The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate"

Transcription

1 The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate by Rich Cameron Department of Philosophy University of Colorado, Boulder Boulder, Colorado

2 Despite evolutionary biology's success explaining the genesis and constitution of living things, neither biology nor contemporary philosophy of biology has provided an adequate account of being animate. Quotation one on the handout adequately represents the contemporary state of the art concerning the nature of life: there is no agreed upon definition, and there is disagreement even over whether we ought to be seeking a definition. The reason usually given for thinking that life cannot be defined, that living things are materially continuous with nonliving things, need not keep us from offering a substantive definition of life. Just as we can define being bald despite the fact that this state is materially continuous with being hairy, life's material continuity with nonlife poses no insuperable barrier to an adequate definition of life. Further, there is substantive reason to be dissatisfied with contemporary naturalistic accounts of the life's nature. Representative here is Paul Churchland's definition (quotation two on the handout). x is alive = df x is a "semiclosed physical system that exploits the order it already possesses and the energy flux through it, in such a way as to maintain and/ or increase its internal order." 1 Churchland notes that on this definition, beehives, termite colonies, cities, the biosphere and candle flames are all living things. Despite these 1 Churchland (1988, 173). 1

3 counterintuitive consequences, however, Churchland endorses the definition as an adequate theoretical definition of life. 2 Problematically, however, the only reasons Churchland (or anyone else) gives for rejecting the more ambitious task of seeking a definition that is consistent with both our scientifically informed intuitions about life and contemporary evolutionary biology are (a) the continuity of life with nonlife and (b) history of failure at the more ambitious project. Neither of these is decisive, however; the first has already been dealt with, and the second may mean nothing more than that we need to keep looking. My goal in this paper is to provide an adequate, fully naturalistic account of the nature of life, an account that is consistent with both evolutionary biology and our scientifically informed intuitions concerning what it is to be alive. Perhaps surprisingly, the account I endorse is (for the most part) Aristotle's. This paper will, therefore, be devoted mainly to an exegesis of Aristotle's account of the nature of life. Defense of the account that results, and, in particular, defense of the claim that it meets the criteria of adequacy listed on the handout, will be deferred to the question period. 1 Locating Aristotle's account in the de Anima After his typical review of previous views on the soul in book i of the de Anima, Aristotle begins a 'fresh start' in book ii, moving quickly to provide a 2 Those who engage in the project of giving 'theoretical' definitions generally distinguish their task from that of 'conceptual analysis.' Conceptual analysis, on this view, seeks to capture the content of our concepts; theoretical definition seeks to reflect how things are in the world. There is no necessary tension between these two projects however; our concepts may (we hope) 2

4 number of definitions of the soul, each of which employs core concepts from his developed metaphysics. The soul must be a substance in the sense of the form of a natural body having life potentially within it. But substance is actuality, and thus soul is the actuality of a body as above characterized (DA ii.1 412a20; see also 412a27, 412b3, 412b10; ii.2 414a28; PA i.1 641a25-9; GA ii.4 738b27; Met. vii b14-31, vii a5, viii a35) Aristotle believes that he has given a satisfactory general definition, but moves on in de Anima ii.2 to investigate the matter from the point of view of what is more observable to us in order to make clear the cause of his definition (DA ii.2 413a11-20). From this point of view, it turns out that the soul is the starting point of (archê) and is defined by (horistai) powers that the soul has (DA ii.2 413b11-13). These powers are specified with reference to the fact that the soul is the cause of life. We resume our inquiry from a fresh starting-point by calling attention to the fact that what has soul in it differs from what has not in that the former displays life. Now this word has more than one sense, and provided any one alone of these is found in a thing we say that thing is living viz. thinking or perception or local movement and rest, or movement in the sense of nutrition, decay and growth. (DA ii.2 413a21-5) One might suppose that Aristotle here offers a "cluster" definition 3 of life such that: adequately reflect the state of things. For different naturalistic takes on this distinction, see Millikan (1989) and Neander (1991). 3 "Cluster" definitions of life are quite common in the contemporary literature. Mary Ann Warren (1997) expresses the idea behind such definitions well: "It should not surprise us that there is no single (or multiple) necessary and sufficient condition for the proper application of the ordinary concept of life... Basic practical concepts, such as that of life, develop through many generations of experience. Consequently, such concepts often lack the clarity and simplicity that are desirable in, for instance, mathematical or scientific theories... the complexity and the unclear boundaries of many of our ordinary concepts cannot readily be defined away, except that the cost of substituting a different concept for the original one" (26). Further, "I think it best to stay with a definition similar to Webster's, i.e. one that lists 3

5 x is alive = df x has at least one of the following powers: (a) thinking; (b) perception; (c) local movement and rest; (d) the movement of nutrition, growth, and decay. One problem 4 with attributing such a definition to Aristotle is that Aristotle does not typically offer disjunctive lists as definitions; his standard form of definition involves specification of genus and differentia. Further, such a definition would inherit the main problem associated faced by any cluster definition, the problem of the unity of the definition: Why are these powers on the list and others not? What do these abilities have in common that makes them, individually or in groups, sufficient for life? If we can answer the question, it appears that that answer ought to be our definition of life. If we cannot answer it, it would appear that the original cluster of properties provides little more than a set of heuristically useful correlates to being alive. We might try to find unity in Aristotle's cluster of properties through the insight that Aristotle believes that the powers of the soul are arranged hierarchically. The power of nutrition, Aristotle held, can be had without sensation or thought (as in plants), but the powers of thought and sensation cannot be had (at least in biological organisms) without the power of nutrition. 5 Perhaps, then, the original list of properties jumbles together some marks of life (sensation, thought, local movement) while the definition of life is in terms characteristic features that can serve as criteria of life, but that does not attempt to resolve in advance all possible uncertainties about what ought to count as a living thing" (30). 4 In what follows I am covering ground which is already well covered by Matthews (1992) and Shields (1999); I make no claims for originality in this portion of my brief introduction to Aristotle's account of life. 5 See DA 413a32-4, 413b4-13, 414a29-415a12; PN 454a11-454a18, 474b

