Aristotle's Pluralistic Realism

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Aristotle's Pluralistic Realism"

Transcription

1 Western University From the SelectedWorks of Devin Henry 2011 Aristotle's Pluralistic Realism Devin Henry, The University of Western Ontario Available at:

2 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 1. Introduction Realism about natural kinds goes back at least as far as Plato s Phaedrus, which famously employs the metaphor of a butcher to describe the method of collection and division (265D E). 1 Collection (sunagôgê) consists in seeing together the many scattered things and drawing them into a single form, while division (diaresis) involves cutting up each thing along its natural joints (kat arthra ê i pephuken). In doing so, Socrates tells the young Phaedrus, one must be careful not to break any part into pieces like a bad butcher might do. It is hard not to read Socrates s metaphor as expressing a commitment to the reality of natural kinds. The natural world contains parts (cf. Statesman 262AB) that are individuated on the basis of real, mind-independent boundaries (the joints ). Being a bad butcher consists in dividing across those boundaries. In contrast to this, the nominalist claims that nature contains no natural joints; there is simply a continuity of similarities that blend into one another. 2 Therefore, any divisions we make are ultimately arbitrary and selfserving. For the nominalist, even our best scientific classifications will be anthropocentric insofar as they reflect properties that we as humans find interesting. Plato was aware of these anthropocentric concerns. At Statesman 236D, the Eleatic Stranger criticizes Young Socrates s division of animals into humans and nonhumans by saying that if cranes could speak they would balk at this and insist that the world comes divided into cranes and noncranes. Presumably the theory of Forms is supposed to avoid this problem by grounding division in objective reality. Although biologists no longer take seriously the theory of Forms, they are not very impressed by nominalism either, at least when it comes to the existence of species. 3 Species such as Pandion haliaetus and Vampyroteuthis infernalis are real groups individuated on the basis of objective biological properties that do not depend on our recognizing them as such. 4 Aristotle s Pluralistic Realism by Devin Henry, The Monist, vol. 94, no. 2, pp Copyright 2011, THE MONIST, Peru, Illinois

3 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 199 While there are various competing theories of natural kinds on the market, the following characterization captures the main idea behind natural kinds. 5 First, natural kinds are groups of things sharing certain objective properties in common, in virtue of which they form a single kind. What makes a kind natural as opposed to conventional is a difficult issue. One way of drawing the distinction is to say that the former share objective similarities in common while the latter depend mainly on human interests. For this reason gold constitutes a natural kind while all the objects in my garage do not. Second, natural kinds have essences. Typically an essence is understood to be a membership-determining property that is both necessary and sufficient for belonging to a kind. On some more robust theories (such as Aristotle s), the essence also plays a causal role in determining other properties of the kind. For example, having the atomic number 79 not only makes something a member of the kind gold but is also causally responsible for the possession of other characteristic properties, including a certain colour and malleability. Elliot Sober (1980, 354) puts the point this way: The key idea, I think, is that the membership condition must be explanatory. The essentialist hypothesizes that there exists some characteristic unique to and shared by all members of Homo sapiens which explains why they are the way they are. A species essence will be a causal mechanism which works on each member of the species, making it the kind of thing that it is. Not all theories of natural kinds agree on how to characterize the essentialism involved. One might take kinds to be defined by essential properties without thinking of those properties as being causally responsible for other properties associated with the kind. Nor do all essentialist theories accept the idea that kinds are defined by properties that are both necessary and sufficient for membership. So-called cluster kind theories, for example, take certain properties to be diagnostic but deny that they are essential in the sense that nothing can lack them and still be a member of the kind. On this account, natural kinds are defined by a cluster of stable features, none of which are necessary and only a subset of which are sufficient for membership in the kind. 6 While all realists about natural kinds accept Plato s metaphor about cutting nature at the joints, they differ in terms of how they understand the metaphor. 7 Monistic realism is the view that there is only one true set of

4 200 DEVIN HENRY (nonoverlapping) kinds for any given scientific domain and that discovering those kinds will yield a single, unified system of natural classifications. By contrast, pluralistic realism sees a given domain as a multidimensional space that can be divided along multiple axes. 8 This multidimensional complexity is not something that can be captured by a single, universal classification. Instead, there are many equally legitimate ways of dividing the objects in that domain into natural kinds, which may cross-classify one another in indefinitely complex ways. For example, the living world might be divided along its trophic joints into one set of kinds (coprophagous, necrophagous, phytophagous, saprophytic, etc.), or along its parasitic joints into another set of kinds (endoparasites, ectoparasites, parasitoids, etc.), or along its phyletic joints into phylogenetic kinds (monophyletic, paraphyletic, polyphyletic). 9 Assuming that each of these divisions picks out a set of real kinds, the pluralist will argue that no one set of kinds should be privileged over another. In this paper I argue that Aristotle is a pluralist when it came to the study of biological diversity: he denies that there is only one true set of biological kinds and that a natural classification will divide those kinds into a single set of exhaustive and nonoverlapping categories. 10 Instead, there are many equally legitimate ways of classifying living things, though no single way of classifying them is privileged over the other. Despite this pluralistic approach to classification, Aristotle remains committed to realism and thus shares an affinity with traditional scientific realists who hold that there are objective kinds in nature (such as chemical kinds) delineated by real, mind-independent boundaries. 11 Thus, like Plato, Aristotle thinks the natural world comes divided up into kinds that are somehow out there waiting to be discovered and that our best scientific classifications will be those that successfully map out these natural divisions. This interpretation places Aristotle squarely in the camp of pluralistic realism. 12 This reading is similar to that of Pellegrin (1982). On Pellegrin s reading, Aristotle treats classification as a pragmatic exercise in which the division of animals into kinds is developed for the occasion, adapting their extension and rigor to the needs of the exposition in progress (115). My reading differs from this in that I take Aristotle also to be a realist

5 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 201 about biological kinds rather than being merely pragmatic about them. That is, despite his pluralistic approach to classification, Aristotle still believed there is a certain naturalness to the various biological groupings (hence the realism). For at the core of each cross-cutting kind lies a real essence that corresponds to an aitia or cause. And according to APo. II 2, we are justified in claiming that some kind exists once we have discovered that there is a cause that is responsible for the fact that a certain cluster of attributes regularly co-vary. So Aristotle s practice of classification in the biological works is not subjective but identifies real kinds, despite the fact that which kinds are identified is governed largely by the explanatory goals of the classifier. For explanation in Aristotle is limited to phenomena that exhibit a determinate causal structure. My defense of this reading is concentrated in sections 2 and 3. Section 2 establishes the pluralist aspect of this interpretation by showing how Aristotle s biology employs several overlapping divisions without privileging one set of divisions over another. Section 3 attempts to establish the realism by looking at Aristotle s concept of nature and the method he recommends for determining the existence of a natural kind. According to this account a genuine kind is a group of individuals sharing a common nature, which I take to be a nexus of correlations underwritten by a set of causally basic features (the kind s real essence). In the final section ( 4) I defend the claim that Aristotle s biology should remain of interest to philosophers and biologists alike insofar as it combines pluralism and realism with a rank-free approach to classification, which some philosophers see as the way forward in systematics. In this context Grene (1974, 74) is surely right that the besieged biologists and their philosophical defenders can learn something valuable by reflecting on the one great philosopher who was also a great biologist. 2. Aristotle s Pluralism History of Animals I 6 identifies seven major biological kinds, which Aristotle calls the megista genê or Great Kinds: birds, fish, cetaceans, cephalopods, crustaceans, hard-shelled animals, and insects. Yet, this list excludes many groups that Aristotle finds scientifically interesting enough to investigate. For example, snakes are treated as a unified group sharing a single common nature and containing specific forms that differ only by

