Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5"

Transcription

1 Aristotle on the matter of corpses in Metaphysics H5 Alan Code (I) An Alleged Difficulty for Aristotle s Conception of Matter Aristotle s Metaphysics employs a conception of matter for generated items according to which the matter of an X is something that exists before the X, and is that from which the X comes-to-be. 1 Furthermore, for Aristotle there are both actual beings and potential beings, and the matter for an X is a potential X. The matter for a horse, for instance, is a potential horse. The potential horse might never become an actual horse, but if and when it does, it does so because the matter (i.e., the potential horse) possesses the form of a horse. When the form is present to the matter, this potential horse constitutes an actual horse. In De Anima, II.1, his hylomorphic analysis of sublunary living substances treats the matter, or what is potentially living a horse s life, as organic body, 2 and the form that makes the matter an actual horse is described as the first actuality of such a body. 3 The body is what is potentially alive. However, John Ackrill and others 4 have argued that according to this conception of the body of a living thing, the body is not alive merely contingently. This would seem to contradict the thesis from the Metaphysics that the matter for a living substance is a potential F that exists before that substance does. Ackrill argues that the body that is potentially 1 See, for instance, Metaphysics Z7, 1032b a1, with a a27-b a See Ackrill 1972 and Frey

2 alive is not able to exist after the death of the plant or animal of which it is the body. One of the texts adduced in support of this view is: We must not understand by that which is potentially capable of living what has lost the soul it had, but only what still retains it; but seeds and fruits are bodies which are potentially of that sort. 5 The corpse of a horse that has died has no capacity to be brought back to life. Neither it, nor the parts of which it is composed, are potentially living an equine life. This is thought to support the views that whatever it is that remains after the horse has died is not an organic body that served as its matter, and that the matter for a horse cannot exist after the death of the horse. What is this organic body? Commentators often have often understood it to be a body having organs. Ackrill, for instance, writes as follows: Aristotle characterises the animal s body as potentially alive and as having organs such organs, clearly, as eyes, hands, heart, etc. 6 If an organic body is a body having non-uniform organs such as these, then since these kinds of organs cannot exist without soul, 7 it would follow that 5 De Anima II.1, 412b25-27, from The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation. 6 p See Metaphysics Z11, 1036b Something is not a hand (except homonymously) without soul, since without soul it would not be able to perform the function of a hand. His view is not simply that a hand is not a part of a man if it is not ensouled, and hence unable to perform the function of a hand. This would incorrectly leave open the possibility that some hand that is now a part of a human could at a later time exist without soul, though in that case it would no longer be a part of man. However, the hand that is currently a part of some human cannot exist when the man dies, or when it is severed 2

3 the organic body itself cannot exist without soul. This would effectively block the possibility that an organic body of the relevant sort could be potentially alive only contingently. Since the animal itself has organs such as eyes and the like, on such a view it is hard to see how Aristotle could distinguish the animal from its body. If the organic body cannot exist without its non-uniform parts, and these cannot exist without soul, then it cannot exist after the death of the horse. Equally, it would not exist prior to the animal either, and so it is able to exist at all and only those times at which the composite substance exists. Since an animal s organic body is its matter, this requires that the matter exists only when the composite itself exists. Additionally, as the body that potentially has life, the matter of an animal exists only when that potentially is realized. (II) Two Aristotelian Puzzles about Matter Having claimed that there is matter only for things that are generated and that change into one another, Aristotle raises two puzzles about the matter for such changes. The first is a puzzle about the manner in which that matter is related to contraries. Suppose that sickness and health are contraries and that the body is the matter that is potentially healthy. Is the body also potentially sick? Likewise, if water is the matter for wine and is potentially wine, is it also potentially vinegar? from the body. A dead hand, or severed hand, is not the same entity as the living hand. It is a hand in name only. We can see the same view in Meteorology IV.12: 329b31-330a2. 3

4 Aristotle does not develop the puzzle before answering it, but let us pause to consider why it might seem problematic to treat the body as potentially sick or the water as potentially vinegar. Suppose that makes something potentially F in the first place is the possession of a dunamis or capacity. Just as an eye potentially sees because it possesses sight, the capacity to see, a body is potentially healthy because it possesses a certain capacity -- a capacity to be healthy. This is a capacity to receive a certain form. Furthermore, if the matter that is potentially healthy also is potentially sick, and being potentially F always requires an appropriate dunamis by reference to which something is potentially F, then if it is potentially sick it must also have some dunamis or capacity to be sick. But is this the right way to look at the situation? The human body has an ability to be in a healthy condition, and being healthy is the exercise of that ability. However, there is not some other ability that it also has, the exercise of which constitutes its being sick. However, lacking such an ability, how is it that it can be potentially sick? His answer involves distinguishing a form and a corresponding privative condition, or sterêsis. Health is a form and also what he calls a hexis, a state or condition that the body is in when we call it healthy. A body is spoken of as potentially healthy because of its relation to this state. It has the ability to be in that state. However, illness is not some other form or hexis that a body might be in, but rather is the privation of that condition in the kind of body that is of such a nature to be receptive of health. This privation is not merely the absence of health in the 4

5 body, but is the destruction (or, I would suggest, rather the result of the destruction) of health in a body. 8 Additionally, he describes the destruction as against the nature. There are two ways one might take this, according to whether the nature in question is the nature of the body or the nature of health, but arguably they come to the same thing. Health is the good condition of the body, and as such this is a natural condition of the body. The privation of health is contrary to this good condition, and so is against both the nature of the body and the nature of health. Despite the fact that wine and vinegar are not opposites in the way that health and sickness are, he cites this as another instance of the puzzle as to how matter is related to opposites, and the same kind of solution is supposed to apply here as well. Hence water is wine by virtue of the possession of a form and a positive state or condition that water is able to possess. In accordance with his solution to the puzzle, water is vinegar not by possessing the form of vinegar, for there is no such form. It is rather that water is vinegar due to the destruction of the form of wine. As a result of this destruction the water is characterized by privation or lack of a form. Additionally, this destruction is against the nature--either the nature of the form or the nature of water. If this is parallel to the other case, then the form of wine would be a good condition for which water is naturally suited, and as such a natural condition of water. The privation is not simply the absence 8 This would seem to rule out the possibility that something could be chronically ill from birth. A diseased state requires some kind of falling away from a good condition, even if that good condition is merely some part of health, as opposed to its entirety. 5

