The project of general systemology instigated by Ludwig von Bertalanffy Genealogy, genesis, reception and advancement

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "The project of general systemology instigated by Ludwig von Bertalanffy Genealogy, genesis, reception and advancement"

Transcription

1 The current issue and full text archive of this journal is available at The project of general systemology instigated by Ludwig von Bertalanffy Genealogy, genesis, reception and advancement David Pouvreau Bertalanffy Center for the Study of Systems Science, Vienna, Austria The project of general systemology 851 Received 7 May 2013 Revised 6 July 2013 Accepted 16 July 2013 Abstract Purpose The paper aims to present the main perspectives and conclusions of a doctoral research in the history and philosophy of science conducted in France and Austria by the author on the project of general systemology (or general system theory ) instigated by Ludwig von Bertalanffy. Design/methodology/approach A genealogical enquiry accounts for its scientific, philosophical and more generally cultural origins. Its genesis in Bertalanffy s works between 1926 and 1944 is explained. The process that led it to become a collective project is then discussed: the history of the Society for General Systems Research is considered, the ambivalence of its role with regard to general systemology being demonstrated. Finally, the unity of the diverse contributions to the latter s development is asserted in a framework put forward by the author in order to account for its structure and functions. Findings While stating a comprehensive view of its history, the paper characterizes general systemology as the project of a general science of systemic interpretation of the real which remains topical, although it was never fully actualized. Originality/value A new insight is thus provided on the scope and meaning of this hermeneutics: it meets the contemporary need for a better understanding of the foundations of systems research. Keywords Open systems, Philosophy, Systems theory, Mathematical modelling, Systemic thinking Paper type Research paper Introduction This paper is derived from a recently defended doctoral thesis on the history and foundations of so-called general system theory (Pouvreau, 2013). I claim the term general systemology is more relevant to describe the latter, in order to refer to a project of a general science of systemic interpretation of the real, of an original kind of hermeneutics which had various philosophical and scientific dimensions[1]. The instigator of this project was Ludwig von Bertalanffy ( ). Mostly exclusively known through his compendium of papers published in 1968 under the title General System Theory Foundations, Development, Applications, Bertalanffy was trained as a philosopher in Vienna, notably in connection with neo-kantianisms and neo-positivisms. He first oriented his works toward the philosophy of biology ( ) and then developed an organismic theoretical biology ( ). Essentially as a result of his compromising with Nazis, he was forced to emigration after the Second World War and settled in North America from 1949 onwards (Canada and the USA), where he published and promoted his general systemological project. He inspired and cofounded the Society for General Systems Research (SGSR), Kybernetes Vol. 42 No. 6, 2013 pp q Emerald Group Publishing Limited X DOI /K

2 K 42,6 852 the ancestor of the International Society for Systems Sciences, while widening his works and reorienting them mainly towards cancer research, psychiatry, psychology and social sciences. He significantly influenced those disciplines in that way[2]. This paper is structured in four sections. Sections 1 and 2 focus on the genealogy and genesis of general systemology in Bertalanffy s works. Section 3 explains why and how this project became a collective one after the Second World War: it examines the history of the SGSR. Section 4 attempts a reconstruction of general systemology, based on the significant contributions to its advancement. 1. Genealogy of the Bertalanffian project This section accounts for the origins of the reflections which led Bertalanffy to elaborate this project between 1923 and 1937, of the meanings he assigned to it and of the conceptual schemes on which he constructed it. Most crucial has been the role played in the genesis of his humanistic and aristocratic values by a context that was widely experienced as a crisis of culture. These values were rooted in a romanticist idealism stemming from the beginning of the nineteenth century, of which this context had aroused the rehabilitation (Ringer, 1990). This explains the axiological orientations (i.e. value commitments) and ideological positions which permeate Bertalanffy s works to such a degree that one can see them operate in his philosophy of knowledge and some of his epistemological analyses, as well as in several central themes of his systemology. This is the case of his opposition to every form of utilitarianism or materialism; of his elitist conception of education as complete and disinterested formation of mind; of his interpretation of science as an essentially unitarian project, inseparable from the other aspects of culture, the vocation of which would be to contribute to the edification of a consistent world view supplying meanings. His rejection of dogmatic empiricism and of positivisms, as well as his anti-modernist accents and his disdain for a democracy of which the objective function would be the legitimatization of the technocratically organized and ultimately nihilistic reign of commercialism, are major consequences of these values, inherent in his project (von Bertalanffy, 1924, 1957, 1962a, 1964). It is in this context marked by deep questionings giving rise to sharp controversies, which fostered radical relativism as well as thirsts for absolute, that can also be found the sources of what may have been the most powerful driving force of Bertalanffy s thinking: his quest, in a critico-idealist perspective, of a cosmology able to overcome the contradictions of a declining world of which his tormented time would only manifest the ultimate convulsions. One first group of determinants of this cosmology is the omnipresence of philosophies of life, typical of the intellectual climate in which the young Bertalanffy formed his ideas. These philosophies answered to exacerbated existential needs in exalting all the traits judged as characteristic of life, in reaction to the logics of a civilization of the machine regarded as alienating and disastrous. Perpetual movement, spontaneity, creativity, assertion and surpassing of the self, became elevated to the status of an ultimate reality, to the manifestations of which the privilege of a meaning should be reserved. Bertalanffy molded some of his most fundamental conceptual schemes in contact to these fashionable philosophies: the vision of a world in flux in each of its parts, identifying the persistence of an entity to the reproduction of an order of relationships between its changing elements; the attribution of a primary

