What is Skilled Coping?

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "What is Skilled Coping?"

Transcription

1 Simon Høffding What is Skilled Coping? Experts on Expertise Abstract: The paper uses a phenomenological analysis of interviews with a professional string quartet to critique the notion of skilled coping as used by Hubert Dreyfus. According to Dreyfus, skilled coping is a way of being and acting in which one is immersed in one s actions such that one is not thinking or reflecting. He uses examples from various experts, such a chess-, baseball-, and soccer players, to illustrate this. I argue that his account suffers from a reductive dualism between coping and reflection and further from a lack of clarity. I use my work with the string quartet to illustrate that so-called skilled coping, rather than a distinct phenomenon, is a series of connected mental phenomena that span highly reflective stances as well as trance-like states of absorption. Therefore, I point out that Dreyfus s problematic usage in fact prevents us from appreciating the phenomenological complexity of the absorption of experts. 1. Introduction The purpose of this paper is to investigate and question the notion of skilled coping. The discussion on the nature of skilled coping has re-emerged with the Dreyfus-McDowell debate (Dreyfus, 2007a,b; McDowell, 2007a,b; Schear, 2013), concerning whether reason-giving and conceptual knowledge are essential constituents of consciousness. To strengthen their respective claims, Dreyfus and McDowell make use of examples from various experts, such a chess-, baseball-, and soccer players. The debate focuses on experts because these are Correspondence: Simon Hoffding, Center for Subjectivity Research, Department of Media, Cognition and Communication, University of Copenhagen. simonf@hum.ku.dk Journal of Consciousness Studies, 21, No. 9 10, 2014, pp

2 50 S. HØFFDING taken to exemplify the relation between reflection and smooth bodily coping. From Dreyfus s examples it prima facie seems as if the former impedes the latter, an idea with strong intuitive appeal. It is commonly accepted that overthinking a situation inhibits acting, as also expressed in Balanchine s now classical phrase Don t think dear, just dance. 1 This maxim (Montero, 2010) reduces expert coping to a mindless (Dreyfus, 2013) exclusively bodily activity. Further, the use of experts relative to the maxim informs and pertains to central parts of other debates from (radical) enactivism, embodied cognitive science, and interactionism (Hutto and Myin, 2013; Chemero, 2009; Gallagher, 2005; De Jaegher and Di Paolo, 2007; Colombetti, in press) to phenomenology (Zahavi, 1999; 2005; Legrand, 2007; Colombetti, 2011), ecological psychology (Rietveld, 2008; 2012), sports psychology (Sutton et al., 2011; Geeves et al., 2013), and flow theory (Csikszentmihalyi, 1990; 1997). The current paper focuses on Dreyfus, because he, more or less explicitly, is a central stakeholder in all these debates in offering a conceptual framework of skilled coping. But what precisely is skilled coping? I use interviews with the expert musicians of The Danish String Quartet (DSQ) to give a preliminary answer as well as to expand on, and critique, Dreyfus s position. I will structure the remainder of the paper into three parts. Firstly, I assess Dreyfus s account as three claims on (1) reflection, or detached observation, (2) skilled coping, and (3) their relation. Even though Dreyfus s position contains potent descriptions, I find it lacking in precision and ability to portray the nuances of authentic expert experience. In the next part, I turn to the DSQ and present four different prevalent intentional stances involved in musical performance. I use these four intentional stances in the final part to argue that Dreyfus either must abandon his notion of skilled coping as homogeneous or concede that it only applies to a very limited and extremely rare type of expert experience with little bearing on experts typical phenomenology as experts. The latter not being a convincing option, I conclude that the idea of skilled coping as a homogeneous concept in fact blinds us from appreciating the heterogeneous mental life inherent to expertise, not as theorized, but as lived. [1] See Montero s interesting commentpertaining to this statement (Montero, 2013, p. 316).

3 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? Dreyfus on Skilled Coping Over his career, Hubert Dreyfus has worked out an account of perception, practical knowledge, and our being-in-the-world that challenges computationally inspired accounts. In brief, the latter accounts claim that perception and practical knowledge are fundamentally conceptual and dyadic with a subject standing over and against a number of discrete objects constituting the world. In contradistinction, Dreyfus, drawing on traditional phenomenologists, especially Heidegger, as well as the psychologist J.J. Gibson, develops the idea of skilled coping. When coping skilfully, our world is not perceived as consisting of discrete objects. Rather, we perceive affordances and invitations to act, we are pulled or solicited to certain ways of acting. For example, in order to open and go through a door, I do not perceive the shape and size of the doorknob. Rather, the door affords opening and walking through and, already before reaching it, my hand responds to its solicitation by shaping up to match the knob without me being aware of its doing so. In the following, I will go into greater depth to define skilled coping, its relation to expertise, as well as two possible readings of Dreyfus s position Coping and Reason-Giving The central disagreement in the Dreyfus-McDowell debate is on whether conceptuality and reason-giving are necessary for practical knowledge. McDowell thinks yes and Dreyfus no. Dreyfus deploys cases of expert athletes, chess-players, and fighter-pilots to distil his position on skilled coping: McDowell and Heidegger both agree with Aristotle that practical wisdom is a kind of expertise acquired as second nature. So I suggest that to decide who is right as to whether skilled perception and action must be permeated by conceptual rationality we turn to the phenomena and take a look at how one becomes an expert in any domain, and at what capacities an expert thereby acquires. (Dreyfus, 2005, p. 52) In terms of phenomenological methodology, this passage is of importance. Dreyfus here wants to look at experts as a means such that he can decide on a theoretical issue, the nature of practical knowledge the end. The question of conceptual rationality thus becomes the theoretical framework imposed on the phenomena he sets out to explore, disregarding the possibility that the actual phenomenology of expertise might offer him other and more nuanced options. In my own investigation of the phenomenology of expert musicians I have not found the issue of reason-giving to be of special importance:

4 52 S. HØFFDING undertaking a phenomenological investigation of expert musicianship, I could ask a musician, why are you playing this note in this exact way? or what is the reason you played more loudly in this passage?. Most likely, I would be met with an answer to the effect of well I don t know, that is what is written in the score, I guess I just felt like playing it like that, or that is how we agreed to do it. In other words, asking musicians to retroactively ascribe reasons to their actions does not yield much insight into their phenomenology. I am not arguing for or against reason-giving in practical wisdom. Rather, I contend that the question of reason-giving is unimportant or misapplied if one wants to understand the phenomenology of expertise. If this is so, then Dreyfus s wish to argue for non-conceptual coping skews his account and renders it unnecessarily dualistic. Let me elaborate on this dualism Dreyfus s Dualism Dreyfus claims that our fundamental being-in-the-world consists in a non-conceptual coping. He also acknowledges the importance of conceptually mediated rule-following, for instance when learning a new skill. The dualism derives from his account of the relation between skilled coping and rule-following: We should therefore be suspicious of the cognitivist assumption that as we become experts our rules become unconscious. The actual phenomenon suggests that to become experts we must switch from detached rule-following to a more involved and situation-specific way of coping. (Dreyfus, 2005, p. 52, my italics) We normally cope skilfully in our environment. When we meet unforeseen obstacles, our coping breaks down as we switch to a reflective, conceptual, rule-following strategy. Coping, as bodyschematic (Merleau-Ponty, 2004; Gallagher, 2005), continues in the background (Dreyfus, 2007a, p. 354), but ultimately the primary awareness must be either coping or rule-following. They are opposed, but hopefully supplementary (Dreyfus, 2013, p. 21), which I take to mean that both are needed in an exhaustive account of the mind. Fleshing out this dualism further, Dreyfus s position can be refined into three claims: 1) Rationality is an observation-like, reflective, rule-following, distanced intentionality structured with a subject, objects, and conceptual content. 2) Coping is a distanceless, direct responsiveness to solicitations, not based on rule-following.