6 202 DEVIN HENRY degree (e.g. History of Animals [HA] I 6, 490b24; II 14; III 1, 511a14 15). As we shall see, these are marks of a natural kind. Other significant groupings that Aristotle discusses in his biological writings include: livebearers and egg-layers; lung-possessors and gill-possessors; claw-possessors (e.g. Parts of Animals [PA] IV 8, 684a34); horn-bearing animals that lack incisors in both jaws, what we call ruminants (e.g. HA III 1, 511a28 34; cf. Posterior Analytics [APo.] II 14, 98a13 19); bipeds, quadrupeds, and footless animals; walkers, crawlers, leapers, and fliers (e.g. Progression of Animals [IA] III; Generation of Animals [GA] I 1, 715a27 8); political (politika) animals, which include humans, bees, ants, and cranes (HA I 1, 488a9); and my personal favourite, marine animals that make use of crafty mechanisms (technika), which is a rather eclectic group that includes the angler fish, various sea snakes, torpedo fish, fox sharks, cuttlefish, and many more (HA VIII 37). 13 According to the traditional view Aristotle assumes as uncontroversial that there is a single correct way to classify animals into kinds, which could be formulated in a single taxonomy (M. Tweedale, personal communication). Yet, a complete survey of all the ways that Aristotle divides up the living world reveals a tendency to classify things from a multiplicity of viewpoints (to borrow Pellegrin s phrase), a practice which often leads to multiple cross-classifications and overlapping kinds. And yet, none of these ways of dividing up the biological landscape appears to represent a privileged classification. Rather, each set of divisions proves to be useful for a different causal investigation. There are two main pieces of evidence that support this pluralistic reading. The first are the several occurrences of cross-division, where a division of animals into one set of kinds can be shown to cut across a division into another set of kinds. And yet neither way of classifying animals is said to be privileged over the other in any absolute sense. The following example makes the point explicit. Division 1. In GA II 1 Aristotle carves up the biological landscape according to differences in mode of reproduction, which yields four extensive kinds: live-bearers, egg-layers, larva-producers, and animals that are spontaneously generated (732a26 733a1; cf. HA I 5, III 1). This classification identifies the primary reproductive kinds that are the focus of inquiry in the GA. From this perspective lizards and turtles are grouped together with fish, birds, and snakes as egg-layers, while cetaceans are

7 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 203 grouped with humans, elephants, and bats as live-bearers. Some of the insects are then marked off as larva-producers, while others are said to be spontaneously generated. Division 2a. When Aristotle turns from reproduction to locomotion in the IA (cf. HA I 1, 5), the very same animals are regrouped into a different set of kinds. Here two main differentiae are used to classify animals. In some places, Aristotle groups animals according to their type of locomotion (IA III). The primary division here is into those that change place with their whole body at the same time (e.g. jumpers) and those that do so part-by-part (e.g. walkers). 14 From this perspective lizards and turtles are classified together with humans, elephants, and crabs as walkers, cetaceans go with fish, water snakes, and crustaceans as swimmers, while birds, bats, and insects make up the class of flyers. Division 2b. In other places, Aristotle groups animals according to the parts used for locomotion. From this perspective birds and humans are classified together as bipeds, elephants, lions, lizards, and crocodiles as quadrupeds, insects as polypods, while cetaceans, fish, and snakes are classed as footless animals. Division 3. Finally, in On Respiration Aristotle divides animals according to their different ways of cooling themselves, giving us three major refrigerative kinds: lung-possessors, gill-possessors, and membrane-possessors. 15 From this perspective, cetaceans get reclassified with lizards, humans, and birds as lung-possessors, separating them off from fish, cephalopods, and all the other marine animals that cool themselves by means of gills, leaving the insects as the only animals that cool themselves by means of a vibrating membrane. It is easy to see that these different ways of classifying animals partition the biological world into kinds that cross-cut one another. For example, Division 1 cuts across Division 3: some egg-layers are lung-possessors (e.g. birds, lizards, turtles, all the snakes except the viper), while others are gill-possessors (e.g. the bony fish); likewise, some live-bearers possess lungs (e.g. humans, cetaceans, horses, vipers), while others possess gills (e.g. certain sharks and rays). Division 3 also cuts across Divisions 2b: some lung-possessors are two-footed (humans and birds), some four-footed (e.g. horses, oxen), some footless (e.g. whales and dolphins), and at least one four-footed animal is a gill-possessor (e.g. the

8 204 DEVIN HENRY water newt: On Resp. 476a5). 16 Aristotle himself draws our attention to the fact that Division 1 overlaps with Division 2a: In fact there is a good deal of overlapping among the kinds. For not all twofooted animals are live-bearing (for birds are egg-laying) nor are they all egg-laying (for humans are live-bearing), and not all four-footed animals are egg-laying (for horses and oxen and a great deal of others are live-bearing) nor are they all live-bearing (for lizards and crocodiles and many others are egg-laying). Nor does the difference even lie in having-feet or not-havingfeet; for some footless animals are live-bearing (e.g. vipers and the cartilaginous fish), while others are egg-laying (e.g. the kind consisting of fish and the remainder of the snakes). And of the footed animals many are egg-laying, many live-bearing (e.g. the four-footed animals already mentioned). There are two-footed animals which are internally live-bearing (e.g. humans) and footless ones as well (e.g. the whale and dolphin). So we find no means of making a division here. (GA II 1, 732b15 27) Finally, these different ways of classifying animals cut right across the socalled Great Kinds of HA I 6. For example, Division 1 breaks up the fish: bony fish are egg-layers, cartilaginous fish (with the exception of the fishing frog) are live-bearers, 17 while eels are spontaneously generated (GA III 11). The division into larva-producers and spontaneously generated animals also breaks up the insects, while Aristotle s locomotive kinds break up the cephalopods (some cephalopods are footed walkers, while others are footless swimmers: PA IV 9, 685a14 15). The other piece of evidence that suggests Aristotle was a pluralist about classification comes from those animals that he describes as being epamphoterês. Such animals are susceptible to multiple ways of classifying them. Some of their features are best explained by classifying them as one kind of animal, while others are explained by classifying them under another (mutually exclusive) kind. The most spectacular example is the Libyan ostrich. Incredibly, Aristotle claims that the Libyan ostrich is both a bird and a live-bearing quadruped, which explains why this strange animal possesses some of the features characteristic of the one kind and some characteristic of the other kind: In the same way, too, the Libyan ostrich [is ambiguous between two kinds]. On the one hand it has the character of birds, on the other hand that of the live-bearing quadrupeds. For as a non-quadruped it has feathers but as a nonbird it does not take to the air in flight and its feathers are not useful for flying but are hair-like. Furthermore, as a quadruped it has upper eyelashes and is

