Continental philosophies of the social sciences David Teira

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Continental philosophies of the social sciences David Teira"

Transcription

1 Continental philosophies of the social sciences David Teira 1. Introduction In my view, there is no such thing as a continental philosophy of the social sciences. There is, at least, no consensual definition of what is precisely continental in any philosophical approach. 1 Besides, there are many approaches in the philosophy of the social sciences that are often qualified as continental, but there is no obvious connection between them. The most systematic attempt so far to find one is Yvonne Sherratt s (2006) monograph, where continental approaches would be appraised as different branches of the Humanist tradition. According to Sherratt, philosophers in this tradition draw on the ideas and arguments of the ancient Greek and Roman thinkers, since they understand philosophy as an accumulative endeavor, where the past is a continuous source of wisdom. Unlike empiricist philosophers in the analytic tradition, humanists see the world as an intrinsically purpose-laden, ethically, aesthetically, and spiritually valuable entity. However, once you adopt such a broad definition in order to encompass such different thinkers as Marx, Nietzsche, Heidegger or Foucault, it seems difficult not to see humanistic traits in analytic philosophers as well. Moreover, when it comes to the philosophical study of actual social sciences, it is not clear whether adopting a humanistic stance makes, as such, any difference in the analysis: as we will see below, the arguments of the continental philosophers discussed here do not presuppose a particular commitment with, e.g., ideas from classical Antiquity. Certain Greeks named those who did not speak their language Barbarians, but it was never clear who counted as a proper speaker of Greek. Similarly, there is no clear empirical division differentiating continental authors from philosophers of any other kind. I will, therefore, focus on a few paradigmatic instances of continental philosophies of the social sciences, discussing each one separately without any attempt to find a common thread. 2 The following three sections will deal, in this order, with Marxism, phenomenology and, more briefly, Foucault. I have chosen these three approaches for just one reason: they have had a real influence on how social research has been conducted throughout the 20 th century. 3 There have been Marxist, phenomenological and Foucauldian social scientists and they can claim that their research methods are effectively grounded in philosophical principles that analytically-oriented social 1 Nonetheless, there have been several attempts at defining this dichotomy: for a sample, see D Agostini 1997, Sáez Rueda 2002 and Piercey I have received comments and suggestions from competent scholars on each part of the paper, which I have acknowledged at the beginning of each of section. I am also grateful to Luis Arenas, Francesco Guala, Eric Schliesser, William Outhwaite and Jesús Zamora for their observations on the entire piece. Bruno Maltras provided much help in the analysis of the Social Sciences Citation Index. 3 In my view, other authors such as Pierre Bourdieu or Clifford Geertz would have equally deserved a section in this survey, even if philosophers have not paid them much attention so far. It is clearly objectionable that I have not included a line on either Gadamer or, especially, Ricoeur. This latter certainly had important views on the social sciences that deserve consideration, but I could not trace a direct connec on with the work of prominent social scien sts I do not claim it does not exist: I am just making my own limitations explicit. Gender-oriented research has had an impact on the social sciences (e.g., feminist economics), but the underlying philosophy is not necessarily continental. Given the usual time constraints, I have opted for the three approaches that seem to be at least equally popular among philosophers and social scientists. For a more extensive consideration of other continental approaches, see Turner and Risjord 2007.

2 scientists do not share. Next, I will focus on positive guidelines implemented in current social sciences rather than on principled philosophical discussions about how they should be cultivated. In the case of Marxism, this implies an assessment of major contributions in several fields, whereas phenomenologists or Foucauldians have so far been a dissenting minority with minor professional impact. I follow the (mostly) analytically-minded habit of working with case studies where methodologies are actually implemented. The aim of this chapter is just to show the relevance of continental ideas for certain research agendas, focusing more on their efficacy in actual scientific practices than on their internal philosophical merits. This judgment is admittedly analytically inspired, but I hope not entirely unfair to the continental accomplishments. My own understanding of continental philosophy is partial and biased or, if you prefer, situated. I was exposed to these philosophies when I studied philosophy as an undergraduate in Spain and I do not have original views on any of the authors I will deal with: I draw on standard interpretations, which are not always consensual, and I will make my sources explicit at every step. 4 The first section is, then, about Marxism. It surveys its typical explanatory patterns (functionalism and methodological individualism) on particular issues in economics (value theory) and history (the connection between productive forces and relations of production). I will also discuss value judgments in the Marxist tradition, with a brief overview of the positivism dispute. In the second section, on phenomenology, I will present Husserl s views on the connection between philosophy and the social sciences of his times, discussing their implications for the assessment of cultural anthropology. I will also deal with Schütz s contributions to sociology and how they contributed to the articulation of ethnomethodology, the most accomplished phenomenological research paradigm so far. A quick discussion of the embodied approach to cognitive science closes the section. In the third and final section, I will explore Foucault s initial appraisal of the social sciences, that I take to generalize his experience with psychology. I also consider his more mature views on governmentality, trying to explain the success of this concept in current research across several fields. Each section can be read independently. To many, my final conclusion will probably state the obvious. Marxism is of more interest today for philosophers than for social scientists which is probably not a good thing for the former, since this usually implies neglecting the latter s more recent contributions. So far, phenomenology has only achieved success in actual social research today at the cost of dispensing with many of its central assumptions. Foucauldian-inspired research, finally, influential as it is, is based on minimal philosophical presuppositions, but these presuppositions are restrictive enough to limit the kind of analyses that are acceptable. By its own construction, it cannot aspire to become a mainstream paradigm. Obviously, none of this partial conclusion precludes that some other continental philosopher may succeed in inspiring social scientists in the near future, but I personally would not bet on anybody s success at this point. 4 I avoid discussing primary sources, for the sake of brevity. The secondary literature I cite is never exhaustive, but rather, at most, introductory. Following these leads, I hope the interested reader will easily find more complete information.