5 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? 53 3) Rationality and coping are mutually exclusive, the former inhibiting the latter Rationality In his 2013 essay, Dreyfus names rationality a detached observer (Dreyfus, 2013, p. 34). You intermittently become a detached observer and step back from the world, in which you can no longer act taking a free, distanced orientation (Dreyfus, 2007a, p. 354). The gap from one kind of consciousness to the other is almost unbridgeable, comparable to the hiker, who gets lost, and tries to find his way not through his senses and intuitions, but through the abrupt mediation of a map. He now relates to a different world or a representation of the world using logical inference, rule-following, critical reflection, as well as distancing memory and anticipation. This world of reflection is determinate, unified, namable, and thinkable (Dreyfus, 2007a, p. 360). 2 Looking closer at Dreyfus s work, one can identify at least two versions of coping. The first, and weaker, is the merely non-conceptual. The second, and stronger, is both non-conceptual and mindless a. Coping: The weaker claim In the work before the McDowell-Dreyfus debate, Dreyfus s claims make for the weaker reading: Thus, the pure perceiving of the chess master has a kind of intentional content; it just isn t conceptual content. A bare Given and the thinkable are not our only alternatives. We must accept the possibility that our ground-level coping opens up the world by opening us to a meaningful Given a Given that is nonconceptual but not bare. (Dreyfus, 2005, p. 55) The two primary constituents of the weaker reading are intentional content and a Given. This means that our perceiving, qua intentional content, is about something and in being open to a Given has objects, or at least something object-like. Having something object-like again points back to a perceiving subject which gives us an account that, although stressing affordances and motor-intentionality, [2] Thinking of the work done in the phenomenological tradition on the nature of reflection, lumping it together with observation seems odd. Further, in the phenomenological tradition, one can find work on the nature of reflection that resists Dreyfus s reductive account: if one looks to Eugen Fink, there is a description of reflection, not as self-reifying, but as intensifying pre-reflective self-awareness (Fink, 1992, pp , 128). In Sartre we find the notion of pure reflection (Sartre, 1991, p. 155) which imbues ordinary reflection with extraordinary almost omniscient qualities. Why not recognize that reflection can be much more and can be conceived much more flexibly than as a mere detached observer? (See e.g. Zahavi, 1999, Chapter 10; 2013; Merleau-Ponty, 2004, p. xv.)

6 54 S. HØFFDING structurally is not all that different from a classical, conceptual account. Still, coping is non-reflective and non-conceptual b. Coping: The stronger claim As Dreyfus s debate with McDowell advances, so does the radicalness of his position. He now intends to show that mindedness is the enemy of embodied coping (Dreyfus, 2007a, p. 353) and develops an account that seemingly dispenses with all notions of content, objects, and even the subject: There is no place in the phenomenon of fully absorbed coping for intentional content. (Dreyfus, 2013, p. 28) While coping, one is mindless (Dreyfus, 2007a, p. 353): in responding to solicitations they aren t figuring for a subject as features of the world. When one is bodily absorbed in responding to solicitations there is no thinking subject and there are no features to be thought (ibid., p. 358). But does a mindless experience with no thinking subject, no content, and no objects even qualify as an experience? Does Dreyfus literally mean mindless as in unconscious? Likening coping to an aeroplane pilot staying on course, Dreyfus does claim that there is no experience at all (ibid.), and mentioning Olympic swimmers, he speaks of unconscious coping, the swimmer on auto-pilot, like a sleepwalker (Dreyfus, 2013, p. 38, n. 43). In these statements, Dreyfus seems to claim that there is a kind of coping which is not an experience at all. Hence, such non-experiential events are beyond the limits of a phenomenological method, which is solely concerned with conscious experience. 3 From his writings, however, it is not clear whether mindless coping is exceptional, whether it only is available to experts, and how it relates to weaker cases of coping. I will return to these ambiguities, but for now I ll treat the third claim Mutual exclusion We have already been told that there is no place for mindfulness in absorbed coping. Dreyfus s basic intuition here is that if we reflect on, or monitor, our coping on the go, we degrade its smooth operation: even awareness that things are going well [is] sufficient to break the flow and so produce inferior performance (Dreyfus, 2007b, p. 377, n. 5). From experience, most of us know that some kinds of sustained contemplation can indeed halt our walking and shift our normally world-involving attention. But need it be that all reflection or detached observation necessarily degrades coping? Barbara Montero [3] See also Zahavi (2013).

7 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? 55 has provided a clear empirical case that shows Dreyfus to be mistaken in this regard: here, a classical guitarist finding himself stuck at a certain level of play was only able to improve by directing his attention to his movements (Montero, 2010, p. 112). 4 Montero s demonstration, however, has not affected Dreyfus s position. This is due to a certain impenetrability to counterarguments generated in the constellation of his three claims: if it involves reflection and self-awareness, then it is not expert coping Experts and Non-experts It is now apt to explore how ordinary coping and expert coping are related. Is opening and passing through a door phenomenologically the same as a grand-master moving pawns and kings? We should remember that Dreyfus s primary interest in experts derives from his wish to say something about coping and practical wisdom in general. To specify, although most of us are not grand-masters or fighterpilots, we nevertheless are experts in many ordinary affairs, from dishwashing to keyboard typing. The experts in question serve to magnify the nature of this ordinary coping. Dreyfus does not clearly distinguish the different kinds of coping. On one hand: absorbed coping is not just another name for involved coping (Dreyfus, 2007b, p. 373, my italics); and on the other: A Dasein can be fully absorbed in being a soccer mom, a devoted teacher, a victim of discrimination (Dreyfus, 2013, p. 30, my italics). If a soccer mom qua soccer mom can be fully absorbed, it follows that absorption is not relative to expertise, at least understood in a professional sense. Further, in between absorbed coping and involved coping we find terms such as immersed action in which an ego is involved (Dreyfus, 2007b, p. 374), coping at its best (ibid.), fully absorbed coping (Dreyfus, 2013, p. 28), total absorption (ibid.), and finally as mentioned unconscious coping in which the expert is at his best (ibid., p. 30). Two conclusions can be drawn from the above. Firstly, it seems that on Dreyfus s account, when it comes to the absorption in coping, we should not discriminate between professional experts such as athletes and pilots and everyday experts such as soccer moms. Secondly, it is unclear how many kinds of absorption there are, how they relate, and how they are distinguishable. Before moving on to my own investigations, let me sum up this part of the paper: with the language of affordances and coping, Dreyfus has availed an alternative and powerful account of perception and [4] See also Montero and Evans (2011)

