questions What is deconstruction? Where does it come from? How does deconstruction conceptualise language? How does deconstruction see literature and history?

More information

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism THE THINGMOUNT WORKING PAPER SERIES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF CONSERVATION ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism by Veikko RANTALLA TWP 99-04 ISSN: 1362-7066 (Print) ISSN:

More information

Crystal-image: real-time imagery in live performance as the forking of time

Crystal-image: real-time imagery in live performance as the forking of time 1 Crystal-image: real-time imagery in live performance as the forking of time Meyerhold and Piscator were among the first aware of the aesthetic potential of incorporating moving images in live theatre

More information

1/10. The A-Deduction

1/10. The A-Deduction 1/10 The A-Deduction Kant s transcendental deduction of the pure concepts of understanding exists in two different versions and this week we are going to be looking at the first edition version. After

More information

Article On the Nature of & Relation between Formless God & Form: Part 2: The Identification of the Formless God with Lesser Form

Article On the Nature of & Relation between Formless God & Form: Part 2: The Identification of the Formless God with Lesser Form 392 Article On the Nature of & Relation between Formless God & Form: Part 2: The Identification of the Formless God Steven E. Kaufman * ABSTRACT What is described in the second part of this work is what

More information

A Condensed View esthetic Attributes in rts for Change Aesthetics Perspectives Companions

A Condensed View esthetic Attributes in rts for Change Aesthetics Perspectives Companions A Condensed View esthetic Attributes in rts for Change The full Aesthetics Perspectives framework includes an Introduction that explores rationale and context and the terms aesthetics and Arts for Change;

More information

PROFESSION WITHOUT DISCIPLINE WOULD BE BLIND

PROFESSION WITHOUT DISCIPLINE WOULD BE BLIND PROFESSION WITHOUT DISCIPLINE WOULD BE BLIND The thesis of this paper is that even though there is a clear and important interdependency between the profession and the discipline of architecture it is

More information

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER Theories of habituation reflect their diversity through the myriad disciplines from which they emerge. They entail several issues of trans-disciplinary

More information

1/9. The B-Deduction

1/9. The B-Deduction 1/9 The B-Deduction The transcendental deduction is one of the sections of the Critique that is considerably altered between the two editions of the work. In a work published between the two editions of

More information

Louis Althusser, What is Practice?

Louis Althusser, What is Practice? Louis Althusser, What is Practice? The word practice... indicates an active relationship with the real. Thus one says of a tool that it is very practical when it is particularly well adapted to a determinate

More information

PARAGRAPHS ON DECEPTUAL ART by Joe Scanlan

PARAGRAPHS ON DECEPTUAL ART by Joe Scanlan PARAGRAPHS ON DECEPTUAL ART by Joe Scanlan The editor has written me that she is in favor of avoiding the notion that the artist is a kind of public servant who has to be mystified by the earnest critic.

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982), Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982), 12 15. When one thinks about the kinds of learning that can go on in museums, two characteristics unique

More information

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Mind, Thinking and Creativity Mind, Thinking and Creativity Panel Intervention #1: Analogy, Metaphor & Symbol Panel Intervention #2: Way of Knowing Intervention #1 Analogies and metaphors are to be understood in the context of reflexio

More information

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis Keisuke Noda Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy Unification Theological Seminary New York, USA Abstract This essay gives a preparatory

More information

Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts

Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1844/epm/1st.htm We shall start out from a present-day economic fact. The worker becomes poorer the

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology BOOK REVIEWS META: RESEARCH IN HERMENEUTICS, PHENOMENOLOGY, AND PRACTICAL PHILOSOPHY VOL. V, NO. 1 /JUNE 2013: 233-238, ISSN 2067-3655, www.metajournal.org Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic

More information

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture Hans Jakob Roth Nomos 2012 223 pages [@] Rating 8 Applicability 9 Innovation 87 Style Focus Leadership & Management Strategy Sales & Marketing Finance

More information

The Existential Act- Interview with Juhani Pallasmaa

The Existential Act- Interview with Juhani Pallasmaa Volume 7 Absence Article 11 1-1-2016 The Existential Act- Interview with Juhani Pallasmaa Datum Follow this and additional works at: http://lib.dr.iastate.edu/datum Part of the Architecture Commons Recommended

More information

Mass Communication Theory

Mass Communication Theory Mass Communication Theory 2015 spring sem Prof. Jaewon Joo 7 traditions of the communication theory Key Seven Traditions in the Field of Communication Theory 1. THE SOCIO-PSYCHOLOGICAL TRADITION: Communication

More information

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Book review of Schear, J. K. (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, Routledge, London-New York 2013, 350 pp. Corijn van Mazijk