3 2. Marxism It is impossible to cover in just one section the many issues of interest for the philosophy of the social sciences arising within the Marxist tradition. 5 To a great extent, this tradition hinges on the interpretation of the works of Marx and Engels, but there is no agreement about how we should read them. The circumstances in which they were published or edited have significantly complicated (almost up to today) our understanding of many central points in Marxian thought. In addition, interpretative and political disagreement often came hand in hand: communist parties all over the world have justified their strategies in terms of fidelity to the true thought of Marx and Engels, generating a self-serving literature, still virtually inexhaustible. 6 Nonetheless, its practical relevance certainly helps to explain the impact of Marxism in the social sciences of the 20 th century. In the USSR, and then in many other communist regimes, Marxism was enforced among the social scientists by the ruling party, according to their interpretation of choice. In the Western world, Marxism could be adopted by a social scientist for purely intellectual considerations, but a certain degree of commitment with one or another communist party was not rare and if there was none, this circumstance was often denigrated. 7 We may well wonder how relevant Marxian thought would have been, had there been no USSR. Perhaps, Marx s intellectual influence would have been more like, say, Comte s or Spencer s and, regarding politics, no greater than any other utopian socialist of his times. But, in point of fact, Marxism was either the dominant approach or one of the main contenders in many social sciences during the second half of the 20 th century, playing a major role in the methodological literature of those disciplines. 8 By the same token, after the fall of the USSR, the philosophical discussion of Marxist social science has become increasingly rare, at least in mainstream philosophy journals in the English-speaking world. The aim of this section is to survey the main issues in the methodological discussion around Marxian social sciences, comparing the Marxist approach, broadly conceived, with the mainstream methodological tenets in analytical social science. We owe this comparison mostly to Gerald Cohen, John Roemer, Jon Elster and the work of the September group in the 1980s and early 1990s, when the discussion stalled, with no major developments since then. 9 We will then briefly consider the functional 5 I am grateful to Andy Denis, Adolfo García de la Sienra, Andrew Levine, Daniel Little and Félix Ovejero for their comments on this section. They made their disagreement explicit at many points, so the responsibility here (more than in any other section) remains mine. 6 My own understanding of the Marxist tradition owes much to Kolakowski Among Spanish Marxists, I am indebted to Sacristán 1983 and Bueno Walker & Gray 2007 and Glaser & Walker 2007 provide updated overviews. Carver 2003 and Little 2007 provide insightful presentations of this section s topic. 7 E.g., the so-called professorial socialists (Kathedersozialisten) affiliated with the German Verein für Socialpolitik in the late 19th century 8 A good overview is provided by the entries indexed under Marxism in the 1968 edition of the International Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (Sills 1968) and the 2001 International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences (Smelser and Baltes 2001). 9 A quick overview and a basic reference list is provided in van Parijs I am clearly aware that taking sides with analytical Marxism, as I do in this section, is clearly questionable for most other Marxists, so the reader should be warned of my partiality. Certainly, it is historically misleading to present the Marxist tradition solely from the standpoint of its analytical reconstruction, which is only thirty years old and never played a significant role in Marxism as a social movement. Nonetheless, for most philosophers of the social sciences, analytical Marxism seems to be the standard approach to the discussion of Marx.

4 explanation, the controversy around the Marxian theory of value (in economics), methodological individualism, the central tenets of historical materialism and, to conclude, the treatment of normative issues in the Marxist tradition. According to Elster (1985 p. 4), the main Marxist contribution to the methodology of the social sciences (analytically reconstructed) would have been the causal explanation of aggregate phenomena in terms of the individual actions that go into them: pursuing their individual goals, the actors bring about an unintended outcome, namely by making erroneous assumptions about one another. These unintended consequences could be beneficial (or not) to the actors. In Elster s view, Marx often considered these benefits as an explanation of the actions that brought them about. Hempel, Nagel and other philosophers of scientific explanation usually consider such a functional approach to explanation faulty if no causal connection is shown between the actions and their consequences. Otherwise, it would be difficult to understand how an event in the future (the benefits) can generate an individual action without the actor anticipating it. This is the standard appraisal of Marxian functional explanations among analytical philosophers of the social sciences. However, Marx was part of a broad philosophical tradition in which teleological explanations of social processes were considered acceptable. 10 For German idealists from Kant onwards, History could only be appraised through conceptual analysis, where concepts were somehow objectively inscribed in the social processes under discussion. Such concepts had a logic of their own: Marx took his own version from Hegel and this was dialectics. It presided over social aggregates (e.g., classes), guiding their development independently of the intentions of their individual members, who nonetheless benefitted from (or suffered) the consequences. Despite numerous attempts, there is still no consensual elucidation of Marxian dialectics, at least in the philosophy of the social sciences. 11 At most, the style of conceptual analysis cultivated by Marx in his economic writings has been somewhat clarified in terms of abstraction and idealization, but without much impact on actual social research. 12 Indeed, many methodological debates in the Marxist social sciences can be interpreted in the light of the philosophical inspiration (roughly speaking, analytic or continental) of each side. One prominent example is the controversy about the Marxian theory of value, which has been going on for more than a century now. 13 Broadly speaking, the value of an economic good is the amount of homogenized socially necessary labour time it takes to produce it in a given social setting. For Marx, the value of a good would explain its exchange price. Yet, in Marxian economics this explanation may take different forms, deserving more or less attention depending on the philosophical taste of the reader. In many of his economic writings, Marx articulates the discussion of value Critical assessments of analytical Marxism can be found in Roberts 1996, Levine 2003, Tarrit 2006 and Veneziani On the sources of teleological explanations in social research, see Turner The connection between Marx and Hegel regarding this point was widely discussed in the 1960s, mostly around the works of Althusser: Lewis 2005 provides an introduction to these debates, even if it is partial to Althusser. 11 For an overview, see Wilde Philosophical discussions of the role of dialectics in Marxian methodology in the light of contemporary philosophy of science are presented in Little 1986 and Walker On idealization and Marxian economics, see Nowak 1980, De Marchi & Hamminga 1994 and García de la Sienra Two overviews from a different perspective can be found in the latest edition of The New Palgrave: Foley and Duncan 2008 (constructive perspective) and Roemer 2008 (critical perspective).

5 drawing on Aristotelian (e.g., form/substance) and Hegelian (e.g., essence/appearance) categories, whose correct interpretation requires a certain degree of competence in the History of Greek and German philosophy. 14 Through these categories Marx would have articulated a general view of social life hinging on productive activities e.g, Gould Value theory would illuminate how production is truly organized in capitalist societies and the explanation of market prices it yields allowed Marx to establish a conceptual connection between such disparate phenomena as, e.g., economic exploitation, class division or the future collapse of capitalism. The philosophical categories articulating this worldview are no longer part of the standard vocabulary of most social sciences, but many Marxian philosophers appraising economics in the continental tradition (e.g., Negri, Žižek) still rely on their own version of these concepts. Here, philosophy and the social sciences parted ways several decades ago. But Marx s theory of value also owed a great deal to classical political economy, which sought to establish a concrete explanatory relation between values and prices. Marx tried to show that, in capitalist markets, commodities tend to be exchanged in a certain proportion to the labour time they embody. Marx s key insight is that the profit earned in the exchange by the owner of the means of production of a good arise from the embodied labour contributed by the worker without payment. This surplus value measured the exploitation of the worker, independently of her own intentional economic choices. Marx attempted to state this proportion in algebraic terms, giving rise to the socalled transformation problem: it has been argued (Roemer 2008) that Marx s equations are either unnecessary for calculating prices or internally contradictory. The transformation problem created a methodological dilemma among economists. Some argued that the labour theory of value should be abandoned for some other economic approach to price calculation (usually, neoclassical demand theory). At this point, this seems to be the choice of the majority within the profession. Others have tried to reform the equations, preserving the concept of value while arguing that its main role within the theory is the analysis of exploitation rather than exchange prices. More recently, John Roemer has restated the key Marxian normative insights about exploitation, using standard analytic tools in neoclassical economics, i.e., modeling the agents interaction in a way that makes their individual choices explicit. I.e., their micro-foundations. 15 Philosophers of the social sciences have appraised the dilemma created by the transformation problem from various perspectives. To name just a couple within the analytic tradition, on one hand, we find a number of set-theoretic (structuralist) reconstructions of the Marxian theory of value. 16 Here the concept of value is either epistemically justified in terms of the role it plays in the architecture of the theory or, alternatively, grounded in formal analyses of the measurement conditions of Marxian value. However, these reconstructions show that it is possible to clarify, in certain respects, the conceptual articulation of the theory, despite the transformation problem, but they do not provide substantive reasons to accept it. Analytical Marxists, such as Roemer or Elster, argue instead that there are, rather, positive reasons to reject it: whatever its aim, in most formulations, the concept of value is methodologically obscure, because it does not involve any consideration of the individual choices of the economic agents. For instance, it has been argued that Marx was interested in abstract 14 See Wood My own understanding of this connection is shaped by Rockmore 2002 (regarding Hegel) and Arteta 1993 (regarding Aristotle). 15 Again, see the references in Duncan 2008 and Roemer See García de la Sienra 1992 and Álvarez 1991 for an overview.