8 56 S. HØFFDING expertise. However, on one hand Dreyfus s picture is dualistic and rigid: even on the weaker account it is impossible for the absorbed coper to be reflectively and conceptually aware of himself and his surroundings. On the other hand, Dreyfus s account is general and imprecise because it is impossible to determine what the different kinds of coping entail on the experiential level and how they relate. Coming out of a debate on reason-giving, Dreyfus does not provide a clear and nuanced understanding of skilled coping. The following, then, can be seen as an attempt to expand and clarify the phenomenology of skilled coping as seen in expert musicians. 3. A Taxonomy of Expertise Dreyfus primarily relies on anecdotes from experts to construct his account. In contrast, I chose to base my phenomenological analyses on interviews. Going from context-relative, qualitative interviews to more universal phenomenological claims, i.e. from individual complex and often contradictory human experience to formal structures of subjectivity, is a methodological minefield. A justification of the transposition of insights from one type of enquiry to the other requires an entire paper in itself. The aim of this paper is different, and instead of proposing even a brief sketch of specific methodological challenges and their resolution, for the time being I will simply presuppose that my interview-obtained data are applicable to the domain of phenomenological philosophy. For about two years, I have been following the DSQ through a number of concerts and tours during which I have conducted in-depth interviews with each of the members concerning their experience of playing their instrument. From these interviews, I have collected data that directly pertain to Dreyfus s claims about skilled coping. My strategy from here is, based on direct quotations from the DSQ, to describe four more or less distinct intentional stances, all of which could be considered instances of skilled coping. I bring out their differences and similarities in order to show the following: since they significantly differ and since they equally qualify as acts of skilled coping, it follows that the very term skilled coping is too general to be of value: the unified term thus prevents, rather than furthers, any real understanding of the phenomenon in question. Interviewing the DSQ reveals significant differences in perception of how one should focus (or not focus) while playing, how one should practise and how significant immersion and concentration are to the overall effort. In other words, there is little consensus on even the

9 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? 57 most basic aspects of music and musicianship. Thorough analysis, however, reveals certain general patterns in the musical mind. Below, I categorize some of these into four distinct kinds of musical intentionality. Such distinct boxes do not do justice to the complexity of the mentality in question and they should therefore be understood as overlapping and as a matter of degree rather than of determinate type. Further, this particular diagram is one of many possible and used primarily as a heuristic to facilitate at least a superficial understanding of expert, musical intentionality. 2 Absent-minded playing Figure 1. Expert musicians intentionality in four categories Standard playing 1 Standard playing 4 Absorbed playing 4a Playing under stress/fighting to get back Trance/lack of self-awareness Ex-stasis/distance/ spectatorial awareness Standard playing is a very wide concept covering the kind of mentality in which the DSQ-members most often find themselves. They do not give much explicit expression to its nature, exactly for that reason. It can easily oscillate between bored, another-day-at-the-job, absent-minded playing, and more concentrated, absorbed playing. Frederik Ø, 6 one of the two violinists, puts it in the following words: 4b 3 [5] Besides these basic categories, one can make a more elaborate version describing how musicians in various ways move between these and under what circumstances. This is unfortunately beyond the scope of the present paper. [6] I add Ø, the first letter of the violinist Frederik s surname, to his name to help distinguish him from Fredrik, who is the cellist.

10 58 S. HØFFDING But you can perhaps say that what we re striving for at a technical level, that is to be that it is coming by itself and that you are not too aware of it, that you do not spend any energy on it, that you just have this that it is coming by itself, but that you are aware of it maintaining itself, that there is this little control Frederik Ø is here giving voice to the kind of agency that marks standard playing. All four DSQ-members mention something along the lines of playing as you want to indicating a correspondence between expectation and execution of the musical phrase or piece. When this match exists, attention can be directed somewhere else than on the execution, which is why one rarely comes across detailed expressions of the actual standard playing: There were no bumps on that road It was very smooth. I could do as I wished to. Attention is then directed away from technical, sensorimotor aspects of the performance (besides, in Frederik Ø s case, this little control ) and can go to all sorts of places: looking at the audience, looking at the score, looking at the other DSQ-members, listening, enjoying, imagining, performing mental tricks to enhance musical expression, or being absentminded. To speak more directly to Dreyfus s thesis, this attention can both be of what would match his understanding of affordances, such as suddenly being pulled into a new musical idea, but it certainly can also be of a much more reflective nature: Frederik Ø, while playing, can imagine how he might want to play an occurrent passage in a different fashion later on, and Rune, the other violinist, lays claim to paradigmatic cases of reflective self-awareness, asking himself, while performing, how is my current facial expression?, what am I conveying right now?, or how is my page-turning? without this interfering with his level of musical expression. 7 In conclusion, standard playing can be expressed as the default mode of performing, when the music, circumstances, or performance are not overly challenging, 8 when the musicians are not overly distracted or absent-minded, or when they are not deeply concentrated on or absorbed into the task at hand. [7] See also Michael, Overgaard and Christensen (2013) and Christensen et al. (2013) for an account of the integration of complex cognition with basic embodied responses. [8] See Csikszentmihalyi (1997, p. 30) for thoughts on the relation between flow and feeling challenged.

11 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? Absent-minded playing Once in a while, the DSQ-members get distracted or absent-minded. Frederik Ø calls this going to Netto, 9 such that you for some time mentally leave the performance to think about something as trivial as what you might need to shop for later. Asbjørn expresses it as follows: It could be like if you are driving and then have driven or suddenly find yourself someplace else on the road, that you suddenly are 500 metres further down the highway and cannot recollect having driven those 500 metres. 10 Both Frederik Ø and Asbjørn confirm that absentminded playing is just like normal absent-mindedness, as when one cannot remember whether one has locked the front door, where one s keys are placed, etc. While playing, and seemingly without detracting much from the quality of the performance, the mind wanders somewhere else and thus exhibits an intentionality distinctively different from that of standard playing in which one is intentionally directed towards some aspect of the performance. Except for Fredrik, the cellist, the DSQ-members recognize that this mode of awareness is distinctively different from the other absent-mindedness-like experience of absorption and is unlikely to lead to anything of particular experiential or artistic value. 3. Playing under stress/fighting to get back Certain situations can impose a great deal of stress on the musicians, which prevents the kind of effortless execution, already described as standard playing. These are the bumps or obstacles not experienced in normal situations and can take the form of physical or mental disturbances/irritations/pains or derive from a noisy or inattentive audience. Rune, one of the violinists, gives an example: In the Nielsen string quartet it was not a good experience to play this piece of music. You entered a kind of to hell with it -like [mood], which is not very good when you have to play music. It became pure survival and I had these frustrated thoughts in my head, partly because of my own play, partly because I know we can do it better. It is not the kind of result I could have wished for. Far from it actually. And it was such a strange feeling, because I entered and kind of, it is often such that if you don t feel it is going well, then you [9] Netto is a Danish grocery chain store. [10] This example has striking similarity with Armstrong s absent-minded truck driver. See Armstrong (1981).

12 60 S. HØFFDING start thinking about here we are not together, here it is not in tune, such that you begin to look for errors and once on this track, then it is hard for me to make my way back. The intentional stance here is more one of pure survival, of trying to make one s way back to standard playing, often leading to an overly technical focus or a reflective attention to specific body-parts aching, functioning improperly, or to aspects of the performance not working optimally. There is a mismatch between expectation and execution preventing the freedom experienced in standard playing from unfolding. While playing under stress often leads to a more technical and reflective attention, it need not always be so. In some instances, pure survival should be taken in a much more literal sense. Asbjørn describes it as: fight or flight Like if you are running for your life. This mind-state cannot be characterized as reflective, but rather as just barely keeping up without missing the notes, yet nevertheless coping, managing to perform without mistakes. Even if it is unpleasant or a state of panic it is still coping. Another example occurred at a particular performance of Beethoven string quartet no. 15 A minor, 3 rd movement, which is a very long (easily 15 minutes) and slow movement, incredibly fragile and requiring a strong sustained concentration on the part of the musicians and audience: a member of the audience sitting just behind the two violins wanted to leave due to coughing, but instead fell flat and very loudly on the church floor, causing genuine shock in both audience and musicians. The DSQ almost interrupted their performance, but went on, now with the daunting task of rebuilding the sense of concentration in the room. Here is an extract of Fredrik s experience of the accident: [Fredrik] Yes, I got a shock. I did, and I, and I, like you say, was pulled out of the experience. And actually had a hard time coming back in again. [Interviewer] OK, can you try to describe how it was difficult to get back in again? [Fredrik] The problem was the focus disappeared to something outside of our quartet-community. And I clearly remember that I was paying attention to all kinds of sounds and things that happened and reactions in the audience at the time. And I somehow had some of my focus removed from our quartet-play to something out there in the hall and it was kind of difficult to turn the gaze back inside myself and come back But the concentration simply disappeared, not