3 activity to every organized entity, which subordinates to its own logic the re-actions of this entity to its environment; the interpretation of every evolution as an anamorphosis, an intrinsic trend towards an increase of order identified with the expression of a perpetual compulsion to go beyond the present conditions of existence in order to reach the perfection of the self. Bertalanffy found here a motive for his recurrent references to Heraclitus, Leibniz and Goethe, but one should also see the influences of Schopenhauer and Nietzsche, which operated through the intermediary of some major philosophers of life : Dilthey, Simmel, Bergson and Spengler. There was also an influence on his theory of knowledge of some kind of pragmatism, the emergence of which was connected to the one of the philosophies of life, and the origins of which can be found in Nietzsche s works, in Machian positivism and in a biologicist tradition of interpretation of Kant leading to Vaihinger and von Uexküll: Bertalanffy retained their idea that the categories of experience are instruments of adaptation molded by the necessities of evolution[3]. However, the philosophies of life have in several regards aroused Bertalanffy s opposition, hence also have contributed to the formation of his initial enquiries in that negative way. It was out of question for him to yield to the irrationalism that most of them were inclined to promote. And he was not at all satisfied with the radical ontological, epistemological and methodological gaps they induced, because they contradicted his unitarian tropism: a gap between nature and culture on the one hand, which set an antithesis between sciences of nature and sciences of culture ; a gap between physical world and the world of life on the other hand, which induced a tearing between mechanicist and vitalist biologists notably harbored by psychological analogies deriving from a pseudo-concept of life which was too wide and vague to avoid fallacies. The keynote of the young Bertalanffy s time was especially the ubiquity of the category of wholeness, which passed for the most fundamental category of life (Harrington, 1996). Reconstructing the net of his many scientific and philosophical influences in that regard makes possible to clarify how this context of promotion of holistic ways of thinking has, more deeply than the philosophies of life as such, conditioned his systemological thinking, and to spot the marks that this context has imprinted on his conceptual schemes. Bertalanffy borrowed old philosophies of unity and wholeness, regarding them as forming a tradition. He affiliated himself to Nicholas of Cusa and Leibniz, to the prophets of a romanticist philosophy of nature such as Schelling and Goethe, and to Fechner and von Hartmann. He found in these philosophies food for his inclinations towards a monism identifying mind and matter as manifestations of a single reality, and for his humanistic view of an essentially unified science, dedicated to the formation of the whole man. He could also find in them the inspiration of a monadological view of an integrated world of wholes ruled by universal principles of development, conservation, reproduction and evolution justifying and making necessary the analogical correspondence as a way towards the intelligibility of cosmos. A systematic cartography of the holistic themes in the scientific and philosophical productions from the 1910s to the mid-1930s justifies Bertalanffy s recurrent allegations in that regard: these themes can be found in every academic discipline (although they nowhere imposed their domination) and they were mobilized by some of the most renowned scientists and philosophers of the time. The project of general systemology 853