6 labour time, rather than in imputating concrete labour time to different commodities. But shouldn t the abstract be the aggregate of concrete instances? Once you incorporate micro-foundations into Marxian economics, you can either analyze exploitation or calculate prices without Marxian values. 17 The point of contention illustrated by this case is whether the social sciences should adhere to methodological individualism or not in Elster s minimal characterization: whether collective actions should be explained in terms of the desires and beliefs that enter into the motivation of the individuals participating in them. Marxists and other continental philosophers of the social sciences usually question such an assumption, whereas neoclassical economists and analytically oriented philosophers usually defend it. 18 Notice that this is more a conceptual than an empirical issue. The analysis of prices in neoclassical economics relies on individual choices as explained by utility theory. But for many decades this latter was accepted with hardly any positive experimental evidence, just as Marxian values were. Again, the debate on methodological individualism can be appraised at two different levels. On one hand, it can be conducted as a conceptual discussion about social ontology: should we take individuals or, rather, groups of individuals (classes, for Marx) as the basic units of social analysis? Originally, this was mostly a controversy on the realism of the assumptions of each theory: on the neoclassical side, did utility theory represent any individual psychological process? On the Marxist side, how could class analysis account for individual choices? The debate was initiated by the Austrian school in the late 19 th century and was somehow closed in the 1960s with the gradual turn to instrumentalist justifications of utility theory by neoclassical economists: as long as any economic theory provides good statistical predictions, we can dispense with the realism of its assumptions. 19 Whether neoclassical theories ever yielded such a good prediction remains a controversial issue, but their supporters were, at least, more eager to adopt econometric techniques than Marxian economics. For many Marxists, statistical analyses reduced social entities to aggregates of individual data, which was considered to be contradictory to the reality of classes. 20 This is, perhaps, why Marxism never really competed against neoclassical economics with predictions. However, most varieties of Marxism remained firmly committed to realism and resisted individualistic reductions of social aggregates. 21 On the other hand, it can be posed as a reflection on the explanatory virtues of the analytical tools applied by neoclassical economics, namely decision and game theory. In these latter, it seems possible to interpret expected utility as a combined expression of the beliefs of the agents about the probability of the alternatives considered and their desires, i.e., the utility resulting from each of these alternatives. Hence, we may explain in principle the aggregated effects of individual decisions on intentional grounds. However, such an interpretation is often challenged on various grounds: first, expected utility theory can be applied to group agents, where there is a less clear intentional basis, and second, explanatory reductions to individual decisions are often theoretically 17 The standard references here are Roemer 1981 and A survey of economic approaches to the individual agent can be found in Davis My own appraisal owes a great deal to García-Bermejo The final stage of these debates, hinging on Milton Friedman s 1953 methodological piece, is surveyed in Mäki For an initial exploration, see Hertz 2000 and Mespoulet We still find remnants of this debate in the objections of the so-called critical realists against mainstream economics. On critical realism and Marxism, see Bhaskar 1998, Lawson 2003, Baskhar and Callinicos 2007

7 unreachable and, even in game theory, the analyses of individual choices may depend on macro-features. Despite various attempts at a more precise definition of methodological individualism, there is no consensus yet and it is mostly defended on heuristic grounds: the formal analysis of individual decisions has led to fruitful theoretical results in many different social domains. However, holism in the Marxist tradition is no less difficult to define and, as of today, there are no consensual formal results providing a general framework for social analysis. 22 History and economics were the two main disciplines in the Marxist social sciences. The central claim of the methodology of historical materialism is the connection between productive forces and relations of production, which we shall explore here following Gerald Cohen s (2000) reconstruction once again, the best bridge, so far, between the analytical and the continental Marx. In Cohen s interpretation, the productive forces are, namely, the means of production (tools, raw materials, etc.) and labour-power. In turn, the relations of production are defined namely in terms of the property relations of the producers with regard to the means of production and their own labour-power (e.g., a capitalist worker owns the latter, but not the former), with some additional provisos. Marx s major claim is that, throughout history, the relations of production first correspond to the productive forces and then enter into a contradiction with them. The interpretation of this claim is controversial. In Cohen s view, the correspondence means that certain relations of production are optimal for the development of certain productive forces and this is why the former appear and take hold. When they are no longer optimal, the relations of production change. Hence, there is a functional connection by which the development of the productive forces explain the relations of production. For Marx, this functional link allows us to explain the transition between the different modes of production that feature in human history. Historical materialism thus affirms the (explanatory) primacy of the productive forces. However, as we already mentioned regarding mechanisms, Marxian analyses usually do not provide all the necessary details for a coherent functional interpretation along the lines suggested by Cohen. Nonetheless, throughout the 20 th century, Marxist historians applied this approach without much regard for explanatory patterns as such. The main point of contention was, instead, how to assess the autonomy of individuals in a materialist perspective. For instance, the so-called structural accounts of Marx prevailing in the 1960s granted them little autonomy, putting all the explanatory weight on the teleological connection between productive forces and relations of productions. This line was widely contested (e.g., the Althusser-Thompson-Anderson debate: Lewis 2005), but Marxist historiography never reached a clear methodological consensus about the role of individual choices in explanation. 23 It is interesting to notice that a somewhat clearer view of functional explanations was developed by an intellectual offspring of Marxism in anthropology, the cultural materialism school (Bueno 1978). Marvin Harris (1999) argued, for instance, that individuals select infrastructural innovations depending on their estimations of the costs and benefits for them, making the collective adoption of those novelties that increase the efficiency of their productive and reproductive processes more likely. This principle seems particularly plausible in the analysis of populations constrained in well-defined ecological niches, where the effects of certain cultural traits on the production and consumption of calories can somehow be measured. In these niches, individual choices about these traits can result 22 Kincaid 2008 provides a quick overview. For a more extensive analysis, see Turner and Risjord 2007, pp For a recent sympathetic overview of Marxist historiography, see Blackledge 2006.