13 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? 61 just from us, but from the audience and it is evident that there you also have quite a task when the audience is no longer directing focus on us, then it also becomes difficult for us to get it [back]. In that case, we have to seize it and that is something entirely different. The three other DSQ-members express a similar experience of the event. Even so, after a few seconds of musical confusion, the playing continued seamlessly. In my opinion, the technical musical output was not much different from an instance of standard playing, even if the DSQ-members own experiences were of a radically different nature. As Fredrik expresses, they were intensively focusing on trying to get back to standard playing, or even to a more immersed state from whence they seemed to come prior to the accident. They were forcefully concentrating, yet knowing the futility of the effort as absorption is not something one can enter forcefully or at will: you can try to bring yourself in the right circumstances, mood, and concentration, but there is an inherent kind of passivity in absorption, meaning that you have to let it come by itself, which points back to Frederik Ø s statement about standard playing. There are many kinds of stressors that can cause the state of mind in question. The above-mentioned is quite unusual. It is instructive, however, as it is clearly different from both standard playing and absent-minded playing. Being an amateur musician and having known the DSQ for over ten years, the past two with sustained and intense observations, I find myself unable to detect whether a particular performance instantiates standard playing or playing under unusual stress, although I certainly could infer it in the above-mentioned case. One may have an impression of a particular performance being of higher or lower quality, but this is by no means necessarily connected to the musicians being under stress. It might be that an expert musician knowing the DSQ intimately could detect a difference between stressful and standard playing, but on the other hand, the musicians are performers trained to play their best no matter the circumstances. Alternatively, one might argue that coping is not really a question of a physical performance, but rather concerns a specific subjective quality of consciousness. The present paper, however, is rejecting this proposal and arguing that coping cannot be reduced to a single mental state but rather shows up in different types of awareness. What I will mention later under absorbed playing might indeed possess such a distinguishing subjective quality, but, as I shall show in the conclusion, it would be problematic

14 62 S. HØFFDING to reduce all forms of coping to just this rare kind of experience. Since performance is not seemingly degraded or enhanced relative to the three kinds of playing mentioned so far, stressful performance included, it is reasonable to claim that all three are instances of skilled coping. 4. Absorbed playing Like the other kinds of playing that shade off into one another, absorbed playing occurs on a continuum. But most musicians I have interviewed recollect one, or a very few, particular instances of very deep absorption. Most can recall the exact time and place and the deep absorption is of great significance to them on a personal level. Although the recollection of the existence of the experience is clear, the accompanying expression of its nature is quite to the contrary. Phenomenologically, a description of absorbed playing is challenging, because much of the subject object structuring intentionality seems to be changed or blurred in accord with Dreyfus s claims. There are only vague contours of intentional objects sometimes to the extent that the experience completely blurs, also described as a total lack of awareness, a blackout, a trance, or even that it wasn t the musician himself who played (Bastian, 1987). Examining this experience in some depth, however, I have also come across another quality of quasi-ecstatic self-observation (4b in the diagram). I shall briefly sketch these two: 4A. Lack of self-awareness/trance The claim to a loss of self-awareness can be found in all kinds of artistic experiences (e.g. Bastian, 1987; Meinertz, 2008). To a phenomenologist, this experience is particularly interesting, because losing self-awareness, qua the minimal self as an essential feature of consciousness (see Zahavi, 2005; 2011a), would entail unconsciousness and clearly a performing musician is not unconscious. Here follows an excerpt with Fredrik on his experience of disappearing : [Fredrik] The deeper you are in, the less you observe the world around you and I had this especially powerful experience where I completely disappeared. I remember that it was an incredibly pleasant feeling in the body. And it was incredibly strange to come back and at that point I spent a few seconds to realize where I had been. I had been

15 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? 63 completely gone and with no possibility of observing It was this intense euphoric joy. 11 [Interviewer] OK, but if you are certain of having played, you cannot have been completely gone, so you must have known that you were playing, or? [Fredrik] Weeell in this case I cannot completely answer you. You can say that it was easy for me to figure out that I had played at the time I was finished. [Interviewer] But how can it be that it was easy for you to figure out? [Fredrik] Well because there was still, you can hear a bit of resonance in the room and you kind of feel Wow, now I have been playing. [Interviewer] Neither can you remember what you were playing? [Fredrik] Yes I can. Because I know that I was practising Bach 5 th suite. And that is quite long. There is the overture and the fugue that together take 6 7 minutes. So I have probably been starting it. [Interviewer] You can remember starting it? [Fredrik] Yes. And the in the course of, I have been playing and playing, and then in the course of the 6 7 minutes, I have just disappeared somewhere. From Fredrik s description, it seems that his primary mode of recollective access to the absorbed experience is a kind of retroactive inference. 12 Of the actual experience, all he can remember is that there was a pleasant bodily sensation. He remembers beginning, and once there were no more notes in the piece, it seems as if he woke up. I cannot go further into a phenomenological interpretation of the experience, but for present purposes note that, prima facie, this experience fits Dreyfus s idea of absorbed coping without subjects and objects. Here, I interject that although Fredrik mentions often experiencing deep absorption, he has only once (having played for no less than 25 [11] Fredrik is inconsistent in that being completely gone or completely disappeared is incompatible with a powerful experience or an incredibly pleasant feeling. As a minimum it seems acceptable to claim that aspects of his experience were so altered that he was unable to recognize himself as being the subject of it in a conventional sense. [12] Dreyfus mentions the same, see Dreyfus (2005, p. 54).

16 64 S. HØFFDING years) experienced this paradigmatic occurrence that we could call total absorption. Consequently, the question to Dreyfus is whether he wants to restrict absorbed coping to such rare occurrences. Again, parallel to the three other modes of playing, there are no clear indications that this kind of absorption either increases or detracts from the overall aesthetic quality of the output. Many musicians, Asbjørn as a case in point, 13 believe in a correspondence between depth of absorption and aesthetic expression, but I would not know how to qualify or disqualify this belief, which appeals to aesthetic judgment. 4B. Ex-stasis/distance/spectatorial awareness As can be seen from the above, very deep absorption is difficult to account for phenomenologically. It certainly does not make it simpler that the experience on occasions also is expressed in terms seemingly contrary to the idea of a lack of self-awareness. Here follows two descriptions from Asbjørn (whose set expression for deep absorption is being in the zone ) and Frederik Ø respectively: You are both less conscious and a lot more conscious I think. Because I still think that if you re in the zone, then I know how I m sitting on the chair, I know if my knees are locked, I know if I am flexing my thigh muscle, I know if my shoulders are lifted, I know if my eyes are strained, I know who is sitting on the first row, I know more or less what they are doing, but it is somewhat more, like disinterested, neutrally registering, I am not like inside, I am not kind of a part of the set-up, I am just looking at it, while I m in the zone. But if I m not in the zone, I become a co-player, I become a part of the whole thing. And cannot look at it like a bird over the waters. I become conscious of things because I am not part of them to the same extent 14 It is not a primitive control. It is a kind of very deep control. Ur-control. You really feel like a warlord deploying the troops and control it in a way and it gives a kick that you are just a kind of pure superiority and pure control. [13] Even more interesting: Frederik Ø actively shuns very deep absorption because he thinks it distorts the sound in being overly emotional. The relation between absorption and intensity of emotion is another interesting question to pursue. [14] The transcription here is ambiguous and should be understood as follows: In the zone, Asbjørn becomes conscious of things as standing out to him, open to disinterested, neutral registration. When not in the zone, he is more immersed a part of the set-up or a part of the whole thing. This seems to go against Dreyfus s basic idea of absorbed coping as distanceless.