More information

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 17 November 9 th, 2015 Jerome Robbins ballet The Concert Robinson on Emotion in Music Ø How is it that a pattern of tones & rhythms which is nothing like a person can

More information

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy, Adam Robbert Philosophical Inquiry as Spiritual Exercise: Ancient and Modern Perspectives California Institute of Integral Studies San Francisco, CA Thursday, April 19, 2018 Pierre Hadot on Philosophy

More information

Interpreting Museums as Cultural Metaphors

Interpreting Museums as Cultural Metaphors Marilyn Zurmuehlen Working Papers in Art Education ISSN: 2326-7070 (Print) ISSN: 2326-7062 (Online) Volume 10 Issue 1 (1991) pps. 2-7 Interpreting Museums as Cultural Metaphors Michael Sikes Copyright

More information

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment First Moment: The Judgement of Taste is Disinterested. The Aesthetic Aspect Kant begins the first moment 1 of the Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment with the claim that

More information

vision and/or playwright's intent. relevant to the school climate and explore using body movements, sounds, and imagination.

vision and/or playwright's intent. relevant to the school climate and explore using body movements, sounds, and imagination. Critical Thinking and Reflection TH.K.C.1.1 TH.1.C.1.1 TH.2.C.1.1 TH.3.C.1.1 TH.4.C.1.1 TH.5.C.1.1 TH.68.C.1.1 TH.912.C.1.1 TH.912.C.1.7 Create a story about an Create a story and act it out, Describe

More information

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki 1 The Polish Peasant in Europe and America W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki Now there are two fundamental practical problems which have constituted the center of attention of reflective social practice

More information

Cole Olson Drama Truth in Comedy. Cole Olson

Cole Olson Drama Truth in Comedy. Cole Olson Truth in Comedy Cole Olson Grade 12 Dramatic Arts Comedy: Acting, Movement, Speech and History March 4-13 Holy Trinity Academy 1 Table of Contents Item Description Rationale Page A statement that demonstrates

More information

CRISTINA VEZZARO Being Creative in Literary Translation: A Practical Experience

CRISTINA VEZZARO Being Creative in Literary Translation: A Practical Experience CRISTINA VEZZARO : A Practical Experience This contribution focuses on the implications of creative processes with respect to translation. Translation offers, indeed, a great ambiguity as far as creativity

More information

Unified Reality Theory in a Nutshell

Unified Reality Theory in a Nutshell Unified Reality Theory in a Nutshell 200 Article Steven E. Kaufman * ABSTRACT Unified Reality Theory describes how all reality evolves from an absolute existence. It also demonstrates that this absolute

More information

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason THE A PRIORI GROUNDS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE THAT a concept, although itself neither contained in the concept of possible experience nor consisting of elements

More information

PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG

PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG Dr. Kym Maclaren Department of Philosophy 418 Jorgenson Hall 416.979.5000 ext. 2700 647.270.4959

More information

CONTENTS. part 1: premises and inspirations. Acknowledgments

CONTENTS. part 1: premises and inspirations. Acknowledgments University of Michigan Press, 2012 CONTENTS Acknowledgments xiii Introduction: Human Behavior Is the Core Business of Theater 1 The Measures Taken 2 Theory and Practice 3 How We Solved Our Problems 4 Two

More information

ON GESTURAL MEANING IN ACTS OF EXPRESSION

ON GESTURAL MEANING IN ACTS OF EXPRESSION ON GESTURAL MEANING IN ACTS OF EXPRESSION Sunnie D. Kidd In this presentation the focus is on what Maurice Merleau-Ponty calls the gestural meaning of the word in language and speech as it is an expression

More information

Plan. 0 Introduction and why philosophy? 0 An old paradigm of personhood in dementia 0 A new paradigm 0 Consequences

Plan. 0 Introduction and why philosophy? 0 An old paradigm of personhood in dementia 0 A new paradigm 0 Consequences Plan 0 Introduction and why philosophy? 0 An old paradigm of personhood in dementia 0 A new paradigm 0 Consequences Why philosophy? 0 Plumbing and philosophy are both activities that arise because elaborate

More information

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95. 441 Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95. Natika Newton in Foundations of Understanding has given us a powerful, insightful and intriguing account of the

More information

I Hearkening to Silence

I Hearkening to Silence I Hearkening to Silence Merleau-Ponty beyond Postmodernism In short, we must consider speech before it is spoken, the background of silence which does not cease to surround it and without which it would

More information

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture Roger Williams University DOCS@RWU School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation Faculty Publications School of Architecture, Art, and Historic Preservation 2010 John S. Hendrix Roger Williams

More information

A Brief Guide to Writing SOCIAL THEORY

A Brief Guide to Writing SOCIAL THEORY Writing Workshop WRITING WORKSHOP BRIEF GUIDE SERIES A Brief Guide to Writing SOCIAL THEORY Introduction Critical theory is a method of analysis that spans over many academic disciplines. Here at Wesleyan,

More information

Theatre Standards Grades P-12

Theatre Standards Grades P-12 Theatre Standards Grades P-12 Artistic Process THEATRE Anchor Standard 1 Creating Generate and conceptualize artistic ideas and work. s Theatre artists rely on intuition, curiosity, and critical inquiry.