9 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 205 bald around the head and above the neck, so that it has hairier eyelashes. Yet as a bird the lower body is feathered, and while as a bird it is two-footed, as a quadruped it is hoofed. For it has, not toes, but hoofs. This is because its size is not that of a bird but of a quadruped; for generally speaking, it is necessary for birds to be as small as possible with respect to their size, since it is not easy for a body of great mass to get off the ground. (PA IV 14, 697b13 28) This example nicely illustrates how classification is tied to explanation. 18 In order to explain why the ostrich s lower body is covered in feathers and why it is two-footed we need to classify it as a bird and then ask why those features belong to all birds qua bird. For the cause of those features are to be found at the level of that wider kind. But if we want to explain why the ostrich is bald around the head and above the neck, has eyelashes, and sports hoofs instead of split toes, we need to reclassify it as a quadruped and look for the cause the level of that kind. The crucial point here is that, for Aristotle, there is no single privileged way of classifying the ostrich, either as a bird or as a quadruped, but rather how we classify it depends on what features we are trying to explain. If we want to know why it has some traits, we need to treat it as a bird; if we want to know why it has other traits, we need to treat it as a quadruped. A commitment to the idea that there is one and only one way to classify each animal would inevitably leave some of its traits unexplained. My other example follows the same pattern. In HA II 8 Aristotle tells us that apes, monkeys, and baboons can be classified both as bipeds and as quadrupeds, since they share in the essential properties of both kinds (502a16 24). This has explanatory significance. In PA IV 10 we are given a causal explanation for why bipeds have haunches but lack a tail, while quadrupeds have a tail but lack haunches. We are then told that being intermediate between these two kinds explains why the ape lacks both features: The ape, because it is intermediate between the two (epamphoterês) with respect to its form, and because it is neither and both, has neither a tail nor haunches: as a biped it lacks a tail, and as a quadruped it lacks haunches (689b32 4). Again, how we classify the ape depends on what features we want to explain. If we want to know why it lacks a tail, we need to treat it as a biped; if we want to know why it lacks haunches, we need to treat it as a quadruped. There is no privileged way of classifying the ape from an unqualified perspective.

10 206 DEVIN HENRY There is a worry here about substances having multiple essences and thus being subject to multiple definitions, a position that Aristotle undoubtedly rejects. The worry can be reduced by noting that its force derives from the thinking of an essence (the object of definition) as a single property. In that case in order to be a bird and a quadruped the ostrich would have to have two essences. But Aristotle thinks biological kinds are characterized by essences composed of multiple attributes (PA I 3), some of which may be part of the essences of other kinds. His essentialism only requires that the entire complex of attributes that makes up a kind s essence picks out that kind uniquely (APo. II 13, 96a24 b1). The single essence of the Libyan ostrich will thus be defined by a single complex of multiple attributes, some of which are characteristic of birds and others characteristic of quadrupeds. 19 For Aristotle, then, there is no single way of classifying animals from some absolute, context-free perspective. Instead, how we classify animals depends on the problem at hand: what wider kinds we subsume an animal under depends on which of its features we are trying to explain. This is hard to square with the idea that Aristotle was committed to a form of monism when it came to classification. For Aristotle, there is no one way of carving nature at the joints that will fit all animals into a single set of mutually exclusive, exhaustive, and nonoverlapping kinds. Instead nature contains many cross-cutting joints, and which joints we choose to cut along depends in large part on the explanatory aims of the biologist. The embryologist divides the animal kingdom according to the various modes of reproduction, while the student of biomechanics divides by the different ways of moving in space. And yet a division of animals into swimmers, walkers, flyers, and crawlers will be of no use to the biologist studying animal refrigeration. The set of problems that define her inquiry require dividing the world into lung-possessors, gill-possessors, and membrane-possessors. There is one passage that appears to commit Aristotle to monism. In PA I 2 Aristotle criticizes Platonic division for splitting apart certain kinds that he claims ought to be kept together: Further, one should avoid tearing each kind apart, e.g. putting some of the birds in one division and some in the other, as the written [sc. Platonic] divisions have done; there, some of the birds end up divided off with the water-dwellers, some in another kind.... If, then, nothing alike in kind

11 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 207 should be torn apart, division into two is worthless. For people who divide in this way necessarily separate and tear apart; some of the many-footed things are among the land-dwellers, while some are among the water-dwellers. (642b10 19, Lennox trans.) It is tempting to read this passage as treating certain kinds as privileged so that any divisions that split them up must somehow be unnatural. However, as we have just seen, this way of reading the text faces the problem that Aristotle himself is willing to split up kinds when the occasion calls for it. One way to avoid this tension is to distinguish between one set of true kinds (e.g. the Great Kinds) and downgrade all cross-cutting groups to mere pragmatic groupings formed for expedience. 20 While this might work for a group like the technika (HA VIII 37), which is a motley crew of animals from different Great Kinds, it will not work for groups like egg-layers and lung-possessors, which (as we shall see) bear all the hallmarks of Aristotelian natural kinds. The alternative is to take the claim that one should avoid tearing each kind apart and nothing alike in kind should be torn apart as being relative to the division under consideration. Thus, for example, when dividing by mode of reproduction we should avoid tearing apart those groups that share a common reproductive nature (e.g. live-bearers, egg-layers, etc.). However, when dividing by mode of locomotion those same animals should be kept apart as belonging to different kinds (e.g. flyers and swimmers), since their locomotive features are the same only by analogy. A further worry arises from the fact that Aristotle s so-called Great Kinds (birds, fish, etc.) appear to play a special role in the organization of his various biological treatises. For most of the time Aristotle s discussions proceed according to the Great Kinds. 21 The role of the Great Kinds in Aristotle s biology is a very complicated issue, and I do not have the space to offer anything more than a cursory response. The key question is whether or not Aristotle privileges these kinds as having inviolable boundaries such that any divisions that cut across those boundaries must fail to pick out true kinds. The answer seems to be No. For example, while Aristotle often treats the fish together as a single kind, he thinks that it sometimes makes better sense to classify the cartilaginous fish with things that are not fish for the purpose of explaining some of their features for example, when trying to understand certain parts of their reproductive

12 208 DEVIN HENRY anatomy that make no sense when compared with other fish (e.g. GA 716b26 33, 718a35 b2, 718b34 719a2, 732a26 b7). Although I have only pointed to a few such examples, they are evidence of a tendency on Aristotle s part to split up the Great Kinds when the occasion calls for it. It is this tendency towards splitting that is important for my reading. For it shows that Aristotle did not treat the Great Kinds as ontologically privileged so that don t tear apart the Great Kinds is not an overriding concern of his systematics. However important the Great Kinds might be as organizational concepts, they do not enjoy a privileged status as ontological groupings. 3. Aristotle s Realism So far I have argued that Aristotle was a pluralist when it came to biological classification. According to this view, there are a number of equally legitimate ways of dividing living things into kinds, and these kinds often overlap with one another. Within this pluralistic framework, no one set of kinds is privileged in any absolute sense; rather, which set of kinds is selected for a given inquiry depends on the explanatory goals of the inquirer. Despite this fact, Aristotle remained committed to realism. For Aristotle, the kinds from which the inquirer selects are natural kinds delineated by objective, mind-independent boundaries. Defending that thesis will be the focus of this section. A common objection to the idea of pluralistic realism is that the pluralism involved is far too liberal. Without any clear criteria for deciding which classifications are legitimate and which are not, pluralistic realism allows anything to count as a genuine kind and thus loses its connection with reality: The metaphysical angst that many realists experience with pluralism concerns the extent to which one can make sense of the idea that there are incompatible but equally natural (i.e., real) ways in which a science can taxonomize the entities in its domain. There is at least the suspicion that... pluralism is driven more by the purpose of the classification than by the peculiarities of the organisms in question.... (Wilson 1999, 203; cf. Wilkins 2003, ) The worry here is that pluralistic realism simply collapses into a form of conventionalism, with classification depending entirely on the interests of