8 in the niches either sustaining or exhausting their carrying capacity, thus explaining why such traits survive or disappear. Even the best examples of such anthropological analyses are, nonetheless, controversial (e.g., Dawson 2002), but there is at least an explicit principle linking infrastructural changes and their cultural effects through individual behavior. An implicit question in this methodological dispute is how autonomous individuals were in making their choices. This was a normative issue of foremost relevance, 24 and it often appeared in the debate on the practical implications of Marxist theories or the unity of theory and praxis, to use a more traditional statement of the problem among Western Marxists. Marx was, indeed, as much an activist as a theorist and it often seems as if his arguments aimed to both describe and transform capitalist societies. How his arguments would achieve such a transformation was, again, open to dispute. Those who more explicitly denied their normative dimension (e.g., Lenin and the Soviet tradition) usually assumed that communist activists were just acting in accordance to the laws of history. Marxian theories would provide communist parties with the tools to properly interpret these laws and act accordingly. In this approach, Marxists would act instrumentally: given that communism is the objective end of History, and they want it to arrive, their political activity should just find the proper means to bring it about sooner than later. However, there have been Marxists, even if only a minority, who defended a more explicitly normative version of communist politics (e.g., Rosa Luxemburg or Antonio Gramsci). The most philosophically influential among them come from the Frankfurt School, namely Adorno and Horkheimer, on one hand, and Jürgen Habermas, still active today. Unlike other Marxists, they not only confronted their own tradition, but presented their case in open dialogue with Anglo-American philosophers. A good case in point, regarding the philosophy of the social sciences, is the so-called positivism dispute in the 1960s (Adorno 1976), bringing the Frankfurt school face to face with Popper and other critical rationalists. We will shortly consider here two crucial points in this debate, presenting Habermas current stance regarding both. The positivism in dispute in this controversy can be traced to the definition of economics presented by Lionel Robbins in An Essay on the Nature and Significance of Economic Science (1932): the unity of subject of the discipline lay in the forms assumed by human behavior in disposing of scarce means. If the means are scarce and the agent must choose a particular combination of them in order to achieve her goals, the economist can provide a mathematical analysis of the degree of achievement (say, satisfaction) reported by each combination. It will be (instrumentally) rational for the agent to choose the combination of means that maximizes the achievement of her goals. About the ends as such, Robbins adopted a skeptic stance: these were value judgments and, in case of ultimate disagreement about them, we can only fight to solve the conflict. In The Poverty of Historicism (1957), Popper added a corollary about what sort of political intervention the economist could advise to this view. For instance, the statistical analysis of demand theory could just ground what Popper called piecemeal social engineering. Testing how much a model deviates from empirical data predictions provides guidance for policy-makers, inspiring their reforms in the model. But since the model deals with just a few variables, usually complicated to isolate and measure, its application can only yield partial reforms. Popper claimed, against Marxism, that there 24 But take into account that the dichotomy between facts and values was rarely acknowledged as such within Marxism: see Wood 1991 and Cohen 1996 about the controversial status of moral philosophy within Marxism. The standard study of Marxian ethics is Kamenka 1969.

9 were no general laws in History and any global transformation of society based on such laws was utopian. In sum, for the positivist social scientist, the social scientists are neither morally committed to the transformation of society (or to any other normative position) as a result or their research. His theoretical contribution to this enterprise is necessarily restricted to the analysis of means for partial reforms. This instrumental view of science and rationality was widely contested in Frankfurt, with a view to criticize the theoretical approaches to society developed both in the capitalist and the communist world. Up until de 1970s, Adorno and Horkheimer s Dialectic of Enlightment (1972) provided the most influential statement of this position. But nowadays the discussion hinges, rather, on Jürgen Habermas restatement, perhaps because Habermas view has been elaborated incorporating many insights from analytic philosophy. 25 For Habermas, the pragmatics of linguistic communication reveals a use of language that is irreducible to instrumental rationality: speech acts commit the speakers to achieve mutual understanding, evaluating the epistemic claims that each of them undertake through their utterances. Communication requires the speaker to justify those claims for the sake of mutual understanding, creating a web of inferential commitments where words acquire their meaning. Social norms would be grounded on such communicative demand for mutual accountability, constituting publicly shared reasons for action. Instrumental rationality would only appear derivatively, against a background of shared meanings and social norms. In Habermas view, the social sciences should accept this irreducibly moral setting of our social life and appraise individual interactions taking their communicative dimension into account. Marx would have missed this in making the instrumental rationality of labour the key to any social analysis. The normative mission of the social sciences would be to contribute to the critical elucidation of the communicative practices that sustain our social life, as psychoanalysis did, paradigmatically. The social scientist should be morally committed to the advancement of democracy, understood as the regime that best promotes such communicative practices. It is open to discussion whether there is much left of Marx in Habermas, leaving aside the intellectual genealogy. Nonetheless, today Habermas provides the more articulated philosophical account of the connection between facts and values in the social sciences, a connection that the Marxist tradition struggled for decades to make (against positivism) without much intellectual success. What is left, then, of Marxism for the philosopher of the social sciences? In 1986, Jon Elster closed An Introduction to Karl Marx with a chapter entitled What is living and what is dead in the philosophy of Marx? He listed six items that were still worth considering: dialectics and the theories of alienation, exploitation, class consciousness, ideology and technical change. In the last two decades, none of these topics, as such, has received major attention in any social science, at least if we judge according to informal searches conducted in the Social Sciences Citation Index (SSCI). Nonetheless, this does not imply that Marxism, either in its traditional guise or in its analytical reconstruction, lacks interesting developments: e.g., class analysis is certainly alive (Wright 2005) and there are very good Marxist historians still at work (e.g., Perry Anderson or Robert Brenner). The moral issues involved in exploitation and alienation 25 For the purpose of this analysis, I will mostly follow Heath I have taken some insights about Habermas view of the social sciences from Bouchindomme Key references for the reassessment of Marxism by Habermas are his works of 1971, 1976 and 1988.

10 are still discussed in philosophy, but, as happens with Habermas, dissociated from most claims traditionally linked to Marx and the Marxist tradition. Among the topics that Elster considered dead were all those discussed in this brief review, namely: scientific socialism, functionalism, Marxist economics and the theory of productive forces and relations of production. Another informal look at the SSCI provides evidence that none of these items are being widely discussed. Philosophers re-reading Marx today are motivated more by his moral intuitions than by the scientific cogency of the concepts he used to elaborate them. For these approaches, current debates in the mainstream social sciences apparently do not seem very relevant. 26 Habermas went further than anyone within the Marxian tradition in keeping the connection between social research and philosophy up to date, but only until the 1970s: the theories he discussed, e.g., in sociology or psychology, are not cutting-edge research paradigms anymore. Marx and Marxism will always be relevant for the philosopher who cares for the development of the social sciences and the Marxian tradition contributed to articulate many of our ongoing debates (e.g., explanation) in the field. However, if we want the philosophy of the social sciences to be driven by actual research in the target disciplines, it seems as if Marxism will not be a progressive research program to be considered in the 21 st century Phenomenology Phenomenology is one of the major philosophical trends of the 20 th century, with an impact only second to Marxism or analytic philosophy. 28 There is a phenomenological approach to most topics in philosophy and the social sciences are no exception: there is indeed, a phenomenology of the social sciences, with its own conferences and journals. 29 However, it seems as if the impact of this approach on actual research is minor, at least insofar as the Social Citation Index can capture it. And, so far, there has been no major debate confronting phenomenology with other philosophical accounts of social research. 30 In my view, this can be (partially) explained by considering, on one hand, Husserl s normative position regarding the social sciences. And, on the other hand, by how phenomenological claims are, so to speak, diluted when social scientists incorporate them into their theorizing. Let me first summarily present how Husserl introduced phenomenology in opposition to certain trends in the Geisteswisseschaften of his time. 31 I will then discuss the most accomplished attempt so far to transform phenomenology into an actual philosophy of the social realm, namely Alfred Schütz s attempt, and the impact of his ideas on ethnomethodology as of today, the most successful phenomenological venture in the social sciences. I will quickly address an 26 This is, at least, how I read Carver Obviously, some think otherwise: e.g. Gamble Again, this section hinges on a particular approach to the philosophy of the social sciences, but there are alternative accounts in which Marxism fares somewhat better: see, for instance, Little 2003, pp I am grateful to Havi Carel, Jesús Díaz, Lester Embree, Pablo Hermida and Javier San Martín for their comments on this section. 29 For a short hisstory of The Society for Phenomenology and the Human Sciences (and its journal Human Studies) see [Accessed on January 7th, 2010]. For a short overview of the phenomenological philosophy of the social sciences with an introductory bibliography, see Embree 1997, or for more extensive analyses, Fay 2003 and Outhwaite Nonetheless, there have been significant exchanges that did not attract the attention of either philosophers or social scientists: e.g., between Schütz and Talcott Parsons on social action, as documented in Grathoff Lester Embree (personal communication) reminded me that the Geisteswissenschaften (human sciences), going back to Dilthey, included the historical sciences and were, thus, broader than the social sciences. Whereas Husserl was concerned with the former, Schütz would focus instead on the latter.