6 of this good condition, but is the condition that water is in as a result of that form having been destroyed in that water. Aristotle immediately raises a second puzzle about the matter for such things as follows: and there is also a certain puzzle as to why wine is not the matter of vinegar nor potentially vinegar (and yet vinegar comes to be from it) and why a living thing is not potentially a corpse. 9 Just as wine passes away into vinegar, so too an animal passes away into a corpse. What once was wine is no longer wine, but has become vinegar; likewise what once was a living thing is no longer alive and has become a corpse. There is something X that once was wine and now is vinegar; likewise, there is something Y that once was a living animal and now is just a corpse. In each case the passing away of one thing is the coming to be of something else. The argument is this: (1) a) Vinegar comes to be from the matter of vinegar and what is potentially vinegar. b) A corpse comes to be from the matter of a corpse and what is potentially a corpse. (2) a) Vinegar comes to be from wine. b) A corpse comes to be from a living thing. 9 Metaphysics VIII. 5, 1044b

7 So: (3) a) Wine is the matter of vinegar and potentially vinegar. b) A living thing is the matter of a corpse and potentially a corpse. This is problematic if there is reason to accept the premises as true and yet reject the conclusion as false. The first premise embodies the idea sketched in the first paragraph of this paper that whenever an F comes into being, it comes into being from something X that already exists. Elsewhere Aristotle discusses various uses of the expression from which, and distinguishes the sense in which something comes to be from a lack or privation from a sense in which it comes to be from something that which persists through the change. For instance, in Physics I.7 he tells us that we can use the from which locution in connection with the privation or the form, as when we say such things as that the musical comes to be from the unmusical. In those cases in which that from which something comes to be is designated by reference to a form or its privation, that from which the product comes to be is not something that persists. However, there are also cases in which an item described as that from which a product comes to be does persist. 10 In those cases this persisting item is neither privation nor form, but rather is the matter that at successive times is characterized by possession of form and the corresponding privation. This second aporia arises only if the expression from which is used in the same way in both premises. Thus 10 See Metaph. VII.7,1033a5-23 and Physics I.7,190a

8 one could solve the puzzle by showing that there is no single reading of the locution from which that makes both of our premises 1ab and 2ab true. In accordance with the solution to our first aporia we may say that this matter is both potentially F and potentially deprived of F. In general, prior to the coming to be of an F there must be some X that is potentially F but not yet F. Prior to the coming to be of vinegar there is something that is not yet vinegar, but is potentially vinegar; prior to the production of a corpse there is something that is not yet a corpse but is potentially a corpse. Additionally, the destruction of a G requires that there is something that prior to the destruction is G, but is no longer G. Suppose that the living thing in question is a horse. Prior to the destruction of the horse there is some Y that is a horse, but is potentially not horse. This Y is something that exists before the corpse is produced, and at that prior time this Y was a horse. It is also something that continues to exist even after the horse has died, and when that Y is no longer a horse Y is a corpse. In both of these cases something has perished and what has perished did not persist through the change. What persists is rather some matter that is potentially characterized both by a form and a privation of that form. (III) Aristotle s Solution and Accidental Destruction Here is how Aristotle explains why the wine is not potentially vinegar and the living thing is not potentially a corpse: In fact they are not, but the corruptions in question are accidental, and it is the matter of the animal that is itself in virtue of its corruption the 8

9 potency and matter of a corpse, and it is water that is the matter of vinegar. 11 In each case something passes away, and the item that passes away does not persist through the change. The item that passes away is not the matter that is potentially vinegar or a corpse, respectively. When he says that the corruptions are accidental he does not mean that it is merely an accident that wine turns into vinegar or that living things become dead things. Rather he is making that point that the item that the change is accidental with respect to is the substratum for that change. For instance, in the wine to vinegar case, the subject for the change is the water that first constitutes wine and later constitutes vinegar. The destruction of the wine is an accidental modification of the water that serves as the matter for the change. The matter for wine is also the matter for vinegar, and it is matter for the latter by virtue of the corruption of form that takes place in it. Likewise, the matter for a living thing is also the matter for corpse, and is so by virtue of the corruption of form that takes place in it. Thus according to this solution, the matter into which some object passes away is only contingently in possession of the form of that object. On this conception of matter the matter for an animal is not something that exists only when soul is present, or only when the animal itself exists. There is a sense in which our second premise 2ab is true, and to convey this he compares it to the way in which night comes to be from day. In this case the substratum is the air, and the air constitutes day when light is present to it, and it constitutes night when the air is characterized by the privation of light. The air itself is contingently related to the light or 11 Revised Oxford Translation, 1044b a2. 9

10 darkness that characterize it at any given time. Light and dark are contraries, and the air is potentially both in the way that water is potentially both wine and vinegar. (IV) Reciprocal Change The topic that has been under discussion, and for which these puzzles were devised, is reciprocal change. He now goes on to apply these results to this main topic and concludes that And all the things which change thus into one another must go back to their matter; e.g. if from a corpse is produced an animal, the corpse first goes back to its matter, and only then becomes an animal; and vinegar first goes back to water, and only then becomes wine. 12 This is sometimes taken to imply that whenever the passing away of one thing is the production of another there must always be an intermediary transitional stage at which the original object reverts to its matter. For instance, if an animal comes to be from the corpse, then first the corpse reverts to its matter. This matter can then, as the result of an additional step, become an animal. There is some matter Y such that Y used to be a horse, later Y was a corpse and still later the corpse reverts back to Y, and then Y is a new animal of some sort. Aristotle does not here give an example, but commentators have their suggestions. David Bostock suggests a case of a

11 spontaneous generation, that of maggots coming to be from dead animals. 13 However, Bostock also disputes Aristotle s claim that an intermediary, transitional stage in necessary for these reciprocal transformation in both directions. To see why Aristotle requires the transitional stage in the vinegar to wine and the corpse to animal cases it is useful to see how he thinks these differ from their reverse changes. Ross wrongly holds that Aristotle does not think that the reverse changes differ on this point, and claims that Aristotle commits himself to the view that the change of one thing into another always involves an intermediate, transitional state in which there is a reversion to matter. He writes there is no direct transition from the normal product to the abnormal product, nor vice versa; the given product must first be reduced to its constituent matter. 14 Hence when the living thing dies, it must first revert to matter before becoming a corpse, and when wine becomes vinegar, it must first become water, before it becomes vinegar. However, as shall become clear in a moment, there is a reason why the transitional state is needed in the transition from the abnormal to the normal product, and that reason does not apply to the change in the other direction. Whatever the examples may be, one feature that is crucial to this kind of case is that the same Y is the matter for all three products: 13 p vol.2. p