6 of one member of the original list: the power of nutrition. As Aristotle says, "By life we mean self-nutrition and growth and decay" (DA ii.1 412a14). 6 Such a definition would appear to solve our problems by giving unity to our original cluster: having the nutritive soul explains a thing's being alive, but sense perception thought and local movement are marks or signs of life that are in some way connected to this power. This definition appears to fail as well, however, for two reasons. The first reason is that such a definition may be circular. After all, we need to discriminate between the taking on of nutrition that living things do and that done by an ordinary household sponge (when wiping up, say, spilt milk), but it is difficult to see how to do this without simply referring to the fact that the kind of taking in nutrition we have in mind is that which living things do. Further, Aristotle himself seems to define the nutritive power in terms of the capacity to absorb food (DA ii.4 416a20-1), but he also defines food in terms of its relation to the soul (DA ii.4 416b10-13; cf. GA 335a15-6). A problematic circularity, then, haunts this type of definition. Because the proposed Aristotelian definition in terms of the nutritive soul is at risk of circularity, we may hope that Aristotle does not endorse it. We have a strong reason to believe that he doesn't, thankfully, since Aristotle is unabashed in supposing god to be alive in virtue of god's possession of nous, but Aristotle's god is nonbiological and possesses no nutritive soul (Met. xii b26-30; see also OH a8; NE b20). Our intuitions about 6 See also 413b1-2, 415a24-5; PN 479a28-9; GA 741a1. 5

7 living, like Aristotle's, seem to allow that it is possible for there to be nonbiological life, and Aristotle's account acknowledges this possibility (as an actuality). This result seems only to increase our difficulties, however. For now we need to find some unity not merely within the list of biological powers Aristotle refers to in de Anima ii.2 413a21-5, but between those powers and whatever it is in virtue of which a being like God would be alive. Aristotle's account of life, if it is to be satisfactory in its own terms must apparently be 'weak' enough to avoid the circularity problem but 'strong' or 'rich' enough to meet conditions of adequacy concerning the unity of definitions that account not only for the actual but also the possible diversity of life. The problems we have thus far surveyed for 'simple solutions' to the problem of locating Aristotle's account of life are indicative of problems contemporary accounts suffer. Problems surrounding the unity and diversity of life and problems concerning the counterintuitive consequences of proposed definitions are extremely common. From this perspective, it is unsurprising that the 'simple' answers that suggest themselves in Aristotle's texts fail as definitions of life, and it is fortunate that Aristotle appears not to endorse such views. As we might expect, we must look more deeply if we are to discover either Aristotle's account or an adequate contemporary account of life. I turn now to discuss perhaps the most widely known interpretation of Aristotle on the nature of life, that of Gareth Matthews' "de Anima and the 6

8 Meaning of Life". 7 I argue that Matthews' core insight is correct, but that his account fails as he has developed it. In the final section of the paper, I offer my positive development of the core insight. 2 Matthews on the Meaning of Life Matthews' interpretation of Aristotle on life takes its central motivation from reflection on the possibility of god's life. If the only (possible) living things were biological organisms, it might be plausible for us to give an account of life in terms of self-nutrition, the most basic and widely shared psychic function. 8 The problem created by (the possibility of) god's life is so drastic, however, that following Aristotle's methodological practice Matthews turns to "try a very different approach" (190). 9 Matthews' new beginning starts from the insight that Aristotelian organisms "naturally act so as to preserve their species" (190, citing DA a27-b2 text one on your handout). From this insight Matthews develops his account around the notion of a 'psychic' or species preserving power, a notion which is then employed in a definition of what it is to be alive. x is a psychic power =df there is a species s, such that, for x to be preserved, individual organisms that belong to s must, in general, exercise x (191). x is a psychic power for species s =df for s to be preserved individual organisms that belong to s must, in general, exercise x (191). 7 Matthews (1992). 8 Of course we would have to get over the circularity problem to make this solution work. Can we give a non-circular, informative, scientifically adequate definition of the power to take on nutrition which includes all and only living things (i.e. includes plants and animals but excludes (household) sponges)? Aristotle scholars would have the additional task of explaining away Aristotle's apparent commitment to the homonymy of life as well. 9 Unless otherwise specified, all page numbers in this section are from Matthews (1992). 7

9 x is alive =df there is a species s, and a psychic power p, such that x belongs to s, p is a psychic power for species s, and x can exercise p (191). Less formally, Matthews explains, "what it means to say that an organism is alive is that it can exercise at least one psychic power; that is, at least one of the powers that organisms of its species must, in general, be able to exercise for the species to survive" (191). Matthews believes that this account of life is Aristotle's, and that it avoids and solves a number of problems. It is claimed to avoid circularity, to solve the problem of explaining the special role nutrition plays in Aristotle's statements about life, and to make room for god's (nonbiological) life. Matthews believes that his account explains both why self-nutrition plays such a central role in Aristotle's discussions of life and explains a scholarly puzzle concerning why Aristotle claims that life is 'said in many ways' (DA ii.2 413a21, Top. vi a27). Among mortal living things the most basic species-preserving power is self-nutrition, and this accounts for its special place in Aristotle's account of life. "Still, what exactly having species-preserving, or psychic, powers amounts to varies from species to species. And in this way something like [the homonymy of life] is also true" (193). 10 Finally, Matthews believes that his account can handle (the possibility of) god's life despite the seemingly insuperable problem that his account is framed 10 I do not believe that Matthews solution to this scholarly puzzle is adequate given the richness of Aristotle's concept of homonymous definition. Elsewhere I defend a solution to this puzzle which locates a kind of homonymous definition in Aristotle similar to the determinable/determinate relation. Roughly, then, I claim that the correct solution to this problem is to view life (in Aristotle's eyes) as a determinable with different determinate ways of being alive satisfied by different orders of living things. Full exegesis and textual defense of these claims is beyond the scope of this paper, however. 8