13 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 209 the classifier. 22 Aristotle s version of pluralistic realism avoids this problem, since the possession of shared similarities is necessary but not sufficient to constitute a genuine kind. For Aristotle, natural kinds are limited to those groups whose shared similarities are underwritten by common causes. In this way Aristotle s approach differs from other versions of pluralistic realism that treat all (or most) classifications as equally legitimate. 23 This reading is supported by two considerations. First, according to PA I 4, genuine kinds (genê) are groups that (1) share a single common nature and (2) contain forms that are not too distant (644b1 6). The second condition has to do with a distinction between higher-level kinds (such as birds and snakes), which are divisible into forms, and so-called infima species (such as humans), which are not. The idea is that, while different forms of wider kind all share a common nature, that common nature will differ in each form by what Aristotle calls the more and less. So, for example, while all birds have beaks, each form of bird (e.g. sparrow, curlew, osprey) has a beak whose particular structure differs by degree along its various dimensions (e.g. longer/shorter, curved/straight, etc.). 24 What exactly it means to share a single common nature is more difficult. However, the rough outlines of an answer can be sketched by considering Aristotle s different uses of the term nature (see Physics II 1, Metaphysics V 4). Although nature is said in many ways, there are two uses that are particularly relevant here. First, Aristotle often associates the nature of a thing with the basic form that results from its normal development (Metaphysics V 4, 1015a11 12). In this sense having wings, a beak, and two backwards-bending legs will be part of the common nature of a bird (HA II 12), while being footless, blooded, and covered in horny plates is part of the common nature of snakes (HA I 6, 490b23 4). However, nature is also said to be a certain principle and cause of a thing s characteristic attributes insofar as it is the inner source of the changes that produce them (Physics II 1, 192b21 3, 193a30 1, 199b31). This is the key to Aristotle s account of natural kinds. What makes a group of similar individuals a genuine kind is the fact that their shared attributes all result from the same intrinsic causes, which Aristotle identifies with the kind s real essence.

14 210 DEVIN HENRY With this in mind let me turn to Aristotle s account of egg-layers in GA III in order to demonstrate how, despite overlapping with other important biological kinds (including the Great Kinds), this group constitutes a natural kind in the technical sense. In GA III Aristotle identifies a network of interrelated egg-laying features that are correlated with one another in systematic ways. At the core of this network lies a common set of causes (including shared developmental capacities, reproductive goals, and a particular material constitution), which together give rise to all those features that mark off the egg-layers from other reproductive kinds. More fine-grained differences within these common causes in turn explain the specific more-and-less differences that mark off one form of egg-layer from another (as predicted by PA I 4). For example, all egg-layers are said to be colder and more solid in their nature than their live-bearing counterparts, which explains why they all lay eggs rather than bear live young (GA II 1, 732b29 ff.). However, where an egg-layer is located within this particular range of the hot-cold/fluid-solid continuum causally determines the kind of egg it lays (GA 751b8 752a10): 1. Those egg-layers whose material nature is hottest and most fluid (e.g. snakes, lizards, and land-dwelling birds) produce doublecoloured eggs that are completely separated into white and yolk. 2. Those whose nature is coldest and least fluid (e.g. bony fish, cephalopods) produce single-coloured eggs that are not at all separated into white and yolk. 3. Those whose nature lies between these two extremes (e.g. waterdwelling birds) produce eggs that are only partially separated into white and yolk. These more-and-less differences in the internal structure of the egg are then further correlated with other reproductive differences, including where the embryo develops inside the egg (GA 751b4 7, 754b20 7), the shape of the egg (GA 752a11 21), and whether or not it can be fertilized multiple times (GA 757b7 14). In this way, differences in the material nature of an egg-layer (where it lies on the hot-cold/fluid-solid continuum) cause differences in the internal structure of its eggs, which are in turn causally linked to other specific egg-laying features.

15 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 211 In this example, the material nature of the animal is causally basic. But there are other causes involved in explaining other differences between egg-layers, including formal, final, and efficient causes. For example, all members of the kind produce embryos that develop inside an egg (for the same reason), which generates the need for protection a final cause. Now in the hotter egg-layers (e.g. birds and snakes) this goal is satisfied by producing a hard shell around the egg. But since shells are hardened by heat, egg-layers that are too cold (e.g. bony fish) can only produce a soft-shelled egg. And since these animals are also naturally prolific, they must lay their eggs before they finish growing, since the female cannot carry a large clutch of full-sized eggs inside herself. But this makes their eggs vulnerable to predation. In order to compensate for this, their eggs get injected with a special yeast-like substance that causes them to expand rapidly after being laid. This causal mechanism provides the necessary protection for the preservation of the kind, which in other egg-layers is achieved by a hard shell. 25 This example nicely illustrates how developmental, material, and teleological causes all conspire to produce a network of other egg-laying attributes included in the common nature of the kind. Aristotle s emphasis on common causes behind the shared attributes of egg-layers, and on the correlation between those attributes and other egg-laying features, is exactly what we should expect if he is thinking of the egg-layers as a natural kind with the right causal structure for being an object of scientific inquiry. The claim that Aristotle limits natural kinds to those groups whose shared similarities are underwritten by common causes is further evidenced by the way he thinks a science goes about determining whether or not its basic kinds exist. In APo. II Aristotle divides scientific inquiry about kinds into three stages: 26 Stage 1.We do not yet know if the kind K exists; all we have is a preliminary grasp of a set of properties that are correlated with one another in regular ways. Stage 2.We know that K exists (it is a real kind), but we do not yet know what it is to be a K (we lack knowledge of its essence). Stage 3.We know both that K exists and what K is (we grasp its essence).

16 212 DEVIN HENRY The key to this approach is Aristotle s insistence that the answer to Why is it? which states a cause, and the answer to What is it? which states an essence, are identical (APo. II 2, 90a15 19). In this way we come to know the essence of a kind at Stage 3 by discovering the cause of those shared similarities grasped in Stage 1. More importantly for our purposes, we know that the kind exists (Stage 2) once we know that there is a cause of those similarities, even if we do not yet know what that cause is (APo. II 2, 89b37 90a1). We can illustrate this method using a simplified example. Imagine the kind cuttlefish (Sepioidea) was unknown to science. Stage 1 of our inquiry is an empirical investigation aimed at building up a profile of features by establishing correlations among the properties of certain individuals. Lennox (2004, 92) calls these predicate profiles, or loci of co-extensive predication, which are built up by establishing links between universal or general differentiae. For example, through careful observations we come to discover a set of general correlations between having eight arms and two tentacles, a single fin around the full length of the body, an internal gas chamber for regulating buoyancy, chromatophores for rapid colour change, and a jet propulsion system. In this way we build up, through induction, a profile of features that are regularly found together in the same individuals. However, at this preliminary stage of our inquiry we do not yet know whether those shared similarities are evidence of a natural kind or whether these correlations are just a coincidence. This is the task of stage 2. According to APo. II 2, the inquiry into whether or not we have hit upon a natural kind involves asking whether or not there is an underlying cause (or middle term as APo. II 2 puts it) that explains the correlations in our preliminary (Stage 1) account. 27 Once we discover that there is a cause although we do not yet know what that cause is we are justified in believing that we ve got a natural kind. At this point we go on to investigate (in Stage 3) what that cause is. That causally basic feature(s) will correspond to the essence in our complete scientific definition of this newly discovered kind. 28 For Aristotle, then, what makes a group of individuals a genuine kind is its possession of a determinate causal structure, which we come to discover by this empirical method. It follows that, while scientific classification is driven mainly by the explanatory aims of the scientist, there