11 emerging interdisciplinary paradigm that vindicates part of the phenomenological legacy, the so-called embodied cognitive sciences. A brief recapitulative discussion will close this section. 32 In his landmark Philosophy as Rigorous Science (Husserl 1965), Husserl articulated phenomenology in opposition to a couple of alternative paradigms in philosophy emerging from positive research in psychology and history. 33 Experimental psychophysiology, as developed by W. Wundt, aimed at establishing a natural science of consciousness, in which mental phenomena would stem from physical events accessible in the laboratory. Historical research in multiple domains accumulated more and more evidence about the particularity of each manifestation of our social life. Historicism would make sense of such empirical diversity with classifications aimed at understanding their particularity, without normative considerations about their validity. According to Husserl, both naturalism and historicism promoted epistemic relativism, since there are no absolute grounds for scientific knowledge in any of them, just the particular psychological or social facts established by positive research on either our epistemic capabilities or what a concrete group called science. Husserl constructed his phenomenology in contrast to such kinds of relativism. Let us briefly examine the case he made in the Second Book of his Ideas Pertaining to a Pure Phenomenology (Husserl 1989). Husserl argued here that positive science presupposed a particular connection between mind and world that philosophy should elucidate. What scientists take as purely external events, for the sake of their own research, are always intentionally appraised, i.e., they appear in a particular aspect of our consciousness (they are perceived, remembered, expected ). Once we appraise the world in its connection with our subjectivity, we can discern an invariable and universal element in these multiple presentations of an object. Following Husserl, we can isolate and classify these elements according to their internal relations. Our world can thus be divided into different regions according to these universal and invariable structures. The sciences will study their empirical manifestations. Husserl explained our access to these a priori structures through a set of concepts such as eidetic reduction, epoché, etc. whose precise interpretation is still debated by the different schools of phenomenology. 34 Putting aside here how we access the a priori, we should notice that Husserl distinguished three different types of a priori structures, depending on how the object appears in our consciousness. Each type corresponds to a particular mode of scientific inquiry. The natural sciences deal with the first type, where objects appear individuated by their temporal and spatial characteristics together with causal links to other entities, i.e., as material things. Psychology deals with the second type of a priori essences, those that appear in animal bodies exhibiting some sort of subjectivity, a kind of embodied first person perspective that is irreducible to psychophysical connections. Husserl was ambiguous enough to capture both human and non-human traits, again another issue of contention in the phenomenological tradition. 32 Not being a phenomenologist myself, my understanding of this tradition is strongly influenced by my colleagues Javier San Martín and Jesús Díaz who, together with Carmen López, run an active research group in phenomenology of the social world at my home university. See San Martín 2005 for an overview of this Spanish approach to phenomenology. Much to my regret, I can only provide a very incomplete picture of phenomenology, focusing on the thread that goes from Husserl to ethnomethodology through Schütz. Neither Heidegger nor Merleau-Ponty are mentioned, to cite just two prominent authors who wrote on the topics I discuss in this section. However, I do not think their inclusion would have changed my overall assessment. 33 I owe this interpretation of Husserl to Díaz Álvarez My own understanding of Husserl s transcendental phenomenology is based on San Martín 1986.

12 The third type of a priori refers to our social world and is captured by the Geisteswissenschaften. Items in this domain (be they groups, institutions, traditions, tools or works of art) present some sort of motivational connection (Motivationsbeziehung) to our consciousness: we appraise them acknowledging their intentional creation and we operate with them according to the intentions we discern. For Husserl, this intentional dimension can only be understood by reconstructing the particular history of each entity, which can never be explained in a naturalistic fashion. The social sciences, therefore, have their own irreducible ontological realm. However, this created quite a thorny problem. On one hand, the natural and the social sciences each have their own types of a priori structures. But, on the other hand, the intentional dimension comes first in our appraisal of any object, whatever its ontological realm. How can we access, say, the universal laws of physics from our folk understanding of physical objects, whose a priori structure is always particular and culturally situated? Husserl tried to solve this apparent dilemma by articulating his concept of Lebenswelt (usually translated as lifeworld). This concept refers to our primary apprehension of the world, balancing its universal and particular dimensions. According to Husserl, even in a culturally situated setting, we are able to grasp universal structures, namely by drawing on perception. But Husserl never fully clarified how this transition from particular appraisals to universal structures takes place. My colleague Jesús Díaz has defended an interpretation based on Husserl s text on the origins of geometry. 35 Ancient mathematical statements are expressed in a way entirely conditioned by their cultural context, but nonetheless we are able to grasp their ideal content, which is potentially universal. In order to grasp this content, we only need to master the argumentational skills that Ancient Greek philosophers first studied, which are preserved in the European tradition to this day. These argumentational skills allow us to discern universal structures not only in science, but also in art and other domains of our lifeworld. Despite the relative success of this concept among philosophers, 36 Husserl s stance is in contradiction to every form of particularism in social research. For instance, phenomenologists like San Martín (2009) have been extremely critical of cultural relativism in anthropology, taking it to be a result of anthropological theory s inability to deal with the distinctions introduced above and account for the objectivity of, among other things, science. 37 In other words, from this phenomenological standpoint, anthropologists would be theoretically misguided in their appraisal of the particularity or universality of certain cultural items. Right or wrong, such an a priori approach is certainly at odds with the philosophical tastes exhibited by professional anthropologists throughout the 20 th century, which is probably why phenomenology does not count as a major influence in their methodological debates, despite its influence on philosophers. There have been less principled attempts at hybridizing phenomenology and social theory. Among these, the most accomplished social phenomenology is still that of Alfred Schütz. Schütz ( ), a Viennese lawyer with a background in Austrian economics and interpretative sociology, spent part of his career in the United States and introduced phenomenology to American social scientists through his writings and 35 See Derrida 1978 for the English text with a commentary. I here follow the interpretation of Díaz Álvarez 2003, pp Mostly thanks to Jürgen Habermas, who made this concept part of his The Theory of Communicative Action (1984) 37 A more phenomenologically oriented anthropology, for San Martín, would be Cancian 1975.