10 in terms of the possession of species preserving powers and that Aristotle's god belongs to no species. "To preserve their species," according to Matthews, nonmortal beings such as god "need only preserve their existence by continuing to engage in whatever activity is essentially theirs" (193). Thus, Matthews offers us a gloss on his account that shows that and how it applies even in the case of a living and nonbiological god. 3 Two objections to Matthews' account In this section I offer two criticisms of Matthews' interpretation and diagnose the interpretation's failure. On my reading, Matthews' account suffers in that it is both too weak and too strong. My diagnosis of the problem is that Matthews' account goes wrong in straying from its motivating insight that living things act to preserve their species (contained in DA 415a27-b2 again text one on the handout). The solution to these problems is to respect Aristotle's intent in this passage more faithfully. To begin, recall that the central concept in Matthews' account of life is the concept of a psychic power. Here is his definition again: x is a psychic power for species s =df for s to be preserved individual organisms that belong to s must, in general, exercise x (191). The first problem for Matthews' account is that on his definition it turns out that the heart's ability to make thumping noises is a psychic power of creatures with hearts. 11 For creatures with hearts to be preserved it must in general be the case that their hearts exercise the power to make thumping noises (this is 11 See DA iii.9 432a-32b4. 9

11 true because when hearts perform their function, circulating blood, they inevitably make thumping noises). If too many hearts cease to exercise the power to make thumping noises, the species will not be preserved. But surely the heart's ability to make thumping noises is not a psychic power it is instead an accidental concomitant of a psychic power. The example I've just given is framed in modern terms 12 that foreshadow my approach to this problem's solution. It is important to note, however, that despite the modern trappings of my example, Aristotle clearly draws the same distinction in his own terms. Thus, with Aristotle we must distinguish between the definitory powers of the nutritive soul and the inevitable concomitants of those powers (such as the production of useless residues and eventual death and disintegration 13 ). The Aristotelian credentials of this distinction are safe. Thus, generalizing from this case, my first conclusion is that Matthews' account fails because it cannot distinguish psychic powers (i.e. pumping blood, the activity of the nutritive soul) from the accidental concomitants of psychic powers (i.e. producing thumping noises, producing useless residues). Another, related, failure may be illustrated with a different example. I begin by noting that in order to save his definition from circularity Matthews must intend us to understand 'organism' in the definition not to mean 'biological entity' but to mean, more generally, 'thing.' 12 I believe the example originates with Carl Hempel. 13 See PA iv.2 677a12-31, cf. GA i. 725a4-6. See also Phys. ii.2 194a30-3, OH ii.6 288b15-18, Met. vi b8-10, PN 465a14-5; PA 670a30. 10

12 x is a psychic power for species s =df for s to be preserved individual organisms [i.e. things] that belong to s must, in general, exercise x (191). Once we see this, we can see immediately that the account is far too liberal. In order for sounds to preserve themselves in echo chambers they must, in general, exercise their power to bounce off of walls. In order for radioactive isotopes to remain the isotopes they are, they must decay at a given rate (when the cease to do this, they have become a different isotope). 14 Examples, may be multiplied indefinitely, but generalizing from these cases we may note that for any continuing subject there will be some list of powers such that subjects of that kind must exercise those powers to continue in existence. Further, any such power may play the role of a 'psychic power' in Matthews' account of life. Matthews' account of life is too liberal, I conclude, since its central concept (if understood in a non-circular fashion) applies to all continuing subjects and not simply to living things. If Matthews' account isn't circular, then it is far too broad. 15 As confirmation that this problem genuinely arises for Matthews' account, note that the fault I've just illustrated explains Matthews' own extension of his account to cover god's life. The prima facie problem Matthews' account faced in god's case was that while god is alive, it is the member of no species while Matthews' account is framed in terms of species preserving powers. How does Matthews solve the problem? By extending his account along exactly the lines 14 I owe this example to Robert Pasnau. 15 It may be objected that none of the counterexamples I raise truly 'exercises' the powers I've listed. The problem with this attempted solution, however, is that it appears to reintroduce the 11

13 marked out in my second line of criticism. He takes it that god is alive just in case god exercises powers necessary for it to remain in existence. But this condition is not satisfied uniquely by god. Instead, as I argued in the previous paragraph, it will be satisfied by any continuing subject whether that subject is alive of not. I conclude that something has gone terribly wrong with Matthews' account. To summarize, the account is too weak in two ways. First, it fails to distinguish between psychic powers and the accidental concomitants of psychic powers. Second, on one interpretation it falls into the circularity problem (if 'organism' is understood to restrict the account to biological organisms). Further, the account is too strong. If we read the account such that it avoids the circularity problem (if 'organism' in the definition is understood to mean nothing more than 'thing'), then the account is far too liberal since on this reading all continuing subjects have the 'psychic powers' definitive of life. My diagnosis of these problems is that Matthews lost the thread of his motivating insight very early on. Matthews took his start from Aristotle's comment that (again, text one on the handout):... for any living thing that has reached its normal development and which is unmutilated, and whose mode of generation is not spontaneous, the most natural act is the production of another like itself, an animal producing an animal, a plant a plant, in order that [hina], as far as its nature allows, it may partake in the eternal and divine. That is the goal towards which all things strive, that for the sake of which [ekeinou heneka] they do whatsoever their nature renders possible [hosa prattei kata phusin]. (415a27-b2) problem of circularity into the account. Which things 'exercise' powers in the appropriate way, after all? Living things. I owe this objection to comments by C. Shields. 12

14 In this passage Aristotle asserts the teleological character of life. The most natural act for any living thing is its action for the sake of participation in the eternal and divine. 16 However, Matthews loses sight of this fact early on in his analysis as is clear from the fact that his analysis contains no teleological concepts or elements. Instead, teleology is analyzed out of Matthews' account in favor of necessary conditions. A sufficient condition for being alive, on Matthews' account, is the possession of a capacity to exercise one on a list of powers which are jointly necessary for kind preservation. 17 Nothing in Matthews' account specifies that the power possessed must be exercised for the sake of kind preservation. This fact explains the account's failure to distinguish psychic powers (the exercise of the nutritive soul) from accidental concomitants of psychic powers (the production of resides or death). The problem that besets Matthews' account in this regard is well known in the literature on biological teleology (i.e., the problem of distinguishing functions from the accidental concomitants of functions Hempel first raised the problem), and its solution is considered by contemporary philosophers of biology a necessary condition on the adequacy of an account of teleology. In addition, the elimination of teleological 16 It is important to note that this commitment to teleology is not as extravagant as it may sound. Aristotle makes clear elsewhere that this comes to no more than the claim that organisms have reproductive ends. See Politics i a I have switched from Matthews' loaded language of preserving species of 'organisms' to speaking more generally of 'kind preservation' to avoid problems associated with unconsciously limiting our attention in evaluating the definition to the kind we are trying to define: living things. 13