4 K 42,6 854 The recent transformations of physics as well as the philosophical commentaries they fostered played a prominent role in their promotion. The causes of this role are its desubstantialization process and the unification of its various fields; the assertion of the statistical character of its laws; the rehabilitation of teleology as a formal principle; the questioning of causalism and determinism; and the fact that holistic themes had entered the very heart of the young quantum mechanics. These aspects were essential in the formation of Bertalanffy s ideas concerning the epistemological justification of a scientific holism and the shape it may have. They also considerably influenced the other contemporary architects of holistic thinking who jointly inspired him. In some metaphysics like Whitehead s and Hartmann s, Bertalanffy found rehabilitations of typical themes of the Naturphilosophie tradition to which he sought to set himself up as a heir, but also systematic and original developments taking into account the state of contemporary science, which significantly influenced his ontology and cosmology. This is the case of the primacy of relation on substance asserted by these metaphysics; of the principles of holistic causality and emergence that they introduced; and, at least in Hartmann s, of a stratified construction of the real conciliating the recognition of the specificity of the laws ruling each stratum and the possibility of an unity based on the ubiquity of some fundamental categories. On the other hand, Bertalanffy s silence about Spann s holistic metaphysics reveals his attachment to the determination of a fertile way of conciliation between scientific and holistic thoughts, of which Spann denied the very possibility[4]. This rejection of every wholeness mysticism can be observed in his analogous silence maintained towards Krüger s psychology of wholeness. On the other hand, the Gestalt psychologists have deeply influenced Bertalanffy. While departing from the associationist paradigm, they had demonstrated the possibility of a psychology being at the same time holistic and scientific (Ash, 1995). They had stated laws ruling the structuring and dynamics of perceptive or cognitive forms. Even if he rejected their physicalism, Bertalanffy was especially impressed by Köhler s attempts to expand this psychology in the direction of a general Gestalt theory, where he could find the foreshadowing of a systemology (Systemlehre) devoted to the statement of general system principles based on isomorphisms in mathematical style (Köhler, 1924, 1927). It is nonetheless in biology that Bertalanffy could observe the greatest diversity of holistic works and find the richest source of epistemological reflections as well as the most elaborated matter for the construction and illustration of his own system concepts. The concerned fields covered a wide spectrum: embryology, to the developments of which Bertalanffy particularly turned his attention; morphology, which struck him by its rehabilitation of the typological approach that Goethe had instigated; theories of phylogenetic evolution, heredity and biocenotic systems; as well as several theories concerning the relationships of the organisms with their environment or the preservation of their integrity despite the variations of the latter. The understanding of the multiple levels of biological organization seemed to require a single organismic scheme, variously interpreted: an entity opened to its environment and interacting with it, which hence gains the ability to develop itself and to preserve its integrity while adapting to this environment, the behavior of its parts being only intelligible with regard to this ability. This observation was crucial in the formation of Bertalanffy s conceptions, especially with Weiss attempts, similar to Köhler s ones, to state system laws having a very general biological scope (Weiss, 1925, 1926).