12 There is a matter Y such that: and (i) Y was the matter for a horse, (ii) Y was later the matter for a corpse, (iii) Y was in a reverted transitional state, (iv) Y is now the matter for some new animal. With the possible exception of stage (iii) the matter constitutes some product where the relation between that matter and what it constitutes is temporary and contingent. At stage (i) this matter is living, but is so only contingently, and can continue to exist as the matter of a corpse. In the transitional stage (iii) Y is no longer a corpse, but not yet a new animal. What can we say about the condition of the matter at this transitional stage? Perhaps Bostock is right and he is thinking of spontaneous generation, but Aristotle gives no indication that the point is restricted to this special type of case. Also, although he does not give us a description of this transitional stage, he does provide one for his other example -- that of wine coming to be from vinegar. The two types of case are intended to exemplify the same general point, and in the vinegar to wine case there is a much more straightforward explanation than something like spontaneous generation. There the matter is water, and the respective stages are: (i) Y was the matter for wine, (ii) Y was later the matter for vinegar, (iii) Y was in a reverted transitional state of being water, and (iv) Y is now the matter for some new wine. 12

13 During the transitional stage the water is not said to be the matter of some product, but is described just as water. The designation that applies to it, namely water, characterizes it in terms of what it is in its own right, independently of its constituting some product. How is it that water can be turned back into wine? Wine is produced out of grapes that ferment, and so to get back to wine the water must be taken in by the roots of grape vines and through the normal processes by which such plants grow and are nourished it must then be matter for grapes, that are then fermented. Aristotle does not give us the steps involved in nourishing plants or in winemaking since the details of this are not relevant to the point he is making. The point is simply that unlike the case in which wine turns to vinegar, where there is no need for the wine first to revert back to its matter, it is not possible to reverse the process in just one step. The reverse process requires a set of steps that get the matter back into a condition in which it is potentially wine once more. An idea that he develops in Metaphysics Theta 7 in order to answer the question when should a thing be said to be in potentiality? can help us to understand this. There he considers processes that take place in a series of stages, such as earth becoming wood, and later the wood becoming a box. The earth is potentially wood, and the wood is potentially a box, but prior to becoming wood the earth is not yet potentially a box. 15 It is potentially something, namely some wood, that is potentially a box. The earth first has to be used as nourishment for a tree before it becomes wood, and not until it is wood is it a box in potentiality. Obviously here too he leaves out the a This is compatible with the claim that earth is potentially a box once it has become wood. 13

14 details of how trees are nourished by elementary matter, and leaves out the details involved in the artistic procedures that start from a natural substance and lead to something becoming a work of art. Such details are not relevant to the point he intends to illustrate. What is important is that before the matter is potentially a box it needs to be changed by various processes until it is in a condition where (i) nothing in the matter itself prevents it from being changed into a box (by the operation of a craft skill or otherwise), and (ii) there are no further changes, additions or subtractions needed to get the matter in a condition such that the relevant craft skill can be exercised on it in such as way as to produce a box. 16 Earth does not possess the passive or receptive dunamis that something must have in order to be a potential box. 17 To apply this idea to the vinegar to wine case we may say that when water is vinegar it is no longer potentially wine. Not only is the water no longer in such a condition that somebody in possession of the winemaking craft can exercise that craft skill in such a way as to turn it into wine, but also it lacks the features that earlier had made it something that is potentially wine. As it is now, the winemaking skill can do nothing with it, for the matter is not suitable to be acted upon by that skill. Before that can take place and wine once again will be able to be produced the vinegar must first revert to its matter identified in this passage as water. The water is not yet potentially wine, but rather needs to undergo some series of changes that puts it in a such a condition that the winemaking art can act on it and turn it into wine. Earlier, when the water was wine, it was potentially both wine 16 Based on 1049a The features that initially make it suitable for an artisan with the relevant craft skill to turn it into a box are still possessed even after it has been turned into a box. However, this by itself does not entail that the product can still be acted upon by an artist in such a way as to make a box. Perhaps it can, but there are also the changes that require it to first revert to its matter. 14

15 and vinegar. It was potentially wine and it had the ability to be acted on in such a way as to receive the form of wine. It was potentially vinegar because its ability to receive this form is something that it possessed only contingently, and when this capacity for form was lost the water became vinegar. Once the water is vinegar it is not exercising an ability to possess the form of vinegar. There is no such form. Rather it is vinegar when its capacity to receive the form of wine has been destroyed. This is the reason why it must first revert to its matter in order to be changed back into wine. It now no longer has the capacity to receive the form of wine and so it no longer potentially wine. It will not be potentially wine again unless some series of changes puts it back in a condition where it once again has this ability. The corpse to animal case is supposed to illustrate the same general point about the need to revert back to matter. If the comparison holds, then just as in the vinegar to wine case, the matter for an animal should have a description that applies to it in its own right, independently of is constituting either an animal or a corpse. Unlike the vinegar case, though, he does not indicate just how far the decomposition must go before the matter can be built up again into the new animal. That is, he does not provide a description for this case comparable to the label water for the vinegar/wine case. In Metaphysics Zeta 10 the matter into which an animal perishes is described as bones and connective tissues and flesh. 18 If we provisionally accept this a A bit later at Z10, 1035a31-33, he says And for this reason the earthen statue perishes into potter's earth, and the sphere into bronze, and Callias into flesh and bones. See also Z8, 1034a5-6 where the matter for Socrates and Callias is flesh and bones. In general, individual natural bodies such as animals have natural bodies as material parts. Socrates is a natural body that is composed of flesh and bones. Passages 15