17 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? 65 Asbjørn s sense of ex-static, disinterested, observation and selfobservation and the sense of clear and pure superior control that ensues is interesting. Phenomenally, it is in strong contradistinction to Fredrik s sense of total absorption. Frederik Ø, who otherwise actively shuns experiences of deep absorption, has nevertheless had the following experience while playing the slow 3 rd movement of Beethoven s string quartet no. 15 A minor: [Frederik Ø] So it is exactly both being present and not being present simultaneously, such that you ooor it is hard to explain it is kind of the feeling that the possibilities, but you don t take heed of each possibility it is like the feeling of looking over a large landscape and knowing that this landscape consists of insects and branches and roots and all kinds of things building up the whole thing, but you cannot see the individual parts, you just know that all of it contributes to the being and that you actually could affect the little things, but you don t want to because you want everything to be there and contribute. But there are nevertheless somehow two tracks running. An awareness of what you are doing and an awareness of what you would like or what you could do, or can do it a little or. [Interviewer] But how about what you describe with Beethoven, are you still in those two levels, or is it entirely different, or? [Frederik Ø] My sense is that things get somewhat dissolved once you get that far out. It is like, it becomes completely open, it goes mostly towards that one, in which you have no sense of what is happening, where it is only the other track [of what you could do]. But there has to be, something mechanical is happening after all, you are moving your fingers after all, so there must be some part of the head which is there. But the awareness of it disappears. Frederik Ø shared with Asbjørn the exact contradiction that you are both more conscious / present and less conscious / not present at the same time, pointing to a fundamental inability to understand and adequately express the nature of this experience. Further, they share the sense of non-involvement and distance ( disinterested, neutral registering / bird over the water / looking over a landscape you don t

18 66 S. HØFFDING want to interfere with ), 15 a freedom of not being caught up with details, and a future-oriented, open expectation ( warlord deploying troops / only awareness of the track yielding a sense of possibility ). This kind of ex-stasis challenges Dreyfus s thesis that absorption is phenomenally distanceless. Absorbed coping is clearly more complex than a mere dismantling of subject and object structures (if such is even possible). Rather, subtle changes in awareness are taking place that can be experienced both as a loss of and a heightened sense of being a subject. The confluence of the absorbed and the ecstatic is fascinating, but deserves a paper in itself. What is of importance is to dismantle the speculation that would reduce absorption to a kind of absent-mindedness. Besides Fredrik, who in an interesting way is able to utilize absent-mindedness or daydreaming as a path to absorption, the other DSQ-members believe very clearly that they are able to distinguish the two states. Such distinguishability justifies labelling absorbed playing even if it has two forms a distinct kind of intentionality on a par with the other three. Absorption in the sense of lack of selfawareness (4a) of course is absent-minded in the sense that there seemingly is an absence of mind, which cannot be located in retrospective memory. Absent-minded playing, as in going to Netto (2), however, is not absent in the sense of being nowhere, but in the sense of being absent from the occurrent situation by having gone somewhere else, daydreaming. It may be hard to retrospectively access the content of one s mind at the time, and it indeed can be quite blurry, but it nevertheless is usually possible to trace as having been somewhere else, e.g. in Netto. In other words, the phenomenological distinction between absent-mindedness (2) and absorption (4a) hinges on the respective presence or absence of an intentional object. In 4a the intentional object seems to have blurred to the extent that it no longer has the boundaries we normally associate with an object. 4. Csikszentmihalyi, Flow, and Coping Before concluding, it is worth digressing to the well-known idea of flow as developed by Csikszentmihalyi and seeing how it might accommodate Dreyfus s idea and the interview data presented. I am motivated to do this by the potential objection that Csikszentmihalyi s ideas can already account for Dreyfus s notion of skilled coping and reflection, combined with the presented interview data, and hence that [15] See Hurlburt (2011) for a number of highly interesting and similar findings.

19 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? 67 I am not presenting anything original. Let me show why this is not the case. To Csikszentmihalyi: The metaphor of flow is one that many people have used to describe the sense of effortless action they feel in moments that stand out as the best in their lives (1997, p. 29). Flow can be experienced in programming a computer, reading a good book, closing a business deal (ibid.), or having a nice dinner conversation with friends (Csikszentmihalyi, 1990, p. 71), and is loosely defined as being full of experiences that are in harmony with each other (ibid.) or even wider as joy, creativity, the process of total involvement with life (ibid., p. xi). On the one hand, there clearly are overlaps between flow and coping; on the other hand, it is difficult to make an expedient comparison, because Csikszentmihalyi as a psychologist uses a different language and has different aims than those presented in this paper. For instance, although Csikszentmihalyi works on both consciousness, the self, and the body (ibid., Chapter 2 and 5), his discussions are understandably often of a more normative and psychologically prescriptive character in so far as he is concerned with Finding Flow (1997, title). 16 More importantly, he does not appear to be concerned with the role of the reflective and the pre-reflective in the flow. Nevertheless, it is worth taking a look at his flow chart. Figure 2. Flowchart from Csikszentmihalyi (1990, p. 74). [16] For instance, Csikszentmihalyi writes: Whenever information disrupts consciousness by threatening its goals we have a condition of inner disorder, or psychic entropy, a disorganization of the self that impairs its effectiveness. Prolonged experiences of this kind can weaken the self to the point that it is no longer able to invest attention and pursue its goals (1990, p. 37). It is quite clear that although words such as consciousness and self occur, the way they can be disrupted, impaired, effective, or weakened points to a more normatively and less transcendentally and formally oriented position than that of phenomenology. Therefore, a substantial amount of analysis of the exact implication of the central terms in both traditions would have to be undertaken before any comprehensive comparison could be made.

20 68 S. HØFFDING As shown above, the relation between perceived challenge and perceived skill is fundamental to the notion of flow. Let us first see how the chart matches Dreyfus s ideas and then see how it accommodates the interview-based taxonomy of absorption. We might identify the diagonal flow line with skilled coping and the upper left triangle, anxiety, with reflection. The lower right triangle boredom could also be subsumed under coping by virtue of not being primarily reflective. As for my own taxonomy, anxiety would prima facie equate to playing under stress (3) and boredom would correspond to absent-minded playing (2). The flow channel would then be standard playing (1) or even absorbed playing (4). This accommodation, however, is too superficial. Coping cannot equate to flow: by virtue of taking place in standard, absent-minded, and stressful playing, coping by implication is taking place in all three categories of the flow chart, perhaps with the exception of an overwhelming anxiety or stress causing the performance to break down altogether. Equating anxiety/stress with reflection is not univocally correct either. One of the descriptions of stressful play is pure survival. As mentioned, this can in rare instances literally mean experiencing a sense of panic, a panic of not being able to keep up, comparable to running for one s life, which is hardly of a reflective nature. 17 When it comes to the relation between a sense of challenge and flow, my taxonomy again is at odds with Csikszentmihalyi s chart: in the example discussed in 4a of lack of self-awareness, Fredrik was alone in a studio playing a movement of a Bach cello-suite. It was not a situation that would be perceived as particularly challenging and nevertheless it gave rise to one of the starkest experiences of absorption. What can be concluded from the above, then, seems to reinforce my general point: when considered somewhat superficially, Dreyfus s ideas combined with my four distinctions fit Csikszentmihalyi s chart rather well. But, once we go into greater detail, it no longer matches up so neatly. Firstly, the notion of coping is much wider than that of flow, because coping goes on both in cases of relative anxiety and in boredom. Secondly, the presented understanding of absorption (4a and 4b) does not fit flow either, on the one hand because it can occur in situations that are seemingly non-challenging, and on the other [17] On the other hand, playing under stress might lead one to think and worry about upcoming difficult passages, in which case it would be of a more reflective nature. Equating anxiety/stress with reflection is not univocally correct because it takes a more detailed analysis to spell out the relation between different kinds of anxiety/stress and different kinds of reflection. See Zahavi (1999, Part I) and Zahavi (2011b) for systematic work on reflection.