15 elements from Matthews' final account also explains why it is possible to extend the account to non-teleological entities which are plainly not alive such as sounds and radioactive isotopes. Such entities (indeed any continuing subject) will 'exercise' powers necessary for their preservation; none will do so for the sake of their preservation. 4 Aristotle on being animate I claim that we avoid the problems that afflict Matthews' account by taking the teleological aspect of de Anima ii.4 much more seriously. I argue that Aristotle defines life in terms of the possession of teleological directedness, and (further) that this definition of life satisfies the criteria of adequacy listed on the handout. Below I will briefly defend the claim that the definition provides the correct interpretation of Aristotle on being alive, leaving the question of whether the account satisfies the criteria of adequacy for discussion. In what follows, I argue first that Aristotle holds life and teleology to be coextensive. I then argue for the stronger thesis that Aristotle defines life teleologically. Finally, I conclude by noting that Aristotle explicitly draws the distinction necessary to head off the most obvious sorts of counterexamples to the original definition. Aristotle held that being teleologically directed is necessary and sufficient for being alive. That being alive is sufficient for teleological directedness is made clear in Aristotle's treatment of the movements of the heavens. In Aristotle's view, once we recognize the heavens to be living beings we must recognize that despite their uniform shape they have functional distinctions which set off their 'right' and 'left' sides (OH ii.2 285a28-31). Further, being 14

16 alive is, in the same context, treated as a necessary condition for being teleologically directed. We can understand the movements of the heavens to be goal directed only if we recognize them as being alive (OH ii a19-292b24). As additional support for the coextensiveness of life and teleology in Aristotle, note Aristotle's claims that we cannot suppose something to have nonteleological desire (orechis) (DA iii a15), 18 but that it is also impossible to conceive of anything with such an orechis not to be alive (EE i a27): orechis is teleological, and sufficient for life. 19 Further evidence comes from the fact that health and disease are coextensive with living (PN 436a18, Rhet. i a30), and these are teleological concepts (HA x.1 633b16-20, and Rhet. i b3-6 with NE ii a15-7 and EE ii a38). Further, we must understand a thing to be alive in order to understand it as having a good of its own (NE viii b30; see also GA ii.5 741a19, Phys. ii.6 197b7). These considerations yield strong positive reason to suppose that Aristotle considered life and teleology to be coextensive It is important to note that Aristotle frequently uses mentalistic sounding terms such as 'desire' to describe processes which he finds to occur in beings which have, on his view, no minds. The teleological use of 'desire' is broader than its use as a psychological notion used in explaining behavior mentalistically. 19 The references, quoted above, from DA ii.4 415a27-b2, b15-20 and MA 6 700b15-6 all constitute additional support for the claim that life is sufficient for teleological directedness. 20 The argument in the main text contains only the positive textual case for believing that Aristotle defined life teleologically; it does not directly respond to arguments to the effect that the scope of teleology is much broader. I argue elsewhere that the most promising interpretations on which Aristotle's teleological commitments extend beyond living things fail. 21 The necessity claim may be doubted given that artifacts possess ends but are not alive; I deal with this objection below. 15

17 Evidence that Aristotle endorses the stronger claim that life is defined teleologically comes from the application of a principle of kind individuation to the case of life. Aristotle commits himself to a metaphysical principle of kind individuation that we may call 22 the functional determination thesis. This view is paradigmatically stated in the following passage (text three on your handout): What a thing is is always defined by its function ((h)apanta d' estin (h)ôrismena tô(i) ergô(i)): a thing really is itself when it can perform its function. (Meteor. iv a10-11) 23 This principle would, if applicable to the case at hand, resolve the issue of whether life was defined by or merely associated with teleological commitment. We may, then, ask whether Aristotle applied this metaphysical principle to the case of living beings. It is clear that he does. As evidence, I cite Aristotle's broadly attested commitment to the claim that living beings' last state (in the normative sense, not merely in the sense that the last point in a series is an end see Met. v b24-9) is their nature, form, and end. Thus, [T]he end is developed last ((h)ustaton gar ginetai to telos), and the peculiar character of the species is the end of the generation in each individual. (GA ii.3 736b3-4. See also Phys. ii.7 198b5-9; IA 2 704b15-6, 8 708a10; Met. v b20; Phys. vii.3 246a10-15) Further, Aristotle applies this thesis to the lives of plants, animals, and men in the famous function argument in Nichomachean Ethics i.7. [I]n general, for all things that have a function (ergon ti) or activity (praxis), the good and the 'well' is thought to reside in the function, so would it seem to be for man, if he has a function.... What then can this be? Life (to zên) seems to be common even to plants, but we are seeking what is peculiar to man. Let us exclude, therefore, the life of nutrition and growth. Next there would be a life of perception, but it also seems to be common 22 Following Shields (1999). 23 See also EE iii b23; OH ii a8, ii b21-2; Pol. i a23; DA ii.4 416b23. 16