17 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 213 are constraints on which groups she can select for her inquiry. And these constraints derive from the world rather than from her own proclivities as a classifier. For whether or not some group constitutes a natural kind depends on whether or not their shared attributes actually do result from common causes. And this depends on certain facts about the world that are independent of our interests. In this way, although the joints the biologist chooses to cut along will depend largely on her explanatory aims as a biologist, those joints are prior to her interests. She does not decide where the joints are. It should be clear by now that Aristotle sees the reality of a kind as being strongly connected with its explanatory power, which in turn derives from the causal structure of the world. Real kinds are just those theoretically important groups that have the sort of causal structure that allows them to enter into scientific explanations. Since not all correlations of properties are due to common causes (e.g. GA IV 4, 771b1 13), not all entities that share properties in common will constitute genuine kinds. Coincidental correlations that are not underwritten by common causes will not constitute real kinds and so cannot enter into any scientific explanations (Metaphysics VI 2, XI 8, APo. I 2). The type of explanations that are relevant here are what we might call classificatory explanations. 29 Here we attempt to explain why some feature F belongs to some subject S by classifying S as a member of some wider kind K to which F belongs universally and primitively (APo. I 5), i.e., F is a basic feature of K. The corresponding causal explanation then attempts to demonstrate why F belongs to K by identifying some aspect of K s nature that is causally linked to F. 30 In syllogistic terms, the middle term of a classificatory explanation identifies the wider kind to which the subject in question belongs, while the middle term of the corresponding causal explanation identifies the underlying cause that explains why the feature in question belongs to that wider kind. For example, we explain why deer lack incisors by first classifying them as a form of horn-bearing animal: deer lack incisors because they are horn-bearers (the classificatory explanation). 31 Assuming this feature is a primitive attribute of that wider kind, our inquiry then shifts to the level of horn-bearers and asks what it is about horn-bearing animals as such that explains why they lack of incisors. On Aristotle s account, all horn-bearing animals lack incisors

18 214 DEVIN HENRY because of certain developmental constraints related to the production of the horns (the causal explanation). 32 This further investigation reveals the ultimate cause for why deer lack this feature. For Aristotle, then, classification plays an important role in science because it helps identify the right level at which causal investigations should take place; it helps locate the widest kind to which a given feature belongs universally and primitively (APo. I 4 5, II 14). 33 By consulting the appropriate classification tree, we can see that lacking incisors is a basic feature of horn-bearers. Thus, in order to discover why deer ultimately lack incisors, we must shift our focus to that wider kind and ask what it is about that kind that explains why its members universally lack that property. Clearly the success of this explanatory strategy depends on picking out real kinds with an appropriate causal structure. Aristotelian natural kinds can also be seen to differ from one another in terms of their explanatory power, depending on the number of features that are explained by being a member of that kind. For example, bird has a high degree of explanatory power; it functions as the middle term in a wide range of classificatory explanations. Thus classifying something as a bird helps explain a whole series of facts about it, including its possession of a beak, two backward-bending legs with four separately articulated toes, a crest and a long haunch bone. This makes the kind bird, we might say, highly inductively projectible. 34 The kinds lung-possessor and egglayer also have a relatively high degree of explanatory power to them for the same reason. Horn-bearer, on the other hand, is less explanatory. Being a horn-bearer helps explain why an animal lacks a complete set of teeth (PA 663b25 644a8; APo. 98a13 19), which in turn explains why it produces hard marrow (PA 651b30), and why it has a four-chambered stomach (PA 674a32 4). But it explains very little else about it. Yet each of these still constitutes a natural kind, for their members all share a set of features in common that result from the same underlying causes (the essence). It is in virtue of this fact that such kinds have the explanatory power they do Realism, Pluralism, and Systematics To close this paper I want to draw attention to a further aspect of Aristotle s approach to classification that finds a close parallel with recent trends in contemporary philosophy of biology, namely, its lack of

19 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 215 taxonomic ranks. The aim is to show that Aristotle s biology is not as outmoded as it is often taken to be. On the contrary, it should remain of interest to philosophers and biologists alike insofar as it combines pluralism and realism with a rank-free approach to classification, which many philosophers of biology see as the way forward in systematics. The contemporary theory of pluralistic realism was first introduced in response to a version of the so-called species problem. Philosophers of biology generally distinguish between the species category, which is a rank in the Linnaean hierarchy, and species taxa, which are the particular groups of organisms that biologists rank under that category (e.g. Homo sapiens, Alca torda). In philosophical terms, the distinction is between a general type of thing and its concrete tokens. One version of the species problem concerns the proper definition of the species category. What is it that makes a group of organisms a species rather than, say, a genus or a phylum? A species concept is an attempt to provide an answer to this question by identifying the essential feature(s) that makes all species taxa instances of the species category. The problem arises because working biologists employ a number of competing species concepts. Some identify species in terms of interbreeding criteria, some on the basis of a shared ecological niche, others based on common ancestry (just to name the three most popular concepts). 36 This is problematic for two reasons. First, in many cases different species concepts partition organisms into different and often cross-cutting species taxa. 37 Second, not all species concepts actually manage to capture all the groups that biologists recognize as species. 38 There are two general responses to this problem. Monists argue that only one species concept should be adopted by all biologists and that further philosophical (and empirical) work will eventually reveal the right one. 39 By contrast, pluralists embrace the fact that nature contains many different and irreducible types of species and argue that these cannot be captured by a single, universal species concept. Instead, biologists should recognize a plurality of equally legitimate species concepts, each one of which is useful for investigating a different set of biological relationships. 40 Biologists and philosophers of biology have traditionally drawn an ontological distinction between species, on the one hand, and higher ranks (genera, families, etc.), on the other. While they agree that the higher

20 216 DEVIN HENRY ranks do not correspond to any real divisions in nature, the species category is taken to have ontological significance. In other words, species picks out a real kind of thing. This has been embraced by both monists and pluralists alike. However, some have urged that a commitment to pluralistic realism should actually lead us to doubt the very existence of the species category itself; it entails antirealism about species. Ereshefsky (1998) advocates this position and offers what he calls the heterogeneity argument to support it: In sum, a realistic interpretation of species pluralism one that accepts the existence of different types of species taxa implies that there is no unified ontological category called species. It implies that the species category does not exist. This I take to be the strong argument from species pluralism to the non-existence of the species category. (113) The heterogeneity argument relies on the principle that some category K exists (it is a unified ontological category ) if only if all the members of K share a common property that unifies them as Ks and distinguishes them from all non-ks. Species pluralism holds that there are a number of different kinds of species (interbreeding species, ecological species, phylogenetic species, etc.) but denies that there is any common feature that makes them all instances of a species. Each kind of species is defined by a different essential property. Therefore, the argument goes, the species category fails to pick out a unified ontological category: [T]here is no single unitary species category, but a heterogeneous collection of base taxa referred to by the term species (Ereshefsky 1999, 290). 41 It is important to be clear on what Ereshefsky is suggesting here. He is not an antirealist about those entities biologists call species: The heterogeneous nature of the species category gives us reason to doubt the existence of that category, yet it does not give us reason to doubt the reality of the taxa we call species. 42 Our recognition of a distinction between, say, Cardinalis cardinalis and Cardinalis sinuatus is not an arbitrary boundary imposed on a perfectly continuous world as a result of our own subjective interests. These two groups really do constitute distinct biological entities. Ereshefsky simply rejects the idea that the distinction we make between species, genera, and the other Linnaean ranks corresponds to any ontological distinctions within those taxa themselves. In other words, there is no natural reason for ranking these as species rather than genera or varieties; for those ranks are all artificial. As