21 WHAT IS SKILLED COPING? 69 because absorption is much too rare to fit Csikszentmihalyi s descriptions of having a nice dinner conversation or reading a book. Further, Csikszentmihalyi s description of flow is phenomenologically uniform, while absorption can be both trance-like (4a) and ex-static (4b). Perhaps it could be said that flow is a kind of emotion. Coping, however, is a structure of subjectivity, irreducible to any emotion, that allows for a kind of bodily unfolding; a structure composed of different, but connected, intentional stances. Some of these, then, can give rise to the emotion of flow. 5. Conclusion Now, let us return to the outset and look at Dreyfus s three main claims in the light of the above analysis: 1) Rationality is an observation-like, reflective, rule-following, distanced intentionality structured with a subject, objects, and conceptual content. 2) Coping is a distanceless, direct responsiveness to solicitations, not based on rule-following. 3) Rationality and coping are mutually exclusive, the former inhibiting the latter. To point one: most kinds of coping I have described are not instances of detached observation. However, the ex-static absorption described seems to fit quite well with the idea of detached and distanced observation. The existence of this kind of absorption contradicts Dreyfus s framework in that it includes a kind of detached observation and a clear subject object distinction. For point two, I have presented the rare case of lack of self-awareness (4a) which seemingly fits Dreyfus s strong version of coping. However, I have presented three other distinct kinds of playing or coping (standard, absent-minded, and stressed) and further a kind of deep absorption (ex-static) that is not distanceless and that is structured with intentional objects presented to the subject. With regard to point three, I have provided examples of Frederik Ø and Rune engaging in high-level reflection while playing. I am not denying that there are kinds of reflection that hinder smooth execution, but the general claim that they are mutually exclusive is not true. If reflection degraded expert coping, why would musicians willingly reflect while playing? If Dreyfus is correct here, it would entail that the experts themselves are not able to tell what kind of mental activity improves or degrades their coping.

Musical Immersion What does it amount to?

Musical Immersion What does it amount to? Musical Immersion What does it amount to? Nikolaj Lund Simon Høffding The problem and the project There are many examples of literature to do with a phenomenology of music. There is no literature to do

More information

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content Book review of Schear, J. K. (ed.), Mind, Reason, and Being-in-the-World: The McDowell-Dreyfus Debate, Routledge, London-New York 2013, 350 pp. Corijn van Mazijk

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION Submitted by Jessica Murski Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University

More information

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers Cast of Characters X-Phi: Experimental Philosophy E-Phi: Empirical Philosophy A-Phi: Armchair Philosophy Challenges to Experimental Philosophy Empirical

More information

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95. 441 Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95. Natika Newton in Foundations of Understanding has given us a powerful, insightful and intriguing account of the

More information

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden Seven remarks on artistic research Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden 11 th ELIA Biennial Conference Nantes 2010 Seven remarks on artistic research Creativity is similar

More information

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press. Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (4) 640-642, December 2006 Michael

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics REVIEW An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics Nicholas Davey: Unfinished Worlds: Hermeneutics, Aesthetics and Gadamer. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2013. 190 pp. ISBN 978-0-7486-8622-3

More information

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education Marilyn Zurmuehlen Working Papers in Art Education ISSN: 2326-7070 (Print) ISSN: 2326-7062 (Online) Volume 2 Issue 1 (1983) pps. 56-60 Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Karin de Boer Angelica Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant

More information

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING Language shapes the way we think, and determines what we can think about. BENJAMIN LEE WHORF, American Linguist A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING TERMS & CONCEPTS The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the

More information

observation and conceptual interpretation

observation and conceptual interpretation 1 observation and conceptual interpretation Most people will agree that observation and conceptual interpretation constitute two major ways through which human beings engage the world. Questions about

More information

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany Internal Realism Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany Abstract. This essay characterizes a version of internal realism. In I will argue that for semantical

More information

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM Section II: What is the Self? Reading II.5 Immanuel Kant

More information

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008 490 Book Reviews between syntactic identity and semantic identity is broken (this is so despite identity in bare bones content to the extent that bare bones content is only part of the representational

More information

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment First Moment: The Judgement of Taste is Disinterested. The Aesthetic Aspect Kant begins the first moment 1 of the Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment with the claim that

More information

Affect, perceptual experience, and disclosure

Affect, perceptual experience, and disclosure Philos Stud (2018) 175:2125 2144 https://doi.org/10.1007/s11098-017-0951-0 Affect, perceptual experience, and disclosure Daniel Vanello 1 Published online: 21 July 2017 Ó The Author(s) 2017. This article

More information

1/10. The A-Deduction

1/10. The A-Deduction 1/10 The A-Deduction Kant s transcendental deduction of the pure concepts of understanding exists in two different versions and this week we are going to be looking at the first edition version. After

More information

Phenomenology Glossary

Phenomenology Glossary Phenomenology Glossary Phenomenology: Phenomenology is the science of phenomena: of the way things show up, appear, or are given to a subject in their conscious experience. Phenomenology tries to describe

More information

CHILDREN S CONCEPTUALISATION OF MUSIC

CHILDREN S CONCEPTUALISATION OF MUSIC R. Kopiez, A. C. Lehmann, I. Wolther & C. Wolf (Eds.) Proceedings of the 5th Triennial ESCOM Conference CHILDREN S CONCEPTUALISATION OF MUSIC Tânia Lisboa Centre for the Study of Music Performance, Royal

More information

1. What is Phenomenology?

1. What is Phenomenology? 1. What is Phenomenology? Introduction Course Outline The Phenomenology of Perception Husserl and Phenomenology Merleau-Ponty Neurophenomenology Email: ka519@york.ac.uk Web: http://www-users.york.ac.uk/~ka519

More information

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict Luke Brunning CONTENTS 1 The Integration Thesis 2 Value: Singular, Plural and Personal 3 Conflicts of Desire 4 Ambivalent Identities 5 Ambivalent Emotions

More information

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 5 September 16 th, 2015 Malevich, Kasimir. (1916) Suprematist Composition. Gaut on Identifying Art Last class, we considered Noël Carroll s narrative approach to identifying

More information

A Guide to Paradigm Shifting

A Guide to Paradigm Shifting A Guide to The True Purpose Process Change agents are in the business of paradigm shifting (and paradigm creation). There are a number of difficulties with paradigm change. An excellent treatise on this

More information

Aristotle on the Human Good

Aristotle on the Human Good 24.200: Aristotle Prof. Sally Haslanger November 15, 2004 Aristotle on the Human Good Aristotle believes that in order to live a well-ordered life, that life must be organized around an ultimate or supreme

More information

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis Keisuke Noda Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy Unification Theological Seminary New York, USA Abstract This essay gives a preparatory

More information

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Introduction Naïve realism regards the sensory experiences that subjects enjoy when perceiving (hereafter perceptual experiences) as being, in some

More information

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation Cogent Science in Context: The Science Wars, Argumentation Theory, and Habermas. By William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009. Pp. 355. Cloth, $40. Paper, $20. Jeffrey Flynn Fordham University Published