18 even to the horse, the ox, and every animal. There remains, then, an active life of the element that has a rational principle. (NE i b26-7, 1097b a4) Life is here identified as a function common to all living things. Specific functions for particular types of living things are specified by reference to the most complete activities of beings of the same type. As a final support for this definitional thesis we may note that Aristotle identifies the life of a living thing with its essence. That it [i.e., the soul] is substance (ousia) is clear; for in everything the substance ((h)ê ousia) is identical with the cause of its being (to aition tou einai), and here, in the case of living things, their being is to live (to de zên... to einai estin), and of their being and their living the soul in them is the cause or source. (DA ii.4 415b12-4) The essence of a living creature is its life, and it is the essence that we specify in the definition of a thing. 24 This is identified with the final cause of living beings at de Anima ii.4 415b15-20 and Generation of Animals i.1 715a4-8. I conclude, then, that Aristotle defines being alive in terms of the possession of teleological directedness. The core notion of being animate, then, can be expressed in the following definition. (D4 on your handout). x is alive =df x possesses teleological directedness. This account captures the core insight appealed to in Matthews' account of life, but avoids the problems associated with his account by explicitly emphasizing the teleological character of life. No reductive strategy is here employed on Aristotle's notion of teleology, as I believe is appropriate to Aristotle's own views. Whatever we initially think about the plausibility of sui generis teleology from a modern naturalistic standpoint, this robust and nonreductive definition 24 See APo. ii.10 93b29-30; Top. i.4 101b20-2, i.5 101b31, i.8 103b9-10, vii.3 153a15-22, vii.5 154a31; Met. viii a

19 of life avoids the problems associated with reductive accounts and sets us on the right track, I claim, for a fully acceptable account of life. (See again the criteria of adequacy on your handout.) Nevertheless, the account as developed thus far is open to obvious counterexamples, for artifacts have purposes but are not alive. Such counterexamples can be overcome, however if Aristotle distinguishes between possessing ends intrinsically (as living things do) and having them derivatively (as artifacts do). I will now argue that Aristotle does draw this distinction. The distinction between intrinsic and derived ends appears in the following extended passage. (This is text 7 on your handout.) But the prior (to proteron) is already [said] in many ways. [E.g.] [i] that for the sake of which a thing is and [ii] the thing which is for its sake are different and the latter [, ii,] is prior in coming to be, but the former [, i,] prior in being (ousia(i)). Further, that which is for the sake of an end has two divisions, first, [ii'] that whence motion is, and second [ii''] that which is used by that for the sake of which. I mean, first, [ii'] something that generates, and second, [ii''] the organ or tool used for the thing generated.... So there are three things: first, [i] the end or that for the sake of which; second, [ii'] the things for the end the source of motion and generation (for what is productive or generative is, as itself, relative to (pros) what it makes or generates); third, [ii''] the useful or those which the end uses. Thus, first some part which contains the source of motion [ii'] must come to be..., next after this the whole and end [i] [comes to be], and third and last the organic parts serving this [i.e., the end] for certain uses [ii'']. (GA ii.6 742a21-36, with omission. My translation, following Peck) This passage claims that both the generative principle, [ii'], and the organs of living beings, [ii''], are posterior in being to the being or form that is the end of generation and whose ends regulate the activity of the organs. Now, the being of an organ is determined by its function, by what it is for (GA i.2 716a23-5). Generation of Animals ii.6, then, states that organs derive their being ( = their ends) from the form; the teleology of organs is derived teleology. The teleological function that defines the organs and generative principle is 18

20 posterior in being, that is, that it derives its end from the prior ends of the mature form. This commitment is confirmed by Aristotle's well known claim that the body and its parts exist for the sake of the soul (DA ii.1 415b17-18, PA i.5 645b15-20, PA i.1 642a12-4; see GA ii b21-2), but that the soul does not likewise exist for the sake of the body (see PA iv b14). The body's parts, defined functionally (GA i.2 716a23-5), are defined in terms of their contribution to the intrinsic well-being of the whole whose ends they serve. But, as we saw in Generation of Animals ii.6 (text seven), the whole is prior in being to the parts and does not derive its ends or goods from any prior ends. This distinction between intrinsic and derived ends is further confirmed by Aristotle's well known commitment to the claim that body parts such as eyes and hands are only homonymously (or equivocally) 'eyes' or 'hands' once the organism of which they are parts has died: the parts are defined by their functions, and their function depends for its existence on the life of the organism to which they belong. 25 I claim, then, that we have Aristotelian license to draw the distinction necessary to adequately handle the problem artifactual ends pose for the original Aristotelian definition of life in terms of the possession of teleological directedness. Aristotle holds that certain things with purposes derive the being or essence of their ends from the being or essence from other, nonderivative ends. Thus, D5 on your handout, 19

21 x is alive = df x possesses intrinsic teleological directedness. expresses Aristotle's notion of what it is to be alive. This account of life in terms of the possession of intrinsic teleological directedness solves the interpretive problems any such account must solve. It avoids the problem of circularity, it provides unity to the diversity of marks of life, it accounts for god's life (for god has ends, see NE i a15 & Met. ii.1 993b21), and it accounts for Aristotle's contention that different things live in different ways (this is so, roughly, since the ends of different kinds of living things will be different). I conclude, therefore, that this is indeed Aristotle's account of life. I hold, more strongly, that this account of life satisfies the criteria of adequacy listed on your handout, but the full argument for that stronger philosophical thesis is beyond the scope of the present paper. Thank you. 25 See Meteor. iv a10-15; DA i.1 412b17-24; Pol. i a20-5; PA i.1 640b30-641a6; GA ii.1 734b25-7; Int a

22 Bibliography Churchland, Paul M Matter and Consciousness. Revised Edition ed. Cambridge: A Bradford Book: The MIT Press. Matthews, Gareth B De Anima and the Meaning of Life. In Essays on Aristotle's De Anima, edited by M. C. N. A. O. Rorty. New York: Oxford University Press. pp Reprinted in Boden, Margaret A., ed The Philosophy of Artificial Life. New York: Oxford University Press. pp Millikan, Ruth G In Defense of Proper Functions. Philosophy of Science 56: Reprinted in Allen, Colin, Marc Bekoff, and George Lauder, eds Nature's Purposes: Analyses of Function and Design in Biology: The MIT Press. pp Neander, Karen Functions as Selected Effects: The Conceptual Analyst's Defence. Philosophy of Science 58: Reprinted in Allen, Colin, Marc Bekoff, and George Lauder, eds Nature's Purposes: Analyses of Function and Design in Biology: The MIT Press. Shields, Christopher Order in Multiplicity: Homonymy in the Philosophy of Aristotle. Oxford: Clarendon Press. Warren, Mary Anne Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and Other Living Things. Oxford: Clarendon Press. 21