5 Some bio-philosophical developments connected to this holistic movement are also important. Especially the critical rehabilitation of teleology, identified with the expression of the logic of preservation of its integrity ruling the behavior of an organism and of its parts; as well as the legitimization of a methodological vitalism recognizing organic wholeness as a problem inaccessible to meristic[5] approaches and offering a framework that makes possible a nomothetic determination of the bio-holistic traits (Ungerer, 1922). Bertalanffy also very early took care of the evolutions of medicine, where he noticed a significant holistic movement which prolonged the biological one and inspired his later orientations towards psychiatry. So was the case of neuropsychiatry, which Goldstein tried to reconstruct around an organismic scheme (Goldstein, 1934); so was also the case of constitutional typologies and pathologies, as well as the emergence of psychosomatic medicine. As for social sciences, they were also subject to holistic ways of thinking. These sciences have formed on the basis of holistic ontologies, but the trend that Bertalanffy witnessed was a detachment from the organicist analogies in biologicist style that were the hallmark of the nineteenth century. While rejecting this inspiration, he was led to a reflection about the legitimacy, the limitations and the dangers of such analogies, which stimulated his progress towards an abstract and purely formal system concept. The various transpositions of the ideal-typological approach that Goethe had introduced in morphology also had a considerable impact. Very important were Spengler s historical morphology and Dilthey s hermeneutics of cultural systems (Spengler, 1920, 1922; Dilthey, 1922) for Bertalanffy s ideas concerning the possibility and the adequate methodology of a science of the systemic interpretation of the real. One of the essential and tragic characteristics of the German world in the 1920s and 1930s is that philosophies of life and holistic ways of thinking joined in the ideological realm: wholeness was transformed in a vehicle of the ideologization of science which, after having first been dedicated to the uprooting of the mechanicist world view, soon happened to play an essential role in the justification of the national-socialist order; especially holistic biologies, which became one of its pillars (Bäumer, 1990; Harrington, 1996). Bertalanffy s position towards this situation was complex (Pouvreau, 2009, 2013). It largely determined his constant inclination to attribute an ideological scope to his works. And it gave rise to a very ambivalent attitude towards national-socialism, which he as promptly served from 1938 onwards in an opportunistic spirit as he had before 1933 been prompt to attack its instrumentation of biology and the mystical deliria accompanying its rise. Bertalanffy s initial set of problems thus arising in that context paved the way to his general systemology: constructing the logical, epistemological and methodological means of a general and rigorous science of the holistic entities, at once able to set holism free from its confinement to metaphysics or to mystical speculations, and to ground firmly a world view that would be an alternative to a mechanicism judged as scientifically inadequate and ethically unacceptable; and getting involved in that direction through a prior enterprise of theoretical reconstruction of biology, the science of life and wholeness par excellence a pressing requirement, because biology remained deprived of the foundations and force which were necessary if it were to take on the central cultural role that it was called to play, hence becoming the subject of the most dangerous speculations. The project of general systemology 855

6 K 42, Genesis of the Bertalanffian project We now turn to how Bertalanffy answered this questioning, in recounting the steps of the construction of his systemological project. His perspectivist theory of knowledge played a key role, although von Bertalanffy (1955, 1966) only left scattered commentaries about it, without any systematization. Its influences were numerous and various[6]. It was rooted in a philosophical anthropology characterizing man as a symbolic animal and seeking to explain the origins of this specific status as well as to state the principles ruling the symbolic universes that this animal is led to create. This perspectivism can be characterized as a constructivist, relationalist, evolutionist, transactionalist and genetic theory of knowledge, that partook of a neo-critical idealism congruent to Cassirer s one. It recognized a biological and cultural relativity of categories and established the fundamental principle of the interpretative and necessarily incomplete character of every knowledge; however, it did not renounce to the principle of objectivity, redefined as the power to reveal structural and ultimately mathematical invariants, through a convergence of various perspectives constructed in order to grasp the same object. The consequences of this perspectivism for Bertalanffy s philosophy of science were substantial, particularly for his system concept. It explains his insistence upon the necessity of theoretical thinking, as well as his conception of its nature and aims, and of the criteria enabling to judge the value of the theoretical constructs. Bertalanffy advocated the substitution of a science of principles to a science of images and early identified theorization with the building of a hypothetic-deductive system his position concerning the possibility of mathematical theorizations outside physical science remaining nonetheless undetermined until the beginning of the 1930s. His perspectivism led Bertalanffy to understand science as an art of omission expressing some aspects of the real in those interpretative constructions that he called theoretical models. He developed in the context of this modelism substantial elements of an epistemology of models and modeling, where the famous concept of nomic isomorphism which was to become a pivot of his general systemology took his natural place. Bertalanffy s perspectivism enabled him to rehabilitate the holistic styles of thinking under a critical form related to structuralisms, in realizing the transition from a concept of wholeness remaining subject to metaphysical controversies because of its realistic ontology, towards a system concept arising out of a constructivist ontology: there is no system in itself, there are only systemic constructions of objects which structure symbolic representations of some aspects of the phenomenal world in conformity to some holistic schemes of theoretical interpretation, the objectivity of which refers to the relational invariants revealed by the isomorphisms that aroused them. The problem hence became for Bertalanffy to construct a framework aiming at elaborating such schemes and at making them operational, in such a way that systemic theorizing would provide a credible and fertile alternative to the meristic logics and methodologies of a normal science confronted with impasses as soon as it ventures into the realm of organized complexity. This framework was destined to merge the hypothetic-deductive and hermeneutical methods, to conciliate the search for exactness and the quest for meanings with the idea that the meaning of one thing is the expression of its function in a holistic structure into which it is integrated. However, the idea and the understanding of this systemological hermeneutics were not