More information

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960]. Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp. 266-307 [1960]. 266 : [W]e can inquire into the consequences for the hermeneutics

More information

Categories and Schemata

Categories and Schemata Res Cogitans Volume 1 Issue 1 Article 10 7-26-2010 Categories and Schemata Anthony Schlimgen Creighton University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Part of the

More information

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3 Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3 1 This Week Goals: (a) To consider, and reject, the Sense-Datum Theorist s attempt to save Common-Sense Realism by making themselves Indirect Realists. (b) To undermine

More information

Year 10 revision Practitioners and devising

Year 10 revision Practitioners and devising Year 10 revision Practitioners and devising Stanislavsky Constantin Stanislavski was a Russian stage actor and director who developed the naturalistic performance technique. His technique included; Magic

More information

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995. The Nature of Time Humberto R. Maturana November 27, 1995. I do not wish to deal with all the domains in which the word time enters as if it were referring to an obvious aspect of the world or worlds that

More information

H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 1

H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 1 H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 1 H-France Review Vol. 15 (October 2015), No. 136 Stephen A. Noble, Silence et langage: Genèse de la phénomenologie de Merleau-Ponty au seuil de l ontologie. Leiden

More information

5th TH.1.CR Identify physical qualities that might reveal a character s inner traits in the imagined world of a drama/theatre

5th TH.1.CR Identify physical qualities that might reveal a character s inner traits in the imagined world of a drama/theatre Envision/Conceptualize THEATRE - Creating 1 Anchor Standard 1: Generate and conceptualize artistic ideas and Enduring Understanding(s): artists rely on intuition, curiosity, and critical inquiry. Essential

More information

MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS. 1. Prewriting Introductions 4. 3.

MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS. 1. Prewriting Introductions 4. 3. MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS 1. Prewriting 2 2. Introductions 4 3. Body Paragraphs 7 4. Conclusion 10 5. Terms and Style Guide 12 1 1. Prewriting Reading and

More information

A Process of the Fusion of Horizons in the Text Interpretation

A Process of the Fusion of Horizons in the Text Interpretation A Process of the Fusion of Horizons in the Text Interpretation Kazuya SASAKI Rikkyo University There is a philosophy, which takes a circle between the whole and the partial meaning as the necessary condition

More information

Joona Taipale, Phenomenology and Embodiment: Husserl and the Constitution of Subjectivity

Joona Taipale, Phenomenology and Embodiment: Husserl and the Constitution of Subjectivity Husserl Stud (2015) 31:183 188 DOI 10.1007/s10743-015-9166-4 Joona Taipale, Phenomenology and Embodiment: Husserl and the Constitution of Subjectivity Northwestern University Press, Evanston, 2014, 243

More information

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2) 1/9 Descartes on Simple Ideas (2) Last time we began looking at Descartes Rules for the Direction of the Mind and found in the first set of rules a description of a key contrast between intuition and deduction.

More information

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Incommensurability and Partial Reference Incommensurability and Partial Reference Daniel P. Flavin Hope College ABSTRACT The idea within the causal theory of reference that names hold (largely) the same reference over time seems to be invalid

More information

Systemic and meta-systemic laws

Systemic and meta-systemic laws ACM Interactions Volume XX.3 May + June 2013 On Modeling Forum Systemic and meta-systemic laws Ximena Dávila Yánez Matriztica de Santiago ximena@matriztica.org Humberto Maturana Romesín Matriztica de Santiago

More information

CHAPTER SEVEN CONCLUSION

CHAPTER SEVEN CONCLUSION CHAPTER SEVEN CONCLUSION Chapter Seven: Conclusion 273 7.0. Preliminaries This study explores the relation between Modernism and Postmodernism as well as between literature and theory by examining the

More information

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC This part of the book deals with the conditions under which judgments can express truths about objects. Here Kant tries to explain how thought about objects given in space and

More information

Title The Body and the Understa Phenomenology of Language in the Wo Author(s) Okui, Haruka Citation 臨床教育人間学 = Record of Clinical-Philos (2012), 11: 75-81 Issue Date 2012-06-25 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/197108

More information

Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008

Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008 Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008 Writing and Memory Jens Brockmeier 1. That writing is one of the most sophisticated forms and practices of human memory is not a new