16 view, then when the corpse comes to be from the animal, the flesh and bones play the role of matter. However, the corpse does not undergo some process by which it decomposes into flesh and bone. Rather the corpse is produced when the flesh and bone no longer have soul present to them. 19 such as Z8 gives us no reason to suppose that Socrates also has a body that is composed of these same flesh and bones. At the very least, then, this should make us cautious about accepting the idea that there is any body having Socrates organic parts other than Socrates himself. 19 Generation of Animals II.1, 734b24-36, is sometimes adduced to show that uniform parts such as flesh cannot exist without soul. If this is so, then he there contradicts the view of the Metaphysics. However, the passage does not actually say that it is only homonymously that they will be called face or flesh if the life has gone out of them (the Oxford translation of b25-6). The Greek for if the life has gone out of them is simply phtharenta ( have perished ), and the point is that when the flesh has perished, what is left is only homonymously flesh. It does not say that flesh perishes when life has gone out of it. This passage is a discussion of the formation of parts in embryological development, and it is in this context that we must understand the import of the claims that there is no such thing as face or flesh without soul in it (bb24-25) and the homogeneous parts and the organic come into being together (b27-28). It is not the case that some tissues are formed prior to the imposition of some non-uniform structure. This is a claim about how the tissues get formed in the first place, but not a claim about the conditions for the continued existence of the tissues. When do these organic tissues actually exist?the parts of animals, including flesh, all have functions, and exist only when they have the ability that grounds their performance of that function. If that ability is lost, what remains may still be called by the name of that part, but the part itself has ceased to exist. Ackrill thinks that Aristotle exploits this point in the Meteorology to rule out the possibility of flesh with outside soul. (See IV.12, 390a10-14). However, this text does not say that soul is required in order for the relevant dunamis to continue to exist. Something is flesh by virtue of having a certain dunamis for acting or being acted upon, but since its definition is not stated in a precise manner it is difficult to specify when that power has been lost. (See 390a18-b1.) When a corpse is thoroughly corrupted it is easy to determine that what we have is no longer flesh. However, Aristotle is here assuming that there will be cases in which we are not sure whether a corpse still contains flesh, and this presupposes that flesh can continue to exist after the death of the animal. It continues to exist as flesh just in case it retains its relevant dunamis, but since the function is not clear it is hard to say just what this dunamis is. Something (namely a corpse) could possess flesh with this dunamis although the flesh is no longer even potentially human. The powers of the uniform bodily parts such as flesh are qualities derived from the processes of heating and cooling (390b3-390b14).The powers that enable the uniform parts to perform their functions, such as fragmentability or softness, do not depend upon soul for their continued existence. This is not to say without qualification that flesh could have been generated without soul, but 16

17 In the way in which these materials still exist in the corpse they are still characterized by all sorts of physical properties that previously enabled them to contribute to the life of the animal when they had been present in the animal. The bones, for instance, are still rigid. However, these dispositional properties are not the properties that put some matter into a condition suitable for generative processes that take place in nature. There are all sorts of ways in which the matter of a decaying corpse can eventually end up in new living things, both plants and animals. Nonetheless, the general outline of the story typically will involve organisms ingesting the matter as nutrition, and having the nutritive faculty of the organism that performs the digestion converting it into a form of nutriment appropriate for an organism of that sort. In the case of blooded animals, it is the blood that is the primary form of nutrition and that contains the motions by virtue of which the bodily parts grow and are nourished. This in turn is concocted into catamenia in females, and in this condition the matter can now be acted upon by the vital heat in the male semen. The details of the right embryological theory are not, though, what is important here. What matters is that before the matter is once again potentially human it must undergo a series of transformation and changes that make it capable of receiving human form. It must possess the receptive dunamis to be acted upon by a suitable agent with the appropriate active dunamis. Prior to the coming-tobe of the new horse, an embryo possessed a relevant internal principle, the nature of a horse. It was in virtue of that principle that the embryo was does commit him to the view that the power by virtue of which it performs its functions is a power that can be possessed even without soul. 17

18 potentially a horse. 20 Prior to the change the embryo and the potential horse were the same thing. We learn from Generation of Animals II.4 that nutritive soul is actually present when the higher faculties of soul are still only potentially present, and this faculty of soul is the internal principle of growth and development that guides and controls the formation of the new living substance. 21 This internal principle is still present once the adult has been generated (that is, once all of the higher faculties of soul are actually present). In Aristotle s biology the formative powers and motions in the generative fluids are the same as those in the blood by which the bodily parts grow and are nurtured in the adult horse. Consequently, if something is a potential horse by virtue of that principle, and if the adult still has that principle, then the adult is a potential horse. After the change the potential horse is no longer the same as an embryo. The matter, i.e., the potential horse, is now the same as the adult horse. 22 (V) Organic Body As Contingently Ensouled I conclude by considering how Metaphysics Eta 5 bears on the claim made at De Anima II.1, 412b25-27: We must not understand by that which is potentially capable of living what has lost the soul it had, but only what still retains it; but seeds and fruits are bodies which are potentially of that 20 See Metaph. IX.7, 1049a b2-740a Notice that even if in the case of the adult the potential horse is flesh and bones, at some early stage of embryological development there will be nutritive soul prior to the formation of these materials. Hence the flesh and bones is not the pre-existing matter from which the horse came to be. The earlier matter is potentially a horse, but not yet flesh and bone. Different material bodies constitute the potential horse at different times in its development. 18

19 sort. This statement is consistent with his solutions to the metaphysical puzzles discussed above if it is uniform matter such as flesh and bones that is potentially capable of living a horse s life, but with the restriction that it is so only contingently and only when soul is present to it. 23 What is potentially a horse can continue to exist after the death of the horse, though not as something that is still potentially horse. Granted, this does involve treating flesh and bones as organic, contrary to Aristotle s more established usage of the term for non-uniform parts. 24 Nonetheless, this has the advantage of rendering the De Anima passage consistent with the view of generation put forth in the Metaphysics. Of course, the story cannot end here. If there is some matter for living things that is only contingently alive, one needs to face the question as to why the living organism is not just an accidental unity of matter and form. 23 According to GC I.5,321b19-22, the term flesh is applied to both the form of flesh and to the matter of flesh. There is a sense in which Socrates perishes into flesh, and a sense in which he does not. Soul is present to the matter of flesh when the animal is alive, and this ensouled matter is correctly called flesh. When Socrates dies what is flesh in this sense does not continue to exist; rather what continues to exist is the matter of ensouled flesh. (See Gill 1997.) 24 As Stephen Everson has pointed out (Aristotle on Perception, p.64) outside of this passage, Aristotle uses the term organikon for something that is an organ, not something that has organs. Although an organ may itself be composed of organs, this is not typically what is being said about an organ when it is described as organikon. (See Bonitz 521a20 ff.) If the organic body of De Anima II.1 412a28-b1 is body that serves as an organ, rather than a body having organs, then uniform matter such as flesh and bones count as organic. Although Aristotle will typically use organic to contrast with uniform material parts (see, for instance, 734b27-28), De Anima II.4 says that all natural bodies are organs of the soul (415b18-19). Further, consider his claim in GA I.22, 730b20, that semen, a uniform body, is a tool. 19