7 engendered by the sole perspectivism of Bertalanffy: he found in the contemporary biology the other driving forces of its genesis. One can account for the whole set of aspects of the organismic biology he mostly elaborated between 1926 and 1937 in describing it as a biological systemology connecting two poles (von Bertalanffy, 1932, 1937): a philosophy of biological nature; and a theoretical biology including a philosophy of biological theorizing, a scientific program setting up its goals, and a conceptual framework enabling to implement this program. This theoretical biology was supposed to confer a conceptual and methodological unity on biology, while promoting the latter to the rank of exact science. Understood in the perspective of a methodological vitalism, it should have a hypothetic-deductive character, its task being the determination of the laws of biological entities as systems at all levels of the world of life (from cells to biocenosis), and the elaboration of general system principles enabling this determination. Bertalanffy formulated such principles in the form of two theoretical schemes of organismic interpretation: the open system to matter exchanges directed towards (or maintained in) a flux equilibrium ; and the progressive hierarchization of structures and functions, which had several modalities (differentiation, specialization, centralization, mechanization) and to which were connected other principles such as trigger action. As a result of his effort to relate his two schemes, Bertalanffy was led to a conceptual model of which he tried to establish the very general scope, the organized system : a system which, thanks to its openness, can structure itself and function in a more and more complex manner, until it becomes a hierarchical order of open systems in flux equilibrium and enhances in that way both his autonomy with regard to its environment and its ability to fit the latter s changes. Insofar as they aimed at guiding system modeling at all levels of biological organization and at showing a formal unity between these levels, these theoretical schemes and this model anticipated essential aspects of general systemology. As for Bertalanffy s philosophy of biological nature, it was based on three philosophical schemes of organismic interpretation: the primacies of wholeness upon part, of dynamical order upon structural-machinalist order and of activity upon reactivity. Although they could not by themselves contribute directly to system theorizing of the phenomena, these schemes aimed at providing the latter with a heuristic and a framework enabling to find out its general meanings, and at making possible fertile connections between organismic biology and the scientific disciplines that were likely to appropriate its schemes. Bertalanffy did not yet clearly understand exactness as mathematic in 1932: how can be explained his unwillingness in that regard and the remarkable evolution that led him five years later to state the constitutive character of mathematics in system theorizing, not only in biology, but in the framework of a general systemology? Powerful motives traditionally stood in the way of the conciliation of scientific biology, holistic thinking and mathematics. But in discovering the first developments of mathematical biology and in contributing himself to its progress, Bertalanffy departed from tradition and was led in that direction. The works of D Arcy Thompson, Przibram, Rashevsky, Lotka, Volterra, Donnan and Woodger brought to his mind the essential ingredients for his general systemology that were still missing in 1932 in his early biological systemology: the possibility of qualitative mathematics (topology, mathematical logic) adequate to the relational problems raised by system theorizing; the resources offered to the latter even by more classical quantitative mathematics The project of general systemology 857