More information

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics REVIEW A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics Kristin Gjesdal: Gadamer and the Legacy of German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. xvii + 235 pp. ISBN 978-0-521-50964-0

More information

Article On the Nature of & Relation between Formless God & Form: Part 2: The Identification of the Formless God with Lesser Form

Article On the Nature of & Relation between Formless God & Form: Part 2: The Identification of the Formless God with Lesser Form 392 Article On the Nature of & Relation between Formless God & Form: Part 2: The Identification of the Formless God Steven E. Kaufman * ABSTRACT What is described in the second part of this work is what

More information

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism THE THINGMOUNT WORKING PAPER SERIES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF CONSERVATION ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism by Veikko RANTALLA TWP 99-04 ISSN: 1362-7066 (Print) ISSN:

More information

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

What is the Object of Thinking Differently? Filozofski vestnik Volume XXXVIII Number 3 2017 91 100 Rado Riha* What is the Object of Thinking Differently? I will begin with two remarks. The first concerns the title of our meeting, Penser autrement

More information

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts Normativity and Purposiveness What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts of a triangle and the colour green, and our cognition of birch trees and horseshoe crabs

More information

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Mind, Thinking and Creativity Mind, Thinking and Creativity Panel Intervention #1: Analogy, Metaphor & Symbol Panel Intervention #2: Way of Knowing Intervention #1 Analogies and metaphors are to be understood in the context of reflexio

More information

Investigating subjectivity

Investigating subjectivity AVANT Volume III, Number 1/2012 www.avant.edu.pl/en 109 Investigating subjectivity Introduction to the interview with Dan Zahavi Anna Karczmarczyk Department of Cognitive Science and Epistemology Nicolaus

More information

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge Stance Volume 4 2011 A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge ABSTRACT: It seems that an intuitive characterization of our emotional engagement with fiction contains a paradox, which

More information

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense Philosophical Psychology, 2015 http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2015.1010197 REVIEW ESSAY Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense Clare Batty The First Sense: A Philosophical

More information

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright Forthcoming in Disputatio McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright In giving an account of the content of perceptual experience, several authors, including

More information

A Condensed View esthetic Attributes in rts for Change Aesthetics Perspectives Companions

A Condensed View esthetic Attributes in rts for Change Aesthetics Perspectives Companions A Condensed View esthetic Attributes in rts for Change The full Aesthetics Perspectives framework includes an Introduction that explores rationale and context and the terms aesthetics and Arts for Change;

More information

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding. Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding. Jessica Leech Abstract One striking contrast that Kant draws between the kind of cognitive capacities that

More information

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary Metaphors we live by George Lakoff, Mark Johnson 1980. London, University of Chicago Press A personal summary This highly influential book was written after the two authors met, in 1979, with a joint interest

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE BOOK TITLE: ORAL TRADITION AS HISTORY

REVIEW ARTICLE BOOK TITLE: ORAL TRADITION AS HISTORY REVIEW ARTICLE BOOK TITLE: ORAL TRADITION AS HISTORY MBAKWE, PAUL UCHE Department of History and International Relations, Abia State University P. M. B. 2000 Uturu, Nigeria. E-mail: pujmbakwe2007@yahoo.com

More information

Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain. Bennett Helm (2002) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman

Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain. Bennett Helm (2002) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain Bennett Helm (2002) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman Introduction Helm s big picture: Pleasure and pain aren t isolated phenomenal bodily states, but are conceptually

More information

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

In his essay Of the Standard of Taste, Hume describes an apparent conflict between two Aesthetic Judgment and Perceptual Normativity HANNAH GINSBORG University of California, Berkeley, U.S.A. Abstract: I draw a connection between the question, raised by Hume and Kant, of how aesthetic judgments

More information

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS The problem of universals may be safely called one of the perennial problems of Western philosophy. As it is widely known, it was also a major theme in medieval

More information

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982), Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982), 12 15. When one thinks about the kinds of learning that can go on in museums, two characteristics unique

More information

Categories and Schemata

Categories and Schemata Res Cogitans Volume 1 Issue 1 Article 10 7-26-2010 Categories and Schemata Anthony Schlimgen Creighton University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Part of the

More information

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Testa, Italo email: italo.testa@unipr.it webpage: http://venus.unive.it/cortella/crtheory/bios/bio_it.html University of Parma, Dipartimento

More information

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign? How many concepts of normative sign are needed About limits of applying Peircean concept of logical sign University of Tampere Department of Mathematics, Statistics, and Philosophy Peircean concept of

More information

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal Cet article a été téléchargé sur le site de la revue Ithaque : www.revueithaque.org Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal Pour plus de détails sur les dates de parution et comment

More information

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK 2.1 Poetry Poetry is an adapted word from Greek which its literal meaning is making. The art made up of poems, texts with charged, compressed language (Drury, 2006, p. 216).

More information

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching Jialing Guan School of Foreign Studies China University of Mining and Technology Xuzhou 221008, China Tel: 86-516-8399-5687

More information

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason THE A PRIORI GROUNDS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE THAT a concept, although itself neither contained in the concept of possible experience nor consisting of elements

More information

HOW TO WRITE A LITERARY COMMENTARY

HOW TO WRITE A LITERARY COMMENTARY HOW TO WRITE A LITERARY COMMENTARY Commenting on a literary text entails not only a detailed analysis of its thematic and stylistic features but also an explanation of why those features are relevant according

More information

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

Existential Cause & Individual Experience Existential Cause & Individual Experience 226 Article Steven E. Kaufman * ABSTRACT The idea that what we experience as physical-material reality is what's actually there is the flat Earth idea of our time.

More information

Prephilosophical Notions of Thinking

Prephilosophical Notions of Thinking Prephilosophical Notions of Thinking Abstract: This is a philosophical analysis of commonly held notions and concepts about thinking and mind. The empirically derived notions are inadequate and insufficient

More information

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action 4 This total process [of Trukese navigation] goes forward without reference to any explicit principles and without any planning, unless the intention to proceed' to a particular island can be considered

More information

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology The Phenomenological Mind: An Introduction to Philosophy of Mind and Cognitive Science Shaun Gallagher and Dan Zahavi New York:

More information

Perception and Concept A Phenomenological Argument for Non-conceptual Content

Perception and Concept A Phenomenological Argument for Non-conceptual Content The 3rd BESETO Conference of Philosophy Session 3 Perception and Concept A Phenomenological Argument for Non-conceptual Content MIYAHARA Katsunori The University of Tokyo Research Fellow of JSPS (DC1)

More information

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 17 November 9 th, 2015 Jerome Robbins ballet The Concert Robinson on Emotion in Music Ø How is it that a pattern of tones & rhythms which is nothing like a person can

More information

DAT335 Music Perception and Cognition Cogswell Polytechnical College Spring Week 6 Class Notes

DAT335 Music Perception and Cognition Cogswell Polytechnical College Spring Week 6 Class Notes DAT335 Music Perception and Cognition Cogswell Polytechnical College Spring 2009 Week 6 Class Notes Pitch Perception Introduction Pitch may be described as that attribute of auditory sensation in terms

More information

EMOTIONS IN CONCERT: PERFORMERS EXPERIENCED EMOTIONS ON STAGE

EMOTIONS IN CONCERT: PERFORMERS EXPERIENCED EMOTIONS ON STAGE EMOTIONS IN CONCERT: PERFORMERS EXPERIENCED EMOTIONS ON STAGE Anemone G. W. Van Zijl *, John A. Sloboda * Department of Music, University of Jyväskylä, Finland Guildhall School of Music and Drama, United

More information

1/9. The B-Deduction

1/9. The B-Deduction 1/9 The B-Deduction The transcendental deduction is one of the sections of the Critique that is considerably altered between the two editions of the work. In a work published between the two editions of

More information

PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG

PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG Dr. Kym Maclaren Department of Philosophy 418 Jorgenson Hall 416.979.5000 ext. 2700 647.270.4959

More information

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12 Reading: 78-88, 100-111 In General The question at this point is this: Do the Categories ( pure, metaphysical concepts) apply to the empirical order?