20 Among other things, this involves explaining how the matter is merely a potential being, and there is no actual being that serves as the matter for the living organism. This is in fact a topic to which Aristotle immediately turns in the very next chapter, Metaphysics H6, and it is a formidable problem indeed. However, if nothing else, I would hope this paper shows that Aristotle s treatment of puzzles about the matter for the generation of new things in Metaphysics H5 helps us to understand how and why he has metaphysical commitments to views that lead him to this kind of problem. BIBLIOGRAPHY Ackrill, J,L, Aristotle s Definitions of Psychê, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 73 (1972), Barnes, J. ed., The Complete Works of Aristotle: The Revised Oxford Translation, 2 vols. (Princeton: 1995). Bostock, David, Aristotle: Metaphysics Books Ζ and Η. (Oxford, Clarendon Press: 1994). Everson, Stephen, Aristotle on Perception (Oxford:1997). Frey, Christopher, Organic Unity and the Matter of Man, Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy, 32 (Summer 2007), pp Gill, Mary Louise Material Necessity and Meterology IV.12, Aristotelische Biologie:Intentionen, Methoden, Ergebnisse, Philosophie der Antike, vol. VIII, eds.w. Kullmann & S. Foellinger (Steiner Verlag:1997), Ross, W. D., Aristotle's Metaphysics, 2 vols. (Oxford, Clarendon Press:1924). 20

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code The aim of this paper is to explore and elaborate a puzzle about definition that Aristotle raises in a variety of forms in APo. II.6,

More information

Aristotle s Metaphysics

Aristotle s Metaphysics Aristotle s Metaphysics Book Γ: the study of being qua being First Philosophy Aristotle often describes the topic of the Metaphysics as first philosophy. In Book IV.1 (Γ.1) he calls it a science that studies

More information

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable, ARISTOTELIAN COLORS AS CAUSES Festschrift for Julius Moravcsik, edd., D.Follesdall, J. Woods, College Publications (London:2008), pages 235-242 For Aristotle the study of living things, speaking quite

More information

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima Caleb Cohoe Caleb Cohoe 2 I. Introduction What is it to truly understand something? What do the activities of understanding that we engage

More information

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Z.13: Substances and Universals Summary of Zeta so far Z.13: Substances and Universals Let us now take stock of what we seem to have learned so far about substances in Metaphysics Z (with some additional ideas about essences from APst.

More information

Lecture 13 Aristotle on Change

Lecture 13 Aristotle on Change Lecture 13 Aristotle on Change Patrick Maher Scientific Thought I Fall 2009 Introduction This lecture discusses parts of Aristotle s book Physics. The word physics come from Greek phusis, which means nature.

More information

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] Like David Charles, I am puzzled about the relationship between Aristotle

More information

Aristotle on Various Types of Alteration in De Anima II 5

Aristotle on Various Types of Alteration in De Anima II 5 Phronesis 56 (2011) 138-161 brill.nl/phro Aristotle on Various Types of Alteration in De Anima II 5 John Bowin Philosophy Department, University of California Santa Cruz, Cowell Academic Services, 1156

More information

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Commentary Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Laura M. Castelli laura.castelli@exeter.ox.ac.uk Verity Harte s book 1 proposes a reading of a series of interesting passages

More information

Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy

Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy Rousseau on the Nature of Nature and Political Philosophy Our theme is the relation between modern reductionist science and political philosophy. The question is whether political philosophy can meet the

More information

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION Submitted by Jessica Murski Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University

More information

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a Comments on Mariska Leunissen s Aristotle s Syllogistic Model of Knowledge and the Biological Sciences: Demonstrating Natural Processes Allan Gotthelf Introduction In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere)

More information

The Doctrine of the Mean

The Doctrine of the Mean The Doctrine of the Mean In subunit 1.6, you learned that Aristotle s highest end for human beings is eudaimonia, or well-being, which is constituted by a life of action by the part of the soul that has

More information

* For referencing this article please use the Blackwell (2009) version.

* For referencing this article please use the Blackwell (2009) version. CHAPTER 23: GENERATION OF ANIMALS * Devin Henry The place of GA in Aristotle s philosophy The best way to understand the place of Generation of Animals in Aristotle s philosophy is to consider the way

More information

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. The Republic is intended by Plato to answer two questions: (1) What IS justice? and (2) Is it better to

More information

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts) Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle Translated by W. D. Ross Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts) 1. Virtue, then, being of two kinds, intellectual and moral, intellectual virtue in the main owes both its birth and

More information

Aristotle on the Human Good

Aristotle on the Human Good 24.200: Aristotle Prof. Sally Haslanger November 15, 2004 Aristotle on the Human Good Aristotle believes that in order to live a well-ordered life, that life must be organized around an ultimate or supreme

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

QUESTION 49. The Substance of Habits

QUESTION 49. The Substance of Habits QUESTION 49 The Substance of Habits After acts and passions, we have to consider the principles of human acts: first, the intrinsic principles (questions 49-89) and, second, the extrinsic principles (questions

More information

3 DA III.8, 432a102 4 Balme 1987b: Balme 1987a: Freudenthal 1995: 31. Vital heat, according to Freudenthal, is heat carrying informing

3 DA III.8, 432a102 4 Balme 1987b: Balme 1987a: Freudenthal 1995: 31. Vital heat, according to Freudenthal, is heat carrying informing Soul s Tools Jessica Gelber (penultimate draft prepared for Heat, Pneuma and Soul in Ancient Philosophy and Medicine, C. King, H. Bartos (eds.) comments welcome!) According to the embryological theory

More information

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

Predication and Ontology: The Categories Predication and Ontology: The Categories A theory of ontology attempts to answer, in the most general possible terms, the question what is there? A theory of predication attempts to answer the question

More information

Aristotle's Metaphysics of Living Bodies. Thomas Gemelli B.A., Vassar College, 2006

Aristotle's Metaphysics of Living Bodies. Thomas Gemelli B.A., Vassar College, 2006 Aristotle's Metaphysics of Living Bodies by Thomas Gemelli B.A., Vassar College, 2006 A Thesis Submitted in Partial Fulfilment of the Requirements for the degree of MASTER OF ARTS in the Department of