21 ARISTOTLE S PLURALISTIC REALISM 217 such, Ereshefsky recommends getting rid of the Linnaean ranks entirely. For Ereshefsky, the way forward is to recognize that there are different types of lineages of greater or lesser inclusiveness, without insisting on their position in some fixed taxonomic hierarchy. This rank-free approach to classification is precisely the approach adopted by Aristotle. One of the main lessons from the work by Balme (1962, 1987) and Pellegrin (1982) is that Aristotle s twin concepts of genos and eidos traditionally translated as genus and species do not designate fixed ranks in any taxonomical hierarchy. In particular, they do not function like genus and species in the modern Linnaean sense. Instead they are relative concepts that can be used to identify groups at any level of inclusiveness in a given division tree. 43 This is why I have insisted on following the more recent conventions of translating genos and eidos as kind and form (of a kind). A genos designates any group at any level of classification that possesses a single common nature and is divisible into forms whose differences are a matter of degree. An eidos is simply one of those divided forms. Thus dogs might be an eidos relative to some wider kind (e.g. four-footed live-bearers) and a genos relative to some more specific forms (e.g. buhunds, sheppards, spaniels, etc.). Some have taken this as evidence that Aristotle is simply inconsistent in how he ranks animals. But for Pellegrin and Balme this is incontrovertible evidence that Aristotle was not interested in taxonomic rankings at all. The kind of plasticity afforded to the concepts of genos and eidos in Aristotle s biological works simply does not sit well with the idea that they were ever meant to pick out fixed ranks in a single taxonomic hierarchy or that they even remotely resemble the modern Linnaean ranks of genus and species. Aristotle s method of classification is free of such ranking concerns. The upshot of looking at things in this way is that the species (category) problem simply disappears. Aristotle has no species problem precisely because he has no concept of a species in our sense. His approach to classification does not involve an attempt to pigeonhole animals into the fixed ranks of some predetermined taxonomic hierarchy. The way he divides animals has no use for such ranks. Thus Aristotle s biology is an interesting case study for Mishler s hypothesis that the current muddle over species concepts is the result of our doomed attempts to shoehorn the diversity of the living world into an outdated and

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] Like David Charles, I am puzzled about the relationship between Aristotle

More information

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code The aim of this paper is to explore and elaborate a puzzle about definition that Aristotle raises in a variety of forms in APo. II.6,

More information

The Birds and the Bees: Aristotle on the Biological Concept of Analogy

The Birds and the Bees: Aristotle on the Biological Concept of Analogy Western University From the SelectedWorks of Devin Henry 2014 The Birds and the Bees: Aristotle on the Biological Concept of Analogy Devin Henry, The University of Western Ontario Available at: https://works.bepress.com/devinhenry/25/

More information

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Commentary Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Laura M. Castelli laura.castelli@exeter.ox.ac.uk Verity Harte s book 1 proposes a reading of a series of interesting passages

More information

An introduction to biological essentialism. John Wilkins Biohumanities Project University of Queensland

An introduction to biological essentialism. John Wilkins Biohumanities Project University of Queensland An introduction to biological essentialism John Wilkins Biohumanities Project University of Queensland An ambiguous term Meaning of essence - what-it-is-to-be Originally tied to substance-form ontology

More information

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) Both the natural and the social sciences posit taxonomies or classification schemes that divide their objects of study into various categories. Many philosophers hold

More information

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015): Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015): 224 228. Philosophy of Microbiology MAUREEN A. O MALLEY Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2014 x + 269 pp., ISBN 9781107024250,

More information

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy METAPHYSICS UNIVERSALS - NOMINALISM LECTURE PROFESSOR JULIE YOO Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy Primitivism Primitivist

More information

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts Normativity and Purposiveness What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts of a triangle and the colour green, and our cognition of birch trees and horseshoe crabs

More information

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT Maria Kronfeldner Forthcoming 2018 MIT Press Book Synopsis February 2018 For non-commercial, personal

More information

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART Tatyana Shopova Associate Professor PhD Head of the Center for New Media and Digital Culture Department of Cultural Studies, Faculty of Arts South-West University

More information

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Introduction Naïve realism regards the sensory experiences that subjects enjoy when perceiving (hereafter perceptual experiences) as being, in some

More information

Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account

Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account Abstract: In this chapter I lay out a notion of philosophical naturalism that aligns with pragmatism. It is developed

More information

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology

The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology The erratically fine-grained metaphysics of functional kinds in technology and biology Massimiliano Carrara Assistant Professor Department of Philosophy University of Padova, P.zza Capitaniato 3, 35139

More information

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Book Review Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values Nate Jackson Hugh P. McDonald, Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values. New York: Rodopi, 2011. xxvi + 361 pages. ISBN 978-90-420-3253-8.

More information

Aristotle s Metaphysics

Aristotle s Metaphysics Aristotle s Metaphysics Book Γ: the study of being qua being First Philosophy Aristotle often describes the topic of the Metaphysics as first philosophy. In Book IV.1 (Γ.1) he calls it a science that studies

More information

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a

In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere) Aristotle makes it clear that his goal in the study of nature is a Comments on Mariska Leunissen s Aristotle s Syllogistic Model of Knowledge and the Biological Sciences: Demonstrating Natural Processes Allan Gotthelf Introduction In Parts of Animals I 1 (and elsewhere)

More information

Aristotle s Categories and Physics

Aristotle s Categories and Physics Aristotle s Categories and Physics G. J. Mattey Winter, 2006 / Philosophy 1 Aristotle as Metaphysician Plato s greatest student was Aristotle (384-322 BC). In metaphysics, Aristotle rejected Plato s theory

More information

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana

Aristotle. By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana Aristotle By Sarah, Lina, & Sufana Aristotle: Occupation Greek philosopher whose writings cover many subjects, including physics, metaphysics, poetry, theater, music, logic, rhetoric, linguistics, politics,

More information

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN: Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, 2013. Pp X -336. $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN: 978-0674724549. Lucas Angioni The aim of Malink s book is to provide a consistent

More information

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative 21-22 April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh Matthew Brown University of Texas at Dallas Title: A Pragmatist Logic of Scientific

More information

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT This article observes methodological aspects of conflict-contractual theory

More information

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn The social mechanisms approach to explanation (SM) has

More information

Aristotle on the Mechanism of Inheritance

Aristotle on the Mechanism of Inheritance Journal of the History of Biology (2006) 39:425 455 Ó Springer 2006 DOI 10.1007/s10739-005-3058-y Aristotle on the Mechanism of Inheritance Department of Philosophy Talbot College The University of Western

More information

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

Predication and Ontology: The Categories Predication and Ontology: The Categories A theory of ontology attempts to answer, in the most general possible terms, the question what is there? A theory of predication attempts to answer the question

More information

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles

Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles Lecture 12 Aristotle on Knowledge of Principles Patrick Maher Scientific Thought I Fall 2009 Introduction We ve seen that according to Aristotle: One way to understand something is by having a demonstration

More information

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas Rachel Singpurwalla It is well known that Plato sketches, through his similes of the sun, line and cave, an account of the good

More information

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 44, 2015 Book Review Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Philip Kitcher

More information

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima Caleb Cohoe Caleb Cohoe 2 I. Introduction What is it to truly understand something? What do the activities of understanding that we engage

More information

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Z.13: Substances and Universals Summary of Zeta so far Z.13: Substances and Universals Let us now take stock of what we seem to have learned so far about substances in Metaphysics Z (with some additional ideas about essences from APst.