More information

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART Tatyana Shopova Associate Professor PhD Head of the Center for New Media and Digital Culture Department of Cultural Studies, Faculty of Arts South-West University

More information

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology We now briefly look at the views of Thomas S. Kuhn whose magnum opus, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), constitutes a turning point in the twentiethcentury philosophy

More information

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality Spring Magazine on English Literature, (E-ISSN: 2455-4715), Vol. II, No. 1, 2016. Edited by Dr. KBS Krishna URL of the Issue: www.springmagazine.net/v2n1 URL of the article: http://springmagazine.net/v2/n1/02_kant_subjective_universality.pdf

More information

Title Body and the Understanding of Other Phenomenology of Language Author(s) Okui, Haruka Citation Finding Meaning, Cultures Across Bo Dialogue between Philosophy and Psy Issue Date 2011-03-31 URL http://hdl.handle.net/2433/143047

More information

The Mind's Movement: An Essay on Expression

The Mind's Movement: An Essay on Expression The Mind's Movement: An Essay on Expression Dissertation Abstract Stina Bäckström I decided to work on expression when I realized that it is a concept (and phenomenon) of great importance for the philosophical

More information

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to 1 Abstract: The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to the relation between rational and aesthetic ideas in Kant s Third Critique and the discussion of death

More information

The Black Book Series: The Lost Art of Magical Charisma (The Unreleased Volume: Beyond The 4 Ingredients)

The Black Book Series: The Lost Art of Magical Charisma (The Unreleased Volume: Beyond The 4 Ingredients) The Black Book Series: The Lost Art of Magical Charisma (The Unreleased Volume: Beyond The 4 Ingredients) A few years ago I created a report called Super Charisma. It was based on common traits that I

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

CHAPTER TWO. A brief explanation of the Berger and Luckmann s theory that will be used in this thesis.

CHAPTER TWO. A brief explanation of the Berger and Luckmann s theory that will be used in this thesis. CHAPTER TWO A brief explanation of the Berger and Luckmann s theory that will be used in this thesis. 2.1 Introduction The intention of this chapter is twofold. First, to discuss briefly Berger and Luckmann

More information

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Perceptions and Hallucinations Perceptions and Hallucinations The Matching View as a Plausible Theory of Perception Romi Rellum, 3673979 BA Thesis Philosophy Utrecht University April 19, 2013 Supervisor: Dr. Menno Lievers Table of contents

More information

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative 21-22 April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh Matthew Brown University of Texas at Dallas Title: A Pragmatist Logic of Scientific

More information

The Existential Act- Interview with Juhani Pallasmaa

The Existential Act- Interview with Juhani Pallasmaa Volume 7 Absence Article 11 1-1-2016 The Existential Act- Interview with Juhani Pallasmaa Datum Follow this and additional works at: http://lib.dr.iastate.edu/datum Part of the Architecture Commons Recommended

More information

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015): Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015): 224 228. Philosophy of Microbiology MAUREEN A. O MALLEY Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 2014 x + 269 pp., ISBN 9781107024250,

More information

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK). Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair in aesthetics (Oxford University Press. 2011. pp. 208. 18.99 (PBK).) Filippo Contesi This is a pre-print. Please refer to the published

More information

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden Mixing Metaphors Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden School of Computer Science, University of Birmingham Birmingham, B15 2TT United Kingdom mgl@cs.bham.ac.uk jab@cs.bham.ac.uk Abstract Mixed metaphors have

More information

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave. The Republic is intended by Plato to answer two questions: (1) What IS justice? and (2) Is it better to

More information

THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT

THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT SILVANO ZIPOLI CAIANI Università degli Studi di Milano silvano.zipoli@unimi.it THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT abstract Today embodiment is a critical theme in several branches of the contemporary

More information

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden PARRHESIA NUMBER 11 2011 89-93 HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden At issue in Paul Redding s 2007 work, Analytic Philosophy and the Return of Hegelian Thought, and in

More information

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: This article was downloaded by: [University Of Maryland] On: 31 August 2012, At: 13:11 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer

More information

Image and Imagination

Image and Imagination * Budapest University of Technology and Economics Moholy-Nagy University of Art and Design, Budapest Abstract. Some argue that photographic and cinematic images are transparent ; we see objects through

More information

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Sidestepping the holes of holism Sidestepping the holes of holism Tadeusz Ciecierski taci@uw.edu.pl University of Warsaw Institute of Philosophy Piotr Wilkin pwl@mimuw.edu.pl University of Warsaw Institute of Philosophy / Institute of

More information

Analysis on the Value of Inner Music Hearing for Cultivation of Piano Learning

Analysis on the Value of Inner Music Hearing for Cultivation of Piano Learning Cross-Cultural Communication Vol. 12, No. 6, 2016, pp. 65-69 DOI:10.3968/8652 ISSN 1712-8358[Print] ISSN 1923-6700[Online] www.cscanada.net www.cscanada.org Analysis on the Value of Inner Music Hearing

More information

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception 1/6 The Anticipations of Perception The Anticipations of Perception treats the schematization of the category of quality and is the second of Kant s mathematical principles. As with the Axioms of Intuition,

More information

PARAGRAPHS ON DECEPTUAL ART by Joe Scanlan

PARAGRAPHS ON DECEPTUAL ART by Joe Scanlan PARAGRAPHS ON DECEPTUAL ART by Joe Scanlan The editor has written me that she is in favor of avoiding the notion that the artist is a kind of public servant who has to be mystified by the earnest critic.

More information

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

1/8. Axioms of Intuition 1/8 Axioms of Intuition Kant now turns to working out in detail the schematization of the categories, demonstrating how this supplies us with the principles that govern experience. Prior to doing so he

More information

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction Introduction Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] As Kant emphasized, famously, there s a difference between

More information

Valuable Particulars

Valuable Particulars CHAPTER ONE Valuable Particulars One group of commentators whose discussion this essay joins includes John McDowell, Martha Nussbaum, Nancy Sherman, and Stephen G. Salkever. McDowell is an early contributor

More information

Embodied music cognition and mediation technology

Embodied music cognition and mediation technology Embodied music cognition and mediation technology Briefly, what it is all about: Embodied music cognition = Experiencing music in relation to our bodies, specifically in relation to body movements, both

More information

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth Mauricio SUÁREZ and Albert SOLÉ BIBLID [0495-4548 (2006) 21: 55; pp. 39-48] ABSTRACT: In this paper we claim that the notion of cognitive representation

More information

6 The Analysis of Culture

6 The Analysis of Culture The Analysis of Culture 57 6 The Analysis of Culture Raymond Williams There are three general categories in the definition of culture. There is, first, the 'ideal', in which culture is a state or process

More information

Fulfillment in Perception: A Critique of Alva Noë s Enactive View

Fulfillment in Perception: A Critique of Alva Noë s Enactive View University of Miami Scholarly Repository Open Access Dissertations Electronic Theses and Dissertations 2011-12-09 Fulfillment in Perception: A Critique of Alva Noë s Enactive View Kristjan Laasik University

More information

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB In his In librum Boethii de Trinitate, q. 5, a. 3 [see The Division and Methods of the Sciences: Questions V and VI of

More information