More information

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles Patrick Maher Scientific Thought I Fall 2009 Introduction We ve seen that according to Aristotle: One way to understand something is by having a demonstration

More information

A Basic Aristotle Glossary

A Basic Aristotle Glossary A Basic Aristotle Glossary Part I. Key Terms These explanations of key terms in Aristotle are not as in-depth nor technically as precise as those in the glossary of Irwin and Fine's Selections. They are

More information

Substantial Generation in Physics I 5-7

Substantial Generation in Physics I 5-7 Western University From the SelectedWorks of Devin Henry 2015 Substantial Generation in Physics I 5-7 Devin Henry, The University of Western Ontario Available at: https://works.bepress.com/devinhenry/24/

More information

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato Aristotle Aristotle Lived 384-323 BC. He was a student of Plato. Was the tutor of Alexander the Great. Founded his own school: The Lyceum. He wrote treatises on physics, cosmology, biology, psychology,

More information

ORGANIC UNITY AND THE MATTER OF MAN

ORGANIC UNITY AND THE MATTER OF MAN Created on 30 November 2006 at 17.10 hours page 167 ORGANIC UNITY AND THE MATTER OF MAN CHRISTOPHER FREY 1. Introduction if we assume, as many have, that Aristotle s discussions of artefacts provide us

More information

1/10. The A-Deduction

1/10. The A-Deduction 1/10 The A-Deduction Kant s transcendental deduction of the pure concepts of understanding exists in two different versions and this week we are going to be looking at the first edition version. After

More information

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 45, 2015 On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me IRENA CRONIN University of California, Los Angeles, USA G. E.

More information

On Happiness Aristotle

On Happiness Aristotle On Happiness 1 On Happiness Aristotle It may be said that every individual man and all men in common aim at a certain end which determines what they choose and what they avoid. This end, to sum it up briefly,

More information

Interpreting Aristotle on Mixture: Problems about Elemental Composition from Philoponus to Cooper

Interpreting Aristotle on Mixture: Problems about Elemental Composition from Philoponus to Cooper Interpreting Aristotle on Mixture: Problems about Elemental Composition from Philoponus to Cooper FINAL REVISED DRAFT (24 FEBRUARY 2004) Rega Wood Department of Philosophy Stanford University Building

More information

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason THE A PRIORI GROUNDS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE THAT a concept, although itself neither contained in the concept of possible experience nor consisting of elements

More information

Aristotle on mind. University of Central Florida. Rachel R. Adams University of Central Florida. Open Access HIM

Aristotle on mind. University of Central Florida. Rachel R. Adams University of Central Florida. Open Access HIM University of Central Florida HIM 1990-2015 Open Access Aristotle on mind 2011 Rachel R. Adams University of Central Florida Find similar works at: http://stars.library.ucf.edu/honorstheses1990-2015 University

More information

of perception, elaborated in his De Anima as an isomorphic motion of the soul. It will begin by

of perception, elaborated in his De Anima as an isomorphic motion of the soul. It will begin by This paper will aim to establish that the proper interpretation of Aristotle's epistemology is one of direct realism, rather than representationalism, by way of exploring Aristotle's doctrine of perception,

More information

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA Book III excerpt 3.138 Each of the terms same and diverse, taken by itself, seems to be said in five ways, perhaps more. One thing is called the same as another either i according

More information

Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms. Robert Pasnau

Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms. Robert Pasnau Comments on Dumont, Intension and Remission of Forms Robert Pasnau Stephen Dumont has given us a masterful reconstruction of a fascinating fourteenth-century debate that lies at the boundary of metaphysics

More information

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala 1 Forms and Causality in the Phaedo Michael Wiitala Abstract: In Socrates account of his second sailing in the Phaedo, he relates how his search for the causes (αἰτίαι) of why things come to be, pass away,

More information

Categories and Schemata

Categories and Schemata Res Cogitans Volume 1 Issue 1 Article 10 7-26-2010 Categories and Schemata Anthony Schlimgen Creighton University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Part of the

More information

Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie)

Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie) Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie) Born in Ionia (Greece c. 384BC REMEMBER THE MILESIAN FOCUS!!!), supporter of Macedonia father was physician to Philip II of Macedon. Begins studies at Plato

More information

Substances. The Categories

Substances. The Categories 12 Substances s. marc cohen Aristotle divides the things that there are or beings (ta onta) into a number of different categories. He is not always consistent about how many categories there are (ten in

More information

Fill in the crossword puzzle with the correct vocabulary word by reading the clues below.

Fill in the crossword puzzle with the correct vocabulary word by reading the clues below. Name: Date: Fill in the crossword puzzle with the correct vocabulary word by reading the clues below. 1 2 3 4 5 6 7 8 9 10 11 ACROSS 3. The typical way of life of a person. 6. A substance essential to

More information

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring 2014 Russell Marcus Hamilton College Class #4: Aristotle Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy

More information

observation and conceptual interpretation

observation and conceptual interpretation 1 observation and conceptual interpretation Most people will agree that observation and conceptual interpretation constitute two major ways through which human beings engage the world. Questions about

More information

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238. The final chapter of the book is devoted to the question of the epistemological status of holistic pragmatism itself. White thinks of it as a thesis, a statement that may have been originally a very generalized

More information

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong identity theory of truth and the realm of reference 297 The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong WILLIAM FISH AND CYNTHIA MACDONALD In On McDowell s identity conception

More information

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Anca-Gabriela Ghimpu Phd. Candidate UBB, Cluj-Napoca Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Paper contents Introduction: motivation

More information

Aristotle s Categories and Physics

Aristotle s Categories and Physics Aristotle s Categories and Physics G. J. Mattey Winter, 2006 / Philosophy 1 Aristotle as Metaphysician Plato s greatest student was Aristotle (384-322 BC). In metaphysics, Aristotle rejected Plato s theory

More information

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind. Mind Association Proper Names Author(s): John R. Searle Source: Mind, New Series, Vol. 67, No. 266 (Apr., 1958), pp. 166-173 Published by: Oxford University Press on behalf of the Mind Association Stable

More information

Rabinoff, Eve. Published by Northwestern University Press. For additional information about this book

Rabinoff, Eve. Published by Northwestern University Press. For additional information about this book Perception in Aristotle s Ethics Rabinoff, Eve Published by Northwestern University Press Rabinoff, Eve. Perception in Aristotle s Ethics. Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 2018. Project MUSE.,