13 personal exchanges. 38 Schütz s main contribution was to develop a phenomenological philosophy of the social sciences, namely by reinterpreting Max Weber s theory of action through Husserl s approach. Instead of taking the subjective meaning of individual actions as a primitive category, like Weber, Schütz analyzed its phenomenological grounds. 39 His goal was to go beyond a merely commonsensical understanding of subjective meanings, isolating their a priori sources and explaining the emergence of a shared Lebenswelt. The operations of our consciousness analyzed by Husserl would also generate, for Schütz, the shared structures of meaning allowing us to understand each other s action. Each individual would appraise the social world from a particular perspective. Social agents would then make abstractions from these individual appraisals (here-and-now experiences), generating ideal types in order to grasp wider regions of the social world, temporally and spatially, gradually more and more distant from the hic et nunc self. Communication of increasingly abstract types generated inter-subjective meanings. The social sciences should account for this shared understanding of reality. Any purportedly objective concept they may construct (e.g., statistical aggregates) should always be interpretable from the point of view of these shared meanings, since, ultimately, they constitute the social world they intend to capture. However, for Schütz, Husserl s approach had failed to solve the problem of transcendental intersubjectivity, which was necessary to deal with this relational dimension of the social world. He claimed instead that the social scientists should proceed from the natural understanding of the subjects under study, without paying so much attention to their transcendental foundations. Stimulated by American pragmatism, Schütz focused on the problem of why we take anything social as real. For him, our appraisal of the social world is structured according to the relevance we discern in any of its features whether because these are externally imposed as relevant or due to their connection with our own purposes. We use different cognitive styles to deal with these relevant features, depending on the operations we perform on them. Together, these cognitive styles and the systems of relevance define meaningcontexts in the social world and each of them can be considered a reality of its own. Our sense of paramount reality arises, for Schütz, in the world of working, our bodily interactions with relevant physical objects. We grasp the reality of other realms as variations on these basic experiences. However, we live through all these meaningcontexts, without presupposing any unified sense of reality: switching between realms may come as a shock for an individual. Any self is, in this respect, divided to some extent, depending on the variety of her world experiences. In this framework, the understanding of individual actions requires an analysis of how the agent articulates the different systems of relevance operating in her particular Lebenswelt (Hermida 2009) in a personal life plan. Despite being a scientifically reconstructed ideal type, this abstract plan should be understandable to the agent whose action is under analysis. Schütz s philosophy of the social sciences is as much an ontology of the social world as a methodology for its investigation. However, this ontology stems to a great extent from categories already in use, at least in sociology, and Schütz s phenomenological twist 38 Like other German-speaking social scientists, Schütz emigrated to the United States fearing the ascent of the Nazis, condemning Jewish phenomenology (Wagner 1983). 39 I owe my interpretation of Schütz to P. Hermida s unpublished doctoral dissertation (Hermida Lazcano 2001), conducted under the supervision of J. San Martín at the UNED, as part of San Martín s research project on the phenomenology of the social world. For a general overview with an updated bibliography, including the English editions of Schütz s major texts, see Barber 2010.

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD Unit Code: Unit Name: Department: Faculty: 475Z022 METAPHYSICS (INBOUND STUDENT MOBILITY - JAN ENTRY) Politics & Philosophy Faculty Of Arts & Humanities Level: 5 Credits: 5 ECTS: 7.5 This unit will address

More information

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation Cogent Science in Context: The Science Wars, Argumentation Theory, and Habermas. By William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009. Pp. 355. Cloth, $40. Paper, $20. Jeffrey Flynn Fordham University Published

More information

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms Part II... Four Characteristic Research Paradigms INTRODUCTION Earlier I identified two contrasting beliefs in methodology: one as a mechanism for securing validity, and the other as a relationship between

More information

1. Two very different yet related scholars

1. Two very different yet related scholars 1. Two very different yet related scholars Comparing the intellectual output of two scholars is always a hard effort because you have to deal with the complexity of a thought expressed in its specificity.

More information

The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx

The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx Andy Blunden, June 2018 The classic text which defines the meaning of abstract and concrete for Marx and Hegel is the passage known as The Method

More information

observation and conceptual interpretation

observation and conceptual interpretation 1 observation and conceptual interpretation Most people will agree that observation and conceptual interpretation constitute two major ways through which human beings engage the world. Questions about

More information

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 44, 2015 Book Review Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Philip Kitcher

More information

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Reviewed by Christopher Pincock, Purdue University (pincock@purdue.edu) June 11, 2010 2556 words

More information

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers Cast of Characters X-Phi: Experimental Philosophy E-Phi: Empirical Philosophy A-Phi: Armchair Philosophy Challenges to Experimental Philosophy Empirical

More information

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY Russell Keat + The critical theory of the Frankfurt School has exercised a major influence on debates within Marxism and the philosophy of science over the

More information

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Testa, Italo email: italo.testa@unipr.it webpage: http://venus.unive.it/cortella/crtheory/bios/bio_it.html University of Parma, Dipartimento

More information

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History Review Essay Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History Giacomo Borbone University of Catania In the 1970s there appeared the Idealizational Conception of Science (ICS) an alternative

More information

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative 21-22 April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh Matthew Brown University of Texas at Dallas Title: A Pragmatist Logic of Scientific

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally Critical Theory Mark Olssen University of Surrey Critical theory emerged in Germany in the 1920s with the establishment of the Institute for Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in 1923. The term critical

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Karin de Boer Angelica Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant

More information

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, Volume 7, Issue 1, Spring 2014, pp. 161-165. http://ejpe.org/pdf/7-1-ts-2.pdf PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN PhD in economic

More information

Nicholas Vrousalis Philippe Van Parijs. Analytical Marxism

Nicholas Vrousalis Philippe Van Parijs. Analytical Marxism Nicholas Vrousalis Philippe Van Parijs Analytical Marxism In International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral sciences, James D. Wright ed., 2 nd ed., Oxford: Elsevier, 2015, pp. 665-667. Earlier

More information

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology Marquette University e-publications@marquette Economics Faculty Research and Publications Economics, Department of 1-1-1998 Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology John B. Davis Marquette

More information

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment First Moment: The Judgement of Taste is Disinterested. The Aesthetic Aspect Kant begins the first moment 1 of the Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment with the claim that

More information

The Debate on Research in the Arts

The Debate on Research in the Arts Excerpts from The Debate on Research in the Arts 1 The Debate on Research in the Arts HENK BORGDORFF 2007 Research definitions The Research Assessment Exercise and the Arts and Humanities Research Council

More information

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Book review of Schear, J. K. (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, Routledge, London-New York 2013, 350 pp. Corijn van Mazijk

More information

A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault

A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault By V. E. Koslovskii Excerpts from the article Structuralizm I dialekticheskii materialism, Filosofskie Nauki, 1970, no. 1, pp. 177-182. This article

More information

SECTION I: MARX READINGS

SECTION I: MARX READINGS SECTION I: MARX READINGS part 1 Marx s Vision of History: Historical Materialism This part focuses on the broader conceptual framework, or overall view of history and human nature, that informed Marx

More information

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank Multiple-Choice Questions: 1. Which of the following is a class in capitalism according to Marx? a) Protestants b) Wage laborers c) Villagers d) All of the above 2. Marx

More information

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education The refereed journal of the Volume 9, No. 1 January 2010 Wayne Bowman Editor Electronic Article Shusterman, Merleau-Ponty, and Dewey: The Role of Pragmatism

More information

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory Part IV Social Science and Network Theory 184 Social Science and Network Theory In previous chapters we have outlined the network theory of knowledge, and in particular its application to natural science.