Aristotle s Metaphysics

Aristotle s Metaphysics Aristotle s Metaphysics Book Γ: the study of being qua being First Philosophy Aristotle often describes the topic of the Metaphysics as first philosophy. In Book IV.1 (Γ.1) he calls it a science that studies

More information

Aristotle on the Human Good

Aristotle on the Human Good 24.200: Aristotle Prof. Sally Haslanger November 15, 2004 Aristotle on the Human Good Aristotle believes that in order to live a well-ordered life, that life must be organized around an ultimate or supreme

More information

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code The aim of this paper is to explore and elaborate a puzzle about definition that Aristotle raises in a variety of forms in APo. II.6,

More information

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 5 September 16 th, 2015 Malevich, Kasimir. (1916) Suprematist Composition. Gaut on Identifying Art Last class, we considered Noël Carroll s narrative approach to identifying

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas Rachel Singpurwalla It is well known that Plato sketches, through his similes of the sun, line and cave, an account of the good

More information

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts Normativity and Purposiveness What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts of a triangle and the colour green, and our cognition of birch trees and horseshoe crabs

More information

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] Like David Charles, I am puzzled about the relationship between Aristotle

More information

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Z.13: Substances and Universals Summary of Zeta so far Z.13: Substances and Universals Let us now take stock of what we seem to have learned so far about substances in Metaphysics Z (with some additional ideas about essences from APst.

More information

The Doctrine of the Mean

The Doctrine of the Mean The Doctrine of the Mean In subunit 1.6, you learned that Aristotle s highest end for human beings is eudaimonia, or well-being, which is constituted by a life of action by the part of the soul that has

More information

The Analysis of Aristotelian Teleology. defense of the commitments generated by the view.

The Analysis of Aristotelian Teleology. defense of the commitments generated by the view. Chapter 4. The Analysis of Aristotelian Teleology The topics of the previous chapter included the scope of and the epistemological grounds for Aristotle's natural teleology. I argued that the scope of

More information

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications One and Many in Aristotle s Metaphysics: Books Alpha-Delta. By Edward C. Halper. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing, 2009. Pp. xli + 578. $48.00 (hardback). ISBN: 978-1-930972-6. Julie K. Ward Halper s volume

More information

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example Paul Schollmeier I Let us assume with the classical philosophers that we have a faculty of theoretical intuition, through which we intuit theoretical principles,

More information

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Reviewed by Christopher Pincock, Purdue University (pincock@purdue.edu) June 11, 2010 2556 words

More information

Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5

Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5 Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5 Alan Code (I) An Alleged Difficulty for Aristotle s Conception of Matter Aristotle s Metaphysics employs a conception of matter for generated items

More information

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima Caleb Cohoe Caleb Cohoe 2 I. Introduction What is it to truly understand something? What do the activities of understanding that we engage

More information

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright Forthcoming in Disputatio McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright In giving an account of the content of perceptual experience, several authors, including

More information

Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie)

Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie) Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie) Born in Ionia (Greece c. 384BC REMEMBER THE MILESIAN FOCUS!!!), supporter of Macedonia father was physician to Philip II of Macedon. Begins studies at Plato

More information

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238. The final chapter of the book is devoted to the question of the epistemological status of holistic pragmatism itself. White thinks of it as a thesis, a statement that may have been originally a very generalized

More information

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT This article observes methodological aspects of conflict-contractual theory

More information

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY The six articles in this part represent over a decade of work on subjective probability and utility, primarily in the context of investigations that fall within

More information

Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science

Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science ecs@macmillan.co.uk Encyclopedia of Cognitive Science Mental content, teleological theories of Reference code: 128 Ruth Garrett Millikan Professor of Philosophy University of Connecticut Philosophy Department

More information

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato Aristotle Aristotle Lived 384-323 BC. He was a student of Plato. Was the tutor of Alexander the Great. Founded his own school: The Lyceum. He wrote treatises on physics, cosmology, biology, psychology,

More information

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Commentary Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Laura M. Castelli laura.castelli@exeter.ox.ac.uk Verity Harte s book 1 proposes a reading of a series of interesting passages

More information

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions Francesco Orilia Department of Philosophy, University of Macerata (Italy) Achille C. Varzi Department of Philosophy, Columbia University, New York (USA) (Published

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [Phil Corkum] On: 14 August 2013, At: 09:59 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,

More information

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a Comments on Mariska Leunissen s Aristotle s Syllogistic Model of Knowledge and the Biological Sciences: Demonstrating Natural Processes Allan Gotthelf Introduction In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere)

More information

THE EVOLUTIONARY VIEW OF SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS Dragoş Bîgu dragos_bigu@yahoo.com Abstract: In this article I have examined how Kuhn uses the evolutionary analogy to analyze the problem of scientific progress.

More information

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Book Review Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Nate Jackson Hugh P. McDonald, Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values. New York: Rodopi, 2011. xxvi + 361 pages. ISBN 978-90-420-3253-8.

More information

observation and conceptual interpretation

observation and conceptual interpretation 1 observation and conceptual interpretation Most people will agree that observation and conceptual interpretation constitute two major ways through which human beings engage the world. Questions about

More information

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring 2014 Russell Marcus Hamilton College Class #4: Aristotle Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy

More information

1. Introduction. Kathrin Koslicki Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta

1. Introduction. Kathrin Koslicki Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta The Causal Priority of Form in Aristotle Kathrin Koslicki Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta In various texts (e.g., Met. Z.17), Aristotle assigns priority to form, in its role as a principle

More information

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Testa, Italo email: italo.testa@unipr.it webpage: http://venus.unive.it/cortella/crtheory/bios/bio_it.html University of Parma, Dipartimento

More information

Substance, Nature, and Immanence Form in Aristotle s Constituent Ontology

Substance, Nature, and Immanence Form in Aristotle s Constituent Ontology Substance, Nature, and Immanence Form in Aristotle s Constituent Ontology MICHAEL J. LOUX, UNIVERSITY OF NOTRE DAME Aristotle is what we might call a constituent ontologist. At least, in the Physics and,