More information

The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate

The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate The (Other) Meaning of Life: Aristotle on being animate by Rich Cameron Department of Philosophy University of Colorado, Boulder Boulder, Colorado 80309-0232 Richard.J.Cameron@Colorado.EDU Despite evolutionary

More information

The distinction of form and matter stands at the center of Aristotle s metaphysics. Aristotle

The distinction of form and matter stands at the center of Aristotle s metaphysics. Aristotle TWO KINDS OF MATTER IN ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS The distinction of form and matter stands at the center of Aristotle s metaphysics. Aristotle took it that the account we give of the substance or being of

More information

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Perceptions and Hallucinations Perceptions and Hallucinations The Matching View as a Plausible Theory of Perception Romi Rellum, 3673979 BA Thesis Philosophy Utrecht University April 19, 2013 Supervisor: Dr. Menno Lievers Table of contents

More information

From Blood to Flesh: Homonymy, Unity, and Ways of Being in Aristotle

From Blood to Flesh: Homonymy, Unity, and Ways of Being in Aristotle Ancient Philosophy 35 (2015) Mathesis Publications 1 From Blood to Flesh: Homonymy, Unity, and Ways of Being in Aristotle Christopher Frey My topic is the fundamental Aristotelian division between the

More information

Aristotle, Vision, and Communicable Change

Aristotle, Vision, and Communicable Change Aristotle, Vision, and Communicable Change Micah Bailey University of Kansas 1. Introduction In De Anima, Aristotle states: one must understand that the sense is that which is receptive of the sensible

More information

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism THIS PDF FILE FOR PROMOTIONAL USE ONLY 6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism Representationism, 1 as I use the term, says that the phenomenal character of an experience just is its representational

More information

Potentiality in Aristotle s metaphysics 1. Anna Marmodoro. University of Oxford

Potentiality in Aristotle s metaphysics 1. Anna Marmodoro. University of Oxford Potentiality in Aristotle s metaphysics 1 Anna Marmodoro University of Oxford *** This paper was accepted for publication in April 2013 and is forthcoming in K. Engelhard and M. Quante (eds.) The Handbook

More information

Imagination Becomes an Organ of Perception

Imagination Becomes an Organ of Perception Imagination Becomes an Organ of Perception Conversation with Henri Bortoft London, July 14 th, 1999 Claus Otto Scharmer 1 Henri Bortoft is the author of The Wholeness of Nature (1996), the definitive monograph

More information

To link to this article:

To link to this article: This article was downloaded by: [Phil Corkum] On: 14 August 2013, At: 09:59 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,

More information

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality. Fifteen theses on contemporary art Alain Badiou 1. Art is not the sublime descent of the infinite into the finite abjection of the body and sexuality. It is the production of an infinite subjective series

More information

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD 1 ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD Luboš Rojka Introduction Analogy was crucial to Aquinas s philosophical theology, in that it helped the inability of human reason to understand God. Human

More information

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Action Theory for Creativity and Process Action Theory for Creativity and Process Fu Jen Catholic University Bernard C. C. Li Keywords: A. N. Whitehead, Creativity, Process, Action Theory for Philosophy, Abstract The three major assignments for

More information

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC This part of the book deals with the conditions under which judgments can express truths about objects. Here Kant tries to explain how thought about objects given in space and

More information

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic'

The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic' Res Cogitans Volume 2 Issue 1 Article 22 7-30-2011 The Value of Mathematics within the 'Republic' Levi Tenen Lewis & Clark College Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans

More information

Psuche as Substantial Form

Psuche as Substantial Form Psuche as Substantial Form March 24, 2014 1 After mentioning and discussing previous accounts of the soul, Aristotle states in De Anima II.1 his intention to begin his own definition of the soul: "Τὰ μἐν

More information

Aristotle's Psychology First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version)

Aristotle's Psychology First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version) Page 1 of 11 First published Tue Jan 11, 2000; substantive revision Mon Aug 23, 2010; Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (edited version) Aristotle (384 322 BC) was born in Macedon, in what is now northern

More information

Unity in Aristotle s Metaphysics H 6

Unity in Aristotle s Metaphysics H 6 Unity in Aristotle s Metaphysics H 6 EVAN KEELING Corcoran Department of Philosophy University of Virginia Abstract In this essay I argue that the central problem of Aristotle s Metaphysics H (VIII) 6

More information

Aristotle on the Mechanism of Inheritance

Aristotle on the Mechanism of Inheritance Journal of the History of Biology (2006) 39:425 455 Ó Springer 2006 DOI 10.1007/s10739-005-3058-y Aristotle on the Mechanism of Inheritance Department of Philosophy Talbot College The University of Western

More information

In Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill asserts that the principles of

In Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill asserts that the principles of Aporia vol. 28 no. 1 2018 Connections between Mill and Aristotle: Happiness and Pleasure Rose Suneson In Utilitarianism, John Stuart Mill asserts that the principles of utilitarianism are not far-fetched

More information

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture Emily Caddick Bourne 1 and Craig Bourne 2 1University of Hertfordshire Hatfield, Hertfordshire United Kingdom of Great Britain and Northern Ireland 2University

More information

Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8

Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8 Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8 At Republic 583c3-585a7 Socrates develops an argument to show that irrational men misperceive calm as pleasant. Let's call this the "misperception

More information

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Book Review Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Nate Jackson Hugh P. McDonald, Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values. New York: Rodopi, 2011. xxvi + 361 pages. ISBN 978-90-420-3253-8.

More information

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press, Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. Pp. xiii + 331. H/b 50.00. This is a very exciting book that makes some bold claims about the power of medieval logic.