More information

Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION

Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION In the next several sections we will follow up n more detail the distinction Thereborn made between three modes of interpellation: what is, what

More information

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document Boulder Valley School District Department of Curriculum and Instruction February 2012 Introduction The Boulder Valley Elementary Visual Arts Curriculum

More information

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn The social mechanisms approach to explanation (SM) has

More information

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Department of Philosophy Florida State University Department of Philosophy Florida State University Undergraduate Courses PHI 2010. Introduction to Philosophy (3). An introduction to some of the central problems in philosophy. Students will also learn

More information

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education Marilyn Zurmuehlen Working Papers in Art Education ISSN: 2326-7070 (Print) ISSN: 2326-7062 (Online) Volume 2 Issue 1 (1983) pps. 56-60 Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

More information

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile Web: www.kailashkut.com RESEARCH METHODOLOGY E- mail srtiwari@ioe.edu.np Mobile 9851065633 Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is What is Paradigm? Definition, Concept, the Paradigm Shift? Main Components

More information

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm Ralph Hall The University of New South Wales ABSTRACT The growth of mixed methods research has been accompanied by a debate over the rationale for combining what

More information

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen) GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen) Week 3: The Science of Politics 1. Introduction 2. Philosophy of Science 3. (Political) Science 4. Theory

More information

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst 271 Kritik von Lebensformen By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN 9783518295878, 451pp by Hans Arentshorst Does contemporary philosophy need to concern itself with the question of the good life?

More information

[My method is] a science that studies the life of signs within society I shall call it semiology from the Greek semeion signs (Saussure)

[My method is] a science that studies the life of signs within society I shall call it semiology from the Greek semeion signs (Saussure) Week 12: 24 November Ferdinand de Saussure: Early Structuralism and Linguistics Reading: John Storey, Chapter 6: Structuralism and post-structuralism (first half of article only, pp. 87-98) John Hartley,

More information

AQA Qualifications A-LEVEL SOCIOLOGY

AQA Qualifications A-LEVEL SOCIOLOGY AQA Qualifications A-LEVEL SOCIOLOGY SCLY4/Crime and Deviance with Theory and Methods; Stratification and Differentiation with Theory and Methods Report on the Examination 2190 June 2013 Version: 1.0 Further

More information

Categories and Schemata

Categories and Schemata Res Cogitans Volume 1 Issue 1 Article 10 7-26-2010 Categories and Schemata Anthony Schlimgen Creighton University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Part of the

More information

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it. Majors Seminar Rovane Spring 2010 The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it. The central text for the course will be a book manuscript

More information

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought Décalages Volume 2 Issue 1 Article 18 July 2016 A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought Louis Althusser Follow this and additional works at: http://scholar.oxy.edu/decalages Recommended Citation

More information

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Humanities Learning Outcomes University Major/Dept Learning Outcome Source Creative Writing The undergraduate degree in creative writing emphasizes knowledge and awareness of: literary works, including the genres of fiction, poetry,

More information

Kent Academic Repository

Kent Academic Repository Kent Academic Repository Full text document (pdf) Citation for published version Milton, Damian (2007) Sociological Theory: Cultural Aspects of Marxist Theory and the Development of Neo-Marxism. N/A. (Unpublished)

More information

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras Module - 26 Lecture - 26 Karl Marx Historical Materialism

More information

Normative and Positive Economics

Normative and Positive Economics Marquette University e-publications@marquette Economics Faculty Research and Publications Business Administration, College of 1-1-1998 Normative and Positive Economics John B. Davis Marquette University,

More information

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues TEST BANK Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues 1. As a self-conscious formal discipline, psychology is a. about 300 years old. * b. little more than 100 years old. c. only 50 years old. d. almost

More information

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART Tatyana Shopova Associate Professor PhD Head of the Center for New Media and Digital Culture Department of Cultural Studies, Faculty of Arts South-West University

More information

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press. Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (4) 640-642, December 2006 Michael

More information

Louis Althusser, What is Practice?

Louis Althusser, What is Practice? Louis Althusser, What is Practice? The word practice... indicates an active relationship with the real. Thus one says of a tool that it is very practical when it is particularly well adapted to a determinate

More information

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal Cet article a été téléchargé sur le site de la revue Ithaque : www.revueithaque.org Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal Pour plus de détails sur les dates de parution et comment

More information

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail. This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail. Author(s): Arentshorst, Hans Title: Book Review : Freedom s Right.

More information

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes University Major/Dept Learning Outcome Source Linguistics The undergraduate degree in linguistics emphasizes knowledge and awareness of: the fundamental architecture of language in the domains of phonetics

More information

Mass Communication Theory

Mass Communication Theory Mass Communication Theory 2015 spring sem Prof. Jaewon Joo 7 traditions of the communication theory Key Seven Traditions in the Field of Communication Theory 1. THE SOCIO-PSYCHOLOGICAL TRADITION: Communication

More information

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES BOSTON STUDIES IN THE PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE EDITED BY ROBERT S. COHEN AND MARX W. WARTOFSKY VOLUME 71 EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

More information

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT This article observes methodological aspects of conflict-contractual theory

More information

Critical Theory for Research on Librarianship (RoL)

Critical Theory for Research on Librarianship (RoL) Critical Theory for Research on Librarianship (RoL) Indira Irawati Soemarto Luki-Wijayanti Nina Mayesti Paper presented in International Conference of Library, Archives, and Information Science (ICOLAIS)

More information

List of Illustrations and Photos List of Figures and Tables About the Authors. 1. Introduction 1

List of Illustrations and Photos List of Figures and Tables About the Authors. 1. Introduction 1 Detailed Contents List of Illustrations and Photos List of Figures and Tables About the Authors Preface xvi xix xxii xxiii 1. Introduction 1 WHAT Is Sociological Theory? 2 WHO Are Sociology s Core Theorists?

More information

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden PARRHESIA NUMBER 11 2011 75-79 PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden I came to Paul Redding s 2009 work, Continental Idealism: Leibniz to

More information

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION MICHAEL QUANTE University of Duisburg Essen Translated by Dean Moyar PUBLISHED BY THE PRESS SYNDICATE OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CAMBRIDGE The Pitt Building, Trumpington Street, Cambridge,

More information

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden Seven remarks on artistic research Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden 11 th ELIA Biennial Conference Nantes 2010 Seven remarks on artistic research Creativity is similar

More information

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95. 441 Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95. Natika Newton in Foundations of Understanding has given us a powerful, insightful and intriguing account of the

More information

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May, Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May, 119-161. 1 To begin. n Is it possible to identify a Theory of communication field? n There

More information

The contribution of material culture studies to design

The contribution of material culture studies to design Connecting Fields Nordcode Seminar Oslo 10-12.5.2006 Toke Riis Ebbesen and Susann Vihma The contribution of material culture studies to design Introduction The purpose of the paper is to look closer at

More information

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory. Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory Paper in progress It is often asserted that communication sciences experience

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

Political Economy I, Fall 2014

Political Economy I, Fall 2014 Political Economy I, Fall 2014 Professor David Kotz Thompson 936 413-545-0739 dmkotz@econs.umass.edu Office Hours: Tuesdays 10 AM to 12 noon Information on Index Cards Your name Address Telephone Email