8 K 42,6 858 (differential and integral calculus); the possibility to study abstract systems of relationships in order to establish typologies of a priori possible systemic behavior and to use them in order to construct theoretical models of specific phenomena; and the use of mathematical analogies in order to guide modeling, but also to construct new concepts and hence enrich a theoretical corpus that was still under-developed in comparison with physics. Bertalanffy s great interest in the first bio-mathematical works stemmed from the necessity he felt in 1933 to demonstrate the relevance, the interest and the fecundity of his organismic biology, and that implied to prove its ability to provide an operational framework for the construction of bio-systemic models deserving their qualification as theoretical. It is during the period of his study of the existing bio-mathematical works (from 1933 onwards to 1941) that he himself undertook this task in parallel. The construction of his mathematical model of animal global growth was a success (von Bertalanffy, 1934, 1941b). Elaborated in perfect conformity to the organismic perspective, it overcame the considerable difficulties met until that time by those who had tried to provide a satisfying mathematical description of this phenomenon, while relating two biological fields hitherto largely disconnected (physiology of metabolism and study of growth). Beyond the implementation of the organismic program, it was nonetheless also important for the genesis of Bertalanffy s general systemology: in constructing this model, he could also observe the theoretical value that may have the analysis of a set of purely abstract relationships; moreover, this model resulting in a typology integrating all animal organisms remarkably illustrated the power of formal unification that may have mathematical system theorizing. These considerations explain why Bertalanffy could formulate and present his project of general systemology as early as 1937 in a seminar (at Chicago). But they do not explain the motives and functions of his works in-between this date and the late 1940s, when he published it. These works met two aims: furthering and deepening the implementation of the organismic program; and providing substantial arguments in order to create the conditions of a successful promotion of his more general project. Bertalanffy s dynamical morphology should satisfy two needs: making operational the connection between his two theoretical schemes of organismic interpretation; and demonstrating with regard to the problem of organic form the ability of the organismic program to grasp efficiently all the fields of biology (von Bertalanffy, 1941a, 1942). This morphology did not as a whole succeed in fulfilling these tasks: the Bertalanffian treatment of animal growth is the only part of this morphology that significantly contributed to their realization. It was otherwise essentially limited to an original framework of qualitative interpretation of morphogenetic phenomena, which had the merits to generate relevant critics of the researches concerning that problem and to formulate hypotheses and explanation suggesting credible alternative researches. As for the outline of formal theory of open systems he published in 1940, it was initiated in 1938 in connection with Rashevsky s school of mathematical biophysics, just after the vehement critics that his first presentation of his general systemological project arose. The spirit of this special systemology limited to systems engaged in material exchanges with their environment was similar to the one of Lotka s general kinetics (Lotka, 1925; von Bertalanffy, 1940, 1942). It aimed at completing the organismic bio-theoretical enterprise in suggesting the possibility to deduce from their openness some of the most fundamental characteristics of all biological systems. In view

9 of Bertalanffy s obvious effort to derive a priori from a formal open system some system laws of which he could mention many concretizations in biology, chemistry and demography, it nonetheless appears that the main vocation of his enterprise was to provide to general systemology a convincing paradigm that would then enable him to explain better the theoretical function of the latter, and to illustrate its ability to establish fertile and empirically relevant results. But this Bertalanffian theory did not carry out his expectations: he came up against serious formal difficulties preventing him to derive enough significant results; and the kinetic point of view to which he confined himself did not allow to grasp the problems of structural and functional organization which are characteristic of biological systems. The study of the relationships between Bertalanffy s works on open systems and the young thermodynamics of irreversible processes shows that there was here an important problem that he never solved. The project of general systemology General systemology as a collective project This section considers the destiny of the general systemological project once it had been published by Bertalanffy. His first presentations, from 1948 to 1953, created some difficulties from which arose many misunderstandings: they condensed in a few pages bold ontological postulates and epistemological points of view without discussing their necessary justifications; they remained essentially programmatic, keeping dark most of the methodological ways that one would have to take in order to enable general systemology to come up with the ambitious tasks that Bertalanffy assigned to it, particularly the task of structuring system modeling (von Bertalanffy, 1949, 1950, 1951a). Notwithstanding their apparent very speculative form, those presentations reached their goal: critics remained marginal at that time and did not shock the numerous enthusiasms aroused by a project that promised to meet the many expectations relative to the theoretical needs felt in non physical sciences as well as to the widely felt necessity to counter excessive specialization and to increase interdisciplinary communication, or to the ethical scope and social functions of science. Ralph Gerard, Anatol Rapoport, James Miller and Kenneth Boulding were among the first researchers to put efforts into the defense and development of general systemology. Their role in the foundation of the SGSR raised the question of the reasons of their convergence in this project in In response to a particular political context, Chicago University (which these researchers and Bertalanffy frequented to various degrees) and the Ford Foundation had created a favorable ground for this convergence in supporting research programs of which the epistemological orientations and the praxeological (i.e. praxis-oriented) ambitions were similar to the ones characterizing the Bertalanffian project (Hammond, 2003). Gerard s, Rapoport s, Miller s and Boulding s works prior to their contact with the latter reveal three major agreements with Bertalanffy: a wish to give to their works some axiological and praxeological significance, with the intention to contribute to the resolution of the huge problems posed to humanity according to them; a strong taste for analogical reasoning going with a deep concern for the unification of scientific fields; and the conviction that developing operational holistic conceptual schemes and methodologies is the adequate way in order to serve efficiently these purposes. Some significant divergences (which soon were to become problematic) are nonetheless manifest. Bertalanffy had much more deeper affinities with Rapoport and Boulding than with Gerard and Miller: a concern for a balance between the search for unity and the respect for diversity, that is between a