More information

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Anca-Gabriela Ghimpu Phd. Candidate UBB, Cluj-Napoca Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Paper contents Introduction: motivation

More information

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers Cast of Characters X-Phi: Experimental Philosophy E-Phi: Empirical Philosophy A-Phi: Armchair Philosophy Challenges to Experimental Philosophy Empirical

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

Predication and Ontology: The Categories Predication and Ontology: The Categories A theory of ontology attempts to answer, in the most general possible terms, the question what is there? A theory of predication attempts to answer the question

More information

ARISTOTLE. PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm

ARISTOTLE. PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm ARISTOTLE Dr. V. Adluri Office: Hunter West, 12 th floor, Room 1242 Telephone: 973 216 7874 Email: vadluri@hunter.cuny.edu

More information

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments. Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring 2014 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #3 - Plato s Platonism Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction

More information

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki 1 The Polish Peasant in Europe and America W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki Now there are two fundamental practical problems which have constituted the center of attention of reflective social practice

More information

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015): Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015): 224 228. Philosophy of Microbiology MAUREEN A. O MALLEY Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2014 x + 269 pp., ISBN 9781107024250,

More information

LYCEUM A Publication of the Philosophy Department Saint Anselm College

LYCEUM A Publication of the Philosophy Department Saint Anselm College Volume IX, No. 2 Spring 2008 LYCEUM Aristotle s Form of the Species as Relation Theodore Di Maria, Jr. What Was Hume s Problem about Personal Identity in the Appendix? Megan Blomfield The Effect of Luck

More information

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic 1 Reply to Stalnaker Timothy Williamson In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic as Metaphysics between contingentism in modal metaphysics and the use of

More information

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Introduction Naïve realism regards the sensory experiences that subjects enjoy when perceiving (hereafter perceptual experiences) as being, in some

More information

Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy

Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy Our theme is the relation between modern reductionist science and political philosophy. The question is whether political philosophy can meet the

More information

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. The Republic is intended by Plato to answer two questions: (1) What IS justice? and (2) Is it better to

More information

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala 1 Forms and Causality in the Phaedo Michael Wiitala Abstract: In Socrates account of his second sailing in the Phaedo, he relates how his search for the causes (αἰτίαι) of why things come to be, pass away,

More information

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Action Theory for Creativity and Process Action Theory for Creativity and Process Fu Jen Catholic University Bernard C. C. Li Keywords: A. N. Whitehead, Creativity, Process, Action Theory for Philosophy, Abstract The three major assignments for

More information

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18 Università della Svizzera italiana Faculty of Communication Sciences Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18 Philosophy. The Master in Philosophy at USI is a research master with a special focus on theoretical

More information

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013): Book Review John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel Jeff Jackson John R. Shook and James A. Good, John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. New York:

More information

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy By Wesley Spears For Samford University, UFWT 102, Dr. Jason Wallace, on May 6, 2010 A Happy Ending The matters of philosophy

More information

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In Demonstratives, David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a Appeared in Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (1995), pp. 227-240. What is Character? David Braun University of Rochester In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions

More information

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules Logic and argumentation techniques Dialogue types, rules Types of debates Argumentation These theory is concerned wit the standpoints the arguers make and what linguistic devices they employ to defend

More information

GRADUATE SEMINARS

GRADUATE SEMINARS FALL 2016 Phil275: Proseminar Harmer: Composition, Identity, and Persistence) This course will investigate responses to the following question from both early modern (i.e. 17th & 18th century) and contemporary

More information

On Happiness Aristotle

On Happiness Aristotle On Happiness 1 On Happiness Aristotle It may be said that every individual man and all men in common aim at a certain end which determines what they choose and what they avoid. This end, to sum it up briefly,

More information

Thesis-Defense Paper Project Phi 335 Epistemology Jared Bates, Winter 2014

Thesis-Defense Paper Project Phi 335 Epistemology Jared Bates, Winter 2014 Thesis-Defense Paper Project Phi 335 Epistemology Jared Bates, Winter 2014 In the thesis-defense paper, you are to take a position on some issue in the area of epistemic value that will require some additional

More information

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press. In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press. The voluminous writing on mechanisms of the past decade or two has focused on explanation and causation.

More information

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY Overall grade boundaries Grade: E D C B A Mark range: 0-7 8-15 16-22 23-28 29-36 The range and suitability of the work submitted As has been true for some years, the majority

More information

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) Both the natural and the social sciences posit taxonomies or classification schemes that divide their objects of study into various categories. Many philosophers hold

More information

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna Kuhn Formalized Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna christian.damboeck@univie.ac.at In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1996 [1962]), Thomas Kuhn presented his famous

More information

Categories and Schemata

Categories and Schemata Res Cogitans Volume 1 Issue 1 Article 10 7-26-2010 Categories and Schemata Anthony Schlimgen Creighton University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Part of the

More information

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism THIS PDF FILE FOR PROMOTIONAL USE ONLY 6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism Representationism, 1 as I use the term, says that the phenomenal character of an experience just is its representational

More information

Ridgeview Publishing Company

Ridgeview Publishing Company Ridgeview Publishing Company Externalism, Naturalism and Method Author(s): Kirk A. Ludwig Source: Philosophical Issues, Vol. 4, Naturalism and Normativity (1993), pp. 250-264 Published by: Ridgeview Publishing

More information

Kent Academic Repository

Kent Academic Repository Kent Academic Repository Full text document (pdf) Citation for published version Sayers, Sean (1995) The Value of Community. Radical Philosophy (69). pp. 2-4. ISSN 0300-211X. DOI Link to record in KAR

More information

Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds in Aristotle

Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds in Aristotle Stein, N. 2018. Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds in Aristotle. Metaphysics, 1(1): pp. 33 51, DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/met.8 RESEARCH Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds

More information

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb CLOSING REMARKS The Archaeology of Knowledge begins with a review of methodologies adopted by contemporary historical writing, but it quickly