More information

DARKNESS IN THE THEATRE: THE PERCEPTION OF THE EMBODIED SELF IN ACTION

DARKNESS IN THE THEATRE: THE PERCEPTION OF THE EMBODIED SELF IN ACTION DARKNESS IN THE THEATRE: THE PERCEPTION OF THE EMBODIED SELF IN ACTION David M. Mills The Performance Center, Seattle, Washington, USA Drawing on the phenomenology of Merleau-Ponty, especially his concept

More information

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB In his In librum Boethii de Trinitate, q. 5, a. 3 [see The Division and Methods of the Sciences: Questions V and VI of

More information

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice. Review article Semiotics of space: Peirce and Lefebvre* PENTTI MÄÄTTÄNEN Abstract Henri Lefebvre discusses the problem of a spatial code for reading, interpreting, and producing the space we live in. He

More information

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics REVIEW A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics Kristin Gjesdal: Gadamer and the Legacy of German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. xvii + 235 pp. ISBN 978-0-521-50964-0

More information

K Use kinesthetic awareness, proper use of space and the ability to move safely. use of space (2, 5)

K Use kinesthetic awareness, proper use of space and the ability to move safely. use of space (2, 5) DANCE CREATIVE EXPRESSION Standard: Students develop creative expression through the application of knowledge, ideas, communication skills, organizational abilities, and imagination. Use kinesthetic awareness,

More information

THE APPLICATION OF PHENOMENOLOGICAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE REALM OF ARCHITECTURAL DESIGN ARC6989 REFLECTIONS ON ARCHITECTURAL DESIGN

THE APPLICATION OF PHENOMENOLOGICAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE REALM OF ARCHITECTURAL DESIGN ARC6989 REFLECTIONS ON ARCHITECTURAL DESIGN THE APPLICATION OF PHENOMENOLOGICAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE REALM OF ARCHITECTURAL DESIGN ARC6989 REFLECTIONS ON ARCHITECTURAL DESIGN BY RISHA NA 110204213 [MAAD 2011-2012] APRIL 2012 CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION

More information

PETER - PAUL VERBEEK. Beyond the Human Eye Technological Mediation and Posthuman Visions

PETER - PAUL VERBEEK. Beyond the Human Eye Technological Mediation and Posthuman Visions PETER - PAUL VERBEEK Beyond the Human Eye Technological Mediation and Posthuman Visions In myriad ways, human vision is mediated by technological devices. Televisions, camera s, computer screens, spectacles,

More information

What have we done with the bodies? Bodyliness in drama education research

What have we done with the bodies? Bodyliness in drama education research 1 What have we done with the bodies? Bodyliness in drama education research (in Research in Drama Education: The Journal of Applied Theatre and Performance, 20/3, pp. 312-315, November 2015) How the body

More information

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING Language shapes the way we think, and determines what we can think about. BENJAMIN LEE WHORF, American Linguist A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING TERMS & CONCEPTS The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the

More information

Ideological and Political Education Under the Perspective of Receptive Aesthetics Jie Zhang, Weifang Zhong

Ideological and Political Education Under the Perspective of Receptive Aesthetics Jie Zhang, Weifang Zhong International Conference on Education Technology and Social Science (ICETSS 2014) Ideological and Political Education Under the Perspective of Receptive Aesthetics Jie Zhang, Weifang Zhong School of Marxism,

More information

coach The students or teacher can give advice, instruct or model ways of responding while the activity takes place. Sometimes called side coaching.

coach The students or teacher can give advice, instruct or model ways of responding while the activity takes place. Sometimes called side coaching. Drama Glossary atmosphere In television, much of the atmosphere of the programme is created in post-production through editing and the inclusion of music. In theatre, the actor hears and sees all the elements

More information

MURDOCH RESEARCH REPOSITORY.

MURDOCH RESEARCH REPOSITORY. MURDOCH RESEARCH REPOSITORY http://researchrepository.murdoch.edu.au This is the author's final version of the work, as accepted for publication following peer review but without the publisher's layout

More information

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding. Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding. Jessica Leech Abstract One striking contrast that Kant draws between the kind of cognitive capacities that

More information

Introduction to The music of John Cage

Introduction to The music of John Cage Introduction to The music of John Cage James Pritchett Copyright 1993 by James Pritchett. All rights reserved. John Cage was a composer; this is the premise from which everything in this book follows.

More information

Objects and Things: Notes on Meta- pseudo- code (Lecture at SMU, Dec, 2012)

Objects and Things: Notes on Meta- pseudo- code (Lecture at SMU, Dec, 2012) Objects and Things: Notes on Meta- pseudo- code (Lecture at SMU, Dec, 2012) The purpose of this talk is simple- - to try to involve you in some of the thoughts and experiences that have been active in

More information

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS The problem of universals may be safely called one of the perennial problems of Western philosophy. As it is widely known, it was also a major theme in medieval

More information