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change Ingo Brigandt Department of History and Philosophy of Science 1017 Cathedral of Learning University of Pittsburgh Pittsburgh, PA 15260 E-mail: inb1@pitt.edu

More information

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238. The final chapter of the book is devoted to the question of the epistemological status of holistic pragmatism itself. White thinks of it as a thesis, a statement that may have been originally a very generalized

More information

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. The Republic is intended by Plato to answer two questions: (1) What IS justice? and (2) Is it better to

More information

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson Abstract: Here I m going to talk about what I take to be the primary significance of Peirce s concept of habit for semieotics not

More information

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism James Sage [ jsage@uwsp.edu ] Department of Philosophy University of Wisconsin Stevens Point Science and Values: Holism & REA This presentation

More information

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016 ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS February 5, 2016 METAPHYSICS IN GENERAL Aristotle s Metaphysics was given this title long after it was written. It may mean: (1) that it deals with what is beyond nature [i.e.,

More information

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Anca-Gabriela Ghimpu Phd. Candidate UBB, Cluj-Napoca Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Paper contents Introduction: motivation

More information

THE EVOLUTIONARY VIEW OF SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS Dragoş Bîgu dragos_bigu@yahoo.com Abstract: In this article I have examined how Kuhn uses the evolutionary analogy to analyze the problem of scientific progress.

More information

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring 2014 Russell Marcus Hamilton College Class #4: Aristotle Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction to the Philosophy

More information

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities 1 From Porphyry s Isagoge, on the five predicables Porphyry s Isagoge, as you can see from the first sentence, is meant as an introduction to

More information

Aristotle on the Human Good

Aristotle on the Human Good 24.200: Aristotle Prof. Sally Haslanger November 15, 2004 Aristotle on the Human Good Aristotle believes that in order to live a well-ordered life, that life must be organized around an ultimate or supreme

More information

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal Aristotle 384-322 The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal Pupil of Plato, Preceptor of Alexander 150 books, 1/5 known Stagira 367-347 Academy 347 Atarneus 343-335 Mieza 335-322 Lyceum Chalcis

More information

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Reviewed by Christopher Pincock, Purdue University (pincock@purdue.edu) June 11, 2010 2556 words

More information

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals L C Bargeliotes National and Kapodestrian University of Athens, 157 84 Zografos, Athens, Greece Abstract Aristotle's rejection and reconstruction of

More information

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973 Sonderdrucke aus der Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg RAINER MARTEN Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973 [Rezension] Originalbeitrag

More information

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS The problem of universals may be safely called one of the perennial problems of Western philosophy. As it is widely known, it was also a major theme in medieval

More information

Pluralism is the Answer! What is the Question?

Pluralism is the Answer! What is the Question? Pluralism is the Answer! What is the Question? Marco J. Nathan University of Denver Philosophy and Theory in Biology: Species in the Age of Discordance Abstract This essay provides a critical assessment

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala 1 Forms and Causality in the Phaedo Michael Wiitala Abstract: In Socrates account of his second sailing in the Phaedo, he relates how his search for the causes (αἰτίαι) of why things come to be, pass away,

More information

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Incommensurability and Partial Reference Incommensurability and Partial Reference Daniel P. Flavin Hope College ABSTRACT The idea within the causal theory of reference that names hold (largely) the same reference over time seems to be invalid

More information

Do Universals Exist? Realism

Do Universals Exist? Realism Do Universals Exist? Think of all of the red roses that you have seen in your life. Obviously each of these flowers had the property of being red they all possess the same attribute (or property). The

More information

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses ' 11 Aristotelian Explanation GARETH B. MATTHEWS Jaakko Hintikka's influential paper, "On the Ingredients of an Aristotelian Science,"' suggests an interesting experiment. We should select a bright and

More information

1/10. The A-Deduction

1/10. The A-Deduction 1/10 The A-Deduction Kant s transcendental deduction of the pure concepts of understanding exists in two different versions and this week we are going to be looking at the first edition version. After

More information

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic 1 Reply to Stalnaker Timothy Williamson In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic as Metaphysics between contingentism in modal metaphysics and the use of

More information

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals 206 Metaphysics Universals Universals 207 Universals Universals is another name for the Platonic Ideas or Forms. Plato thought these ideas pre-existed the things in the world to which they correspond.

More information

Scientific Philosophy

Scientific Philosophy Scientific Philosophy Gustavo E. Romero IAR-CONICET/UNLP, Argentina FCAGLP, UNLP, 2018 Philosophy of mathematics The philosophy of mathematics is the branch of philosophy that studies the philosophical

More information

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS NIKOLAY MILKOV THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS The Philosopher must twist and turn about so as to pass by the mathematical problems, and not run up against one, which would have to be solved before

More information

Scientific Revolutions as Events: A Kuhnian Critique of Badiou

Scientific Revolutions as Events: A Kuhnian Critique of Badiou University of Windsor Scholarship at UWindsor Critical Reflections Essays of Significance & Critical Reflections 2017 Apr 1st, 3:30 PM - 4:00 PM Scientific Revolutions as Events: A Kuhnian Critique of

More information

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis BOOK REVIEW William W. Davis Douglas R. Hofstadter: Codel, Escher, Bach: an Eternal Golden Braid. Pp. xxl + 777. New York: Basic Books, Inc., Publishers, 1979. Hardcover, $10.50. This is, principle something

More information

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1) CHAPTER: 1 PLATO (428-347BC) PHILOSOPHY The Western philosophy begins with Greek period, which supposed to be from 600 B.C. 400 A.D. This period also can be classified

More information

Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle s Biology by Allan Gotthelf

Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle s Biology by Allan Gotthelf Teleology, First Principles, and Scientific Method in Aristotle s Biology by Allan Gotthelf Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press, 2012. Pp. xviii + 440. ISBN 978 0 19 928795 6. Cloth $99.00 Reviewed

More information

du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body

du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body Aim and method To pinpoint her metaphysics on the map of early-modern positions. doctrine of substance and body. Specifically, her Approach: strongly internalist.