More information

Conference Nutrition and Nutritive Soul in Aristotle and Aristotelianism March 2017 Abstracts. Wednesday 22 March 2017

Conference Nutrition and Nutritive Soul in Aristotle and Aristotelianism March 2017 Abstracts. Wednesday 22 March 2017 Conference Nutrition and Nutritive Soul in Aristotle and Aristotelianism 22-24 March 2017 Abstracts Wednesday 22 March 2017 James Lennox The most natural of functions : reproduction as a nutritive function

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

Aristotle's Metaphysics

Aristotle's Metaphysics Aristotle's Metaphysics Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy The first major work in the history of philosophy to bear the title Metaphysics was the treatise by Aristotle that we have come to know by that

More information

LYCEUM A Publication of the Philosophy Department Saint Anselm College

LYCEUM A Publication of the Philosophy Department Saint Anselm College Volume IX, No. 2 Spring 2008 LYCEUM Aristotle s Form of the Species as Relation Theodore Di Maria, Jr. What Was Hume s Problem about Personal Identity in the Appendix? Megan Blomfield The Effect of Luck

More information

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts Normativity and Purposiveness What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts of a triangle and the colour green, and our cognition of birch trees and horseshoe crabs

More information

Thomas Coleman Tinnitus Miracle Review (ebook PDF & Download System Program)

Thomas Coleman Tinnitus Miracle Review (ebook PDF & Download System Program) Thomas Coleman Tinnitus Miracle Review (ebook PDF & Download System Program) How to get rid of Tinnitus? Many people are suffering from tinnitus and not able to get rid of this problem permanently. Everyone

More information

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception 1/6 The Anticipations of Perception The Anticipations of Perception treats the schematization of the category of quality and is the second of Kant s mathematical principles. As with the Axioms of Intuition,

More information

Chapter 1. The Power of Names NAMING IS NOT LIKE COUNTING

Chapter 1. The Power of Names NAMING IS NOT LIKE COUNTING Chapter 1 The Power of Names One of the primary sources of sophistical reasoning is the equivocation between different significations of the same word or phrase within an argument. Aristotle believes that

More information

Homo Ecologicus and Homo Economicus

Homo Ecologicus and Homo Economicus 1: Ho m o Ec o l o g i c u s, Ho m o Ec o n o m i c u s, Ho m o Po e t i c u s Homo Ecologicus and Homo Economicus Ecology: the science of the economy of animals and plants. Oxford English Dictionary Ecological

More information

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments. Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring 2014 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #3 - Plato s Platonism Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction

More information

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic 1 Reply to Stalnaker Timothy Williamson In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic as Metaphysics between contingentism in modal metaphysics and the use of

More information

ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE

ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE AN EXAMINATION OF ARISTOTLE'S CONCEPT OF MATIER IN THE CONTEXT OF CHANGE By HORATIO ION BOT, B.A. A Thesis Submitted to the School of Graduate Studies

More information

Notes on Aristotle s Topics, Book III

Notes on Aristotle s Topics, Book III Notes on Aristotle s Topics, Book III Daniel Bonevac, The University of Texas at Austin January 28, 2014 In Book III of the Topics, Aristotle focuses on practical arguments, that is to say, arguments within

More information

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology Markku Keinänen University of Tampere [Draft, please do not quote without permission] ABSTRACT. According to Lowe s Four-Category

More information

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts Tim Black California State University, Northridge Spring 2004 I. PRELIMINARIES a. Last time, we were

More information

Aristotle. Motion being eternal, the first mover, if there is but one, will be eternal also. Aristotle

Aristotle. Motion being eternal, the first mover, if there is but one, will be eternal also. Aristotle 4 Aristotle Motion being eternal, the first mover, if there is but one, will be eternal also. Aristotle Plato s most distinguished pupil was Aristotle (384 322 B.C.E.), on whom Plato had a tremendous influence.

More information

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL CONTINGENCY AND TIME Gal YEHEZKEL ABSTRACT: In this article I offer an explanation of the need for contingent propositions in language. I argue that contingent propositions are required if and only if

More information

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: B. C. 3.

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as the Stagirite. 2. Dates: B. C. 3. - 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: 384-322 B. C. 3. Student at Plato's Academy for twenty years 4. Left Athens at

More information

Aristotle and Human Nature

Aristotle and Human Nature Aristotle and Human Nature Nicomachean Ethics (translated by W. D. Ross ) Book 1 Chapter 1 EVERY art and every inquiry, and similarly every action and pursuit, is thought to aim at some good; and for this

More information

ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME. Irena Cronin

ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME. Irena Cronin ON ARISTOTELIAN UNIVERSALS AND INDIVIDUALS: THE VINK THAT IS IN BODY AND MAY BE IN ME Irena Cronin Abstract G. E. L. Owen, in his influential article Inherence, talks of vink, a name he has created for

More information

Accidental Beings in Aristotle s Ontology 1

Accidental Beings in Aristotle s Ontology 1 Accidental Beings in Aristotle s Ontology 1 S. Marc Cohen Aristotle, as is well known, proposes an ontology of substances and accidents. Substances, such as a man or a horse, are the basic, independent,

More information

Guidelines for Manuscript Preparation for Advanced Biomedical Engineering

Guidelines for Manuscript Preparation for Advanced Biomedical Engineering Guidelines for Manuscript Preparation for Advanced Biomedical Engineering May, 2012. Editorial Board of Advanced Biomedical Engineering Japanese Society for Medical and Biological Engineering 1. Introduction

More information

Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts

Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts http://www.marxists.org/archive/marx/works/1844/epm/1st.htm We shall start out from a present-day economic fact. The worker becomes poorer the

More information

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford

WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College, Oxford Published in in Real Metaphysics, ed. by H. Lillehammer and G. Rodriguez-Pereyra, Routledge, 2003, pp. 184-195. WHAT IS WRONG WITH THE RELATIONAL THEORY OF CHANGE? Gonzalo Rodriguez-Pereyra Hertford College,

More information

Are Potency and Actuality Compatible in Aristotle?

Are Potency and Actuality Compatible in Aristotle? Are Potency and Actuality Compatible in Aristotle? Abstract: The belief that Aristotle opposes potency (dunamis) to actuality (energeia or entelecheia) has gone untested. This essay defines and distinguishes

More information

LANGUAGE THROUGH THE LENS OF HERACLITUS'S LOGOS

LANGUAGE THROUGH THE LENS OF HERACLITUS'S LOGOS LANGUAGE THROUGH THE LENS OF HERACLITUS'S LOGOS NATASHA WILTZ ABSTRACT This paper deals with Heraclitus s understanding of Logos and how his work can help us understand various components of language:

More information

Monadology and Music 2: Leibniz s Demon

Monadology and Music 2: Leibniz s Demon Monadology and Music 2: Leibniz s Demon Soshichi Uchii (Kyoto University, Emeritus) Abstract Drawing on my previous paper Monadology and Music (Uchii 2015), I will further pursue the analogy between Monadology

More information

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal Aristotle 384-322 The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal Pupil of Plato, Preceptor of Alexander 150 books, 1/5 known Stagira 367-347 Academy 347 Atarneus 343-335 Mieza 335-322 Lyceum Chalcis

More information