More information

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton This essay will explore a number of issues raised by the approaches to the philosophy of language offered by Locke and Frege. This

More information

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS Martyn Hammersley The Open University, UK Webinar, International Institute for Qualitative Methodology, University of Alberta, March 2014

More information

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT Maria Kronfeldner Forthcoming 2018 MIT Press Book Synopsis February 2018 For non-commercial, personal

More information

SOME QUESTIONS ABOUT THE THEORY OF THE SUBJECT: THE DISCURSIVE POLITICS OF PSYCHOANALYTIC THEORIES

SOME QUESTIONS ABOUT THE THEORY OF THE SUBJECT: THE DISCURSIVE POLITICS OF PSYCHOANALYTIC THEORIES SOME QUESTIONS ABOUT THE THEORY OF THE SUBJECT: THE DISCURSIVE POLITICS OF PSYCHOANALYTIC THEORIES Catherine Anne Greenfield, B.A.Hons (1st class) School of Humanities, Griffith University This thesis

More information

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) AMCIS 2003 Proceedings Americas Conference on Information Systems (AMCIS) December 2003 A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique

More information

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb CLOSING REMARKS The Archaeology of Knowledge begins with a review of methodologies adopted by contemporary historical writing, but it quickly

More information

Phenomenology Glossary

Phenomenology Glossary Phenomenology Glossary Phenomenology: Phenomenology is the science of phenomena: of the way things show up, appear, or are given to a subject in their conscious experience. Phenomenology tries to describe

More information

DIALECTIC IN WESTERN MARXISM

DIALECTIC IN WESTERN MARXISM DIALECTIC IN WESTERN MARXISM Sean Sayers University of Kent at Canterbury The fundamental principles of modern dialectical philosophy derive from Hegel. He sums them up as follows. `Everything is inherently

More information

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work. Research Methods II: Lecture notes These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work. Consider the approaches

More information

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May, Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May, 119-161. 1 To begin. n Is it possible to identify a Theory of communication field? n There

More information

Gender, the Family and 'The German Ideology'

Gender, the Family and 'The German Ideology' Gender, the Family and 'The German Ideology' Wed, 06/03/2009-21:18 Anonymous By Heather Tomanovsky The German Ideology (1845), often seen as the most materialistic of Marx s early writings, has been taken

More information

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp. Review of Sandra Harding s Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Kamili Posey, Kingsborough Community College, CUNY; María G. Navarro, Spanish National Research Council Objectivity

More information

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) Both the natural and the social sciences posit taxonomies or classification schemes that divide their objects of study into various categories. Many philosophers hold

More information

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Action Theory for Creativity and Process Action Theory for Creativity and Process Fu Jen Catholic University Bernard C. C. Li Keywords: A. N. Whitehead, Creativity, Process, Action Theory for Philosophy, Abstract The three major assignments for

More information

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation The U.S. Marxist-Humanists organization, grounded in Marx s Marxism and Raya Dunayevskaya s ideas, aims to develop a viable vision of a truly new human society that can give direction to today s many freedom

More information

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE Introduction Georg Iggers, distinguished professor of history emeritus at the State University of New York,

More information

The Capitalist Unconscious Marx And Lacan

The Capitalist Unconscious Marx And Lacan The Capitalist Unconscious Marx And Lacan 1 / 6 2 / 6 3 / 6 The Capitalist Unconscious Marx And This paper studies how subjectivity in capitalist culture can be characterized. Building on Lacan's later

More information

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage. Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage. An English Summary Anne Ring Petersen Although much has been written about the origins and diversity of installation art as well as its individual

More information

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics REVIEW A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics Kristin Gjesdal: Gadamer and the Legacy of German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. xvii + 235 pp. ISBN 978-0-521-50964-0

More information

Georg Simmel and Formal Sociology

Georg Simmel and Formal Sociology УДК 316.255 Borisyuk Anna Institute of Sociology, Psychology and Social Communications, student (Ukraine, Kyiv) Pet ko Lyudmila Ph.D., Associate Professor, Dragomanov National Pedagogical University (Ukraine,

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article Reading across Borders: Storytelling and Knowledges of Resistance (review) Susan E. Babbitt Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp. 203-206 (Review) Published by Indiana University Press DOI: 10.1353/hyp.2006.0018

More information

In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases as bibliographies become shorter

In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases as bibliographies become shorter Jointly published by Akademiai Kiado, Budapest and Kluwer Academic Publishers, Dordrecht Scientometrics, Vol. 60, No. 3 (2004) 295-303 In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases

More information

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB In his In librum Boethii de Trinitate, q. 5, a. 3 [see The Division and Methods of the Sciences: Questions V and VI of

More information

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5 PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5 We officially started the class by discussing the fact/opinion distinction and reviewing some important philosophical tools. A critical look at the fact/opinion

More information

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that Wiggins, S. (2009). Discourse analysis. In Harry T. Reis & Susan Sprecher (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Human Relationships. Pp. 427-430. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Discourse analysis Discourse analysis is an

More information

The philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; the point, however, is to change it. (Karl Marx, 11 th Thesis on Feuerbach)

The philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; the point, however, is to change it. (Karl Marx, 11 th Thesis on Feuerbach) Week 6: 27 October Marxist approaches to Culture Reading: Storey, Chapter 4: Marxisms The philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; the point, however, is to change it. (Karl Marx,

More information

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism?

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism? Perhaps the clearest and most certain thing that can be said about postmodernism is that it is a very unclear and very much contested concept Richard Shusterman in Aesthetics and

More information

National Standards for Visual Art The National Standards for Arts Education

National Standards for Visual Art The National Standards for Arts Education National Standards for Visual Art The National Standards for Arts Education Developed by the Consortium of National Arts Education Associations (under the guidance of the National Committee for Standards

More information

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions Theresa (Terri) Thorkildsen Professor of Education and Psychology University of Illinois at Chicago One way to begin the [research] enterprise is to walk out

More information

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw Qualitative Design and Measurement The Oregon Research & Quality Consortium Conference April 11, 2011 0900-1000 Lissi Hansen, PhD, RN Patricia Nardone, PhD, MS, RN, CNOR Oregon Health & Science University,

More information

Review of: The Rise and Fall of Structural Marxism: Althusser and His Influence by Ted Benton, Macmillan, 1984, 257 pages, by Lee Harvey

Review of: The Rise and Fall of Structural Marxism: Althusser and His Influence by Ted Benton, Macmillan, 1984, 257 pages, by Lee Harvey Review of: The Rise and Fall of Structural Marxism: Althusser and His Influence by Ted Benton, Macmillan, 1984, 257 pages, by Lee Harvey Benton s book is an introductory text on Althusser that has two

More information

A New Reflection on the Innovative Content of Marxist Theory Based on the Background of Political Reform Juanhui Wei

A New Reflection on the Innovative Content of Marxist Theory Based on the Background of Political Reform Juanhui Wei 7th International Conference on Social Network, Communication and Education (SNCE 2017) A New Reflection on the Innovative Content of Marxist Theory Based on the Background of Political Reform Juanhui

More information

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action 4 This total process [of Trukese navigation] goes forward without reference to any explicit principles and without any planning, unless the intention to proceed' to a particular island can be considered

More information