More information

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato Aristotle Aristotle Lived 384-323 BC. He was a student of Plato. Was the tutor of Alexander the Great. Founded his own school: The Lyceum. He wrote treatises on physics, cosmology, biology, psychology,

More information

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna Kuhn Formalized Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna christian.damboeck@univie.ac.at In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1996 [1962]), Thomas Kuhn presented his famous

More information

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1 Florida Philosophical Society Volume XVI, Issue 1, Winter 2016 105 Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1 D. Gene Witmer, University of Florida Elijah Chudnoff s Intuition is a rich and systematic

More information

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden Seven remarks on artistic research Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden 11 th ELIA Biennial Conference Nantes 2010 Seven remarks on artistic research Creativity is similar

More information

LYCEUM A Publication of the Philosophy Department Saint Anselm College

LYCEUM A Publication of the Philosophy Department Saint Anselm College Volume IX, No. 2 Spring 2008 LYCEUM Aristotle s Form of the Species as Relation Theodore Di Maria, Jr. What Was Hume s Problem about Personal Identity in the Appendix? Megan Blomfield The Effect of Luck

More information

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments. Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring 2014 Hamilton College Russell Marcus Class #3 - Plato s Platonism Sample Introductory Material from Marcus and McEvoy, An Historical Introduction

More information

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable,

It is from this perspective that Aristotelian science studies the distinctive aspects of the various inhabitants of the observable, ARISTOTELIAN COLORS AS CAUSES Festschrift for Julius Moravcsik, edd., D.Follesdall, J. Woods, College Publications (London:2008), pages 235-242 For Aristotle the study of living things, speaking quite

More information

The Object Oriented Paradigm

The Object Oriented Paradigm The Object Oriented Paradigm By Sinan Si Alhir (October 23, 1998) Updated October 23, 1998 Abstract The object oriented paradigm is a concept centric paradigm encompassing the following pillars (first

More information

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA

ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA ABELARD: THEOLOGIA CHRISTIANA Book III excerpt 3.138 Each of the terms same and diverse, taken by itself, seems to be said in five ways, perhaps more. One thing is called the same as another either i according

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

Goldie on the Virtues of Art

Goldie on the Virtues of Art Goldie on the Virtues of Art Anil Gomes Peter Goldie has argued for a virtue theory of art, analogous to a virtue theory of ethics, one in which the skills and dispositions involved in the production and

More information

Conventzionaism in AncientZ Ammerican; Art. 7 I 3 CONVENTIONALISM IN ANCIENT AMERICAN ART.

Conventzionaism in AncientZ Ammerican; Art. 7 I 3 CONVENTIONALISM IN ANCIENT AMERICAN ART. I 887] Conventzionaism in AncientZ Ammerican; Art. 7 I 3 CONVENTIONALISM IN ANCIENT AMERICAN ART. BY J. S. KINGSLEY. THE paper recently published by Prof. F. W. Putnam, under the above title,' is a nice

More information

But, if I understood well, Michael Ruse doesn t agree with you. Why?

But, if I understood well, Michael Ruse doesn t agree with you. Why? ELLIOTT SOBER University of Wisconsin Madison Interviewed by Dr. Emanuele Serrelli University of Milano Bicocca and Pikaia Italian portal on evolution (http://www.pikaia.eu) Roma, Italy, April 29 th 2009

More information

Watching Anna knit, it s clear that the scarf she s making and the yarn

Watching Anna knit, it s clear that the scarf she s making and the yarn Essence and the Grounding Problem Mark Jago In Reality Making, ed. M. Jago, Oxford University Press, 2016, pp. 99 120. Abstract: Pluralists about coincident entities say that distinct entities may be spatially

More information

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver Truth and Tropes by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver Trope theory has been focused on the metaphysics of a theory of tropes that eliminates the need for appeal to universals or properties. This has naturally

More information

CARROLL ON THE MOVING IMAGE

CARROLL ON THE MOVING IMAGE CARROLL ON THE MOVING IMAGE Thomas E. Wartenberg (Mount Holyoke College) The question What is cinema? has been one of the central concerns of film theorists and aestheticians of film since the beginnings

More information

This paper is a near-exact replica of that which appeared in S. Laurence and C. Macdonald

This paper is a near-exact replica of that which appeared in S. Laurence and C. Macdonald 1 This paper is a near-exact replica of that which appeared in S. Laurence and C. Macdonald (eds.), Contemporary Readings in the Foundations of Metaphysics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1998, pp. 329-350.

More information

Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds in Aristotle

Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds in Aristotle Stein, N. 2018. Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds in Aristotle. Metaphysics, 1(1): pp. 33 51, DOI: https://doi.org/10.5334/met.8 RESEARCH Definition and the Epistemology of Natural Kinds

More information

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography Dawn M. Phillips 1 Introduction In his 1983 article, Photography and Representation, Roger Scruton presented a powerful and provocative sceptical position. For most people interested in the aesthetics

More information

1. Introduction. Kathrin Koslicki Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta

1. Introduction. Kathrin Koslicki Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta The Causal Priority of Form in Aristotle Kathrin Koslicki Department of Philosophy, University of Alberta In various texts (e.g., Met. Z.17), Aristotle assigns priority to form, in its role as a principle

More information

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Perceptions and Hallucinations Perceptions and Hallucinations The Matching View as a Plausible Theory of Perception Romi Rellum, 3673979 BA Thesis Philosophy Utrecht University April 19, 2013 Supervisor: Dr. Menno Lievers Table of contents

More information

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In Demonstratives, David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a Appeared in Journal of Philosophical Logic 24 (1995), pp. 227-240. What is Character? David Braun University of Rochester In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions

More information

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes Husserl Stud (2014) 30:269 276 DOI 10.1007/s10743-014-9146-0 Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes De Gruyter, Berlin,

More information

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology

Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology Instantiation and Characterization: Problems in Lowe s Four-Category Ontology Markku Keinänen University of Tampere [Draft, please do not quote without permission] ABSTRACT. According to Lowe s Four-Category

More information

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB In his In librum Boethii de Trinitate, q. 5, a. 3 [see The Division and Methods of the Sciences: Questions V and VI of

More information

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Sidestepping the holes of holism Sidestepping the holes of holism Tadeusz Ciecierski taci@uw.edu.pl University of Warsaw Institute of Philosophy Piotr Wilkin pwl@mimuw.edu.pl University of Warsaw Institute of Philosophy / Institute of

More information

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1 EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA Christos A. Pechlivanidis* The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1 Despite the great interest

More information

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC This part of the book deals with the conditions under which judgments can express truths about objects. Here Kant tries to explain how thought about objects given in space and

More information

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications One and Many in Aristotle s Metaphysics: Books Alpha-Delta. By Edward C. Halper. Las Vegas: Parmenides Publishing, 2009. Pp. xli + 578. $48.00 (hardback). ISBN: 978-1-930972-6. Julie K. Ward Halper s volume

More information

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002) Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002) 168-172. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance

More information

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae Binghamton University The Open Repository @ Binghamton (The ORB) The Society for Ancient Greek Philosophy Newsletter 12-29-1985 The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae Edward Halper University of

More information

How to Fix Kind Membership: A Problem for HPC-Theory and a Solution

How to Fix Kind Membership: A Problem for HPC-Theory and a Solution How to Fix Kind Membership: A Problem for HPC-Theory and a Solution Abstract Natural kinds are often contrasted with other kinds of scientific kinds, especially functional kinds, because of a presumed

More information

Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's <em>the Muses</em>

Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's <em>the Muses</em> bepress From the SelectedWorks of Ann Connolly 2006 Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's the Muses Ann Taylor, bepress Available at: https://works.bepress.com/ann_taylor/15/ Ann Taylor IAPL

More information

Ontological Categories. Roberto Poli

Ontological Categories. Roberto Poli Ontological Categories Roberto Poli Ontology s three main components Fundamental categories Levels of reality (Include Special categories) Structure of individuality Categorial Groups Three main groups

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me

On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 45, 2015 On Aristotelian Universals and Individuals: The Vink that is in Body and May Be In Me IRENA CRONIN University of California, Los Angeles, USA G. E.

More information

Difference and Robustness

Difference and Robustness Rome 14-16 October, 2014 Abstract Difference and Robustness Alfredo Marcos University of Valladolid (Spain) amarcos@fyl.uva.es www.fyl.uva.es/~wfilosof/webmarcos The paper starts by recalling the ordinary

More information