More information

Aristotle on the Perception of Universals

Aristotle on the Perception of Universals Forthcoming in the British Journal for the History of Philosophy. Please cite published version. Aristotle on the Perception of Universals Marc Gasser-Wingate In the Posterior Analytics, Aristotle tells

More information

Aristotle on Various Types of Alteration in De Anima II 5

Aristotle on Various Types of Alteration in De Anima II 5 Phronesis 56 (2011) 138-161 brill.nl/phro Aristotle on Various Types of Alteration in De Anima II 5 John Bowin Philosophy Department, University of California Santa Cruz, Cowell Academic Services, 1156

More information

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense Philosophical Psychology, 2015 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2015.1010197 REVIEW ESSAY Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense Clare Batty The First Sense: A Philosophical

More information

Page 1

Page 1 PHILOSOPHY, EDUCATION AND THEIR INTERDEPENDENCE The inter-dependence of philosophy and education is clearly seen from the fact that the great philosphers of all times have also been great educators and

More information

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal Aristotle 384-322 The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal Pupil of Plato, Preceptor of Alexander 150 books, 1/5 known Stagira 367-347 Academy 347 Atarneus 343-335 Mieza 335-322 Lyceum Chalcis

More information

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 44, 2015 Book Review Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Philip Kitcher

More information

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism

Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism Gruber 1 Blake J Gruber Rhet-257: Rhetorical Criticism Professor Hovden 12 February 2010 Comparing Neo-Aristotelian, Close Textual Analysis, and Genre Criticism The concept of rhetorical criticism encompasses

More information

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART Tatyana Shopova Associate Professor PhD Head of the Center for New Media and Digital Culture Department of Cultural Studies, Faculty of Arts South-West University

More information

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn The social mechanisms approach to explanation (SM) has

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Karin de Boer Angelica Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant

More information

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics, Review of The Meaning of Ought by Matthew Chrisman Billy Dunaway, University of Missouri St Louis Forthcoming in The Journal of Philosophy In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from

More information

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN: Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, 2013. Pp X -336. $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN: 978-0674724549. Lucas Angioni The aim of Malink s book is to provide a consistent

More information

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses ' 11 Aristotelian Explanation GARETH B. MATTHEWS Jaakko Hintikka's influential paper, "On the Ingredients of an Aristotelian Science,"' suggests an interesting experiment. We should select a bright and

More information

On Recanati s Mental Files

On Recanati s Mental Files November 18, 2013. Penultimate version. Final version forthcoming in Inquiry. On Recanati s Mental Files Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu 1 Frege (1892) introduced us to the notion of a sense or a mode

More information

Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms. Robert Pasnau

Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms. Robert Pasnau Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms Robert Pasnau Stephen Dumont has given us a masterful reconstruction of a fascinating fourteenth-century debate that lies at the boundary of metaphysics

More information

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

In his essay Of the Standard of Taste, Hume describes an apparent conflict between two Aesthetic Judgment and Perceptual Normativity HANNAH GINSBORG University of California, Berkeley, U.S.A. Abstract: I draw a connection between the question, raised by Hume and Kant, of how aesthetic judgments

More information

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany Internal Realism Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany Abstract. This essay characterizes a version of internal realism. In I will argue that for semantical

More information

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton This essay will explore a number of issues raised by the approaches to the philosophy of language offered by Locke and Frege. This

More information

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable, ARISTOTELIAN COLORS AS CAUSES Festschrift for Julius Moravcsik, edd., D.Follesdall, J. Woods, College Publications (London:2008), pages 235-242 For Aristotle the study of living things, speaking quite

More information

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna christian.damboeck@univie.ac.at a community of scientific specialists will do all it can to ensure the

More information

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space Book Review/173 Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space BONGRAE SEOK Alvernia University, Reading, Pennsylvania, USA (bongrae.seok@alvernia.edu) Owen Flanagan, The Geography of Morals,

More information

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery Nick Wiltsher Fifth Online Consciousness Conference, Feb 15-Mar 1 2013 In Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery,

More information

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction 1/10 Berkeley on Abstraction In order to assess the account George Berkeley gives of abstraction we need to distinguish first, the types of abstraction he distinguishes, second, the ways distinct abstract

More information

Aristotle's Psychology First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version)

Aristotle's Psychology First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version) Page 1 of 11 First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version) Aristotle (384 322 BC) was born in Macedon, in what is now northern

More information

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason THE A PRIORI GROUNDS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE THAT a concept, although itself neither contained in the concept of possible experience nor consisting of elements

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

Celine Granjou The Friends of My Friends

Celine Granjou The Friends of My Friends H U M a N I M A L I A 6:1 REVIEWS Celine Granjou The Friends of My Friends Dominique Lestel, Les Amis de mes amis (The Friends of my Friends). Paris: Seuil, 2007. 220p. 20.00 Dominique Lestel is a very

More information

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory Patrick Maher Philosophy 517 Spring 2007 Popper s propensity theory Introduction One of the principal challenges confronting any objectivist theory

More information

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana Aristotle By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana Aristotle: Occupation Greek philosopher whose writings cover many subjects, including physics, metaphysics, poetry, theater, music, logic, rhetoric, linguistics, politics,

More information

Substances. The Categories

Substances. The Categories 12 Substances s. marc cohen Aristotle divides the things that there are or beings (ta onta) into a number of different categories. He is not always consistent about how many categories there are (ten in

More information

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography Dawn M. Phillips 1 Introduction In his 1983 article, Photography and Representation, Roger Scruton presented a powerful and provocative sceptical position. For most people interested in the aesthetics

More information

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted Overall grade boundaries PHILOSOPHY Grade: E D C B A Mark range: 0-7 8-15 16-22 23-28 29-36 The range and suitability of the work submitted The submitted essays varied with regards to levels attained.

More information

Alexander of Aphrodisias s Account of Universals and Its Problems

Alexander of Aphrodisias s Account of Universals and Its Problems Alexander of Aphrodisias s Account of Universals and Its Problems R I I N SI R K EL the philosophical problem of universals is traditionally framed as the problem about the ontological status of universals.

More information