10 K 42,6 860 principle of emergence (understood in a critical perspective) and a quest for isomorphic system models, which led the former to reject the biologicism or the physicalism to which Gerard and Miller were inclined when the specifically human levels of organization were concerned; and an ethic that was too much concerned with the problem of conciliating the fulfillment of the individual and social and ecological harmonies to tolerate their technocratic scientism flirting now with the industrial-military complex, now with totalitarian temptations. These affinities were rooted in similar and sometimes identical influences. Most certainly, Rapoport essentially headed for general systemology on the slope of mathematization of biological systems and theory of knowledge, while Boulding especially did the same on the slope of ethics and hermeneutical approach of social systems. But there was thus a complementarity between them, which could then blossom in the project that Bertalanffy instigated (Pouvreau, 2013). The SGSR could hardly have had any future if several research movements, here called cybersciences, had not joined it. Especially because of the great number of scientists involved in these other system sciences and because the latter were historically connected to practical problems and to structures of political or managerial decision-making: such aspects carried promises of expansion and institutionalization for SGSR. The connections of information theory, cybernetics and operations research with general systemology were the most important for the history of the SGSR. There were profound differences between general systemology and cybersciences from the point of view of their scientific, philosophical, ethical and ideological origins and inspirations: their association in the SGSR should not hide them. Many common epistemological and scientific-philosophical traits nonetheless enable to explain the possibility of their rapprochement. Ashby s (1952, 1956, 1958) works played a very important role in that regard. The catalysts of their association in the SGSR were a shared need of institutionalization and the necessity to remedy their respective shortcomings. Stanford s Center for Advanced Studies in the Behavioral Sciences (CASBS) was the birth place of the SGSR, not only because Bertalanffy, Rapoport, Boulding and Gerard met there and decided at the end of 1954 to create this scientific society, but also because much common work was undertaken there with other scientists in : this work constituted a first step in the actualization of the systemological project. His year spent at the CASBS had a strong impact on Bertalanffy. He became aware of the multiplicity of systems research currents and of its consequences for his project: the urge to affirm its vocation and ability to integrate all those currents, while guaranteeing the organismic schemes that he prioritized a prominent place, especially in comparison with cybernetic schemes that he judged less general and often inadequate. The details of the constitution of the SGSR, the manner its founder initially understood its vocations, the characteristics of its head office (Ann Arbor s Mental Health Research Institute (MHRI)), as well as the geographical and disciplinary origins of its first members, have been studied (Hammond, 2003; Pouvreau, 2013). At its beginnings, the SGSR was almost entirely composed of North-Americans. The scientists coming from social sciences, psychology and biology were in large majority. And the cyberscientists constituted most certainly a small minority that was nonetheless already significant (in number as well as in view of the reputation of its representatives). The growth of SGSR membership, together with moderate internationalization, was rapid during the first years of its existence, but underwent an inflexion as early as 1963 and tended towards stabilization from the end of the 1960s onwards, in consequence of a

11 high renewal rate that was partly related to dissatisfactions caused by the relative importance of philosophical concerns with regard to practical applications. The 1960s were a period of expansion and diversification of the SGSR s activities (coordination of research works, organization of meetings, publications, relationships established with other institutions), but some limits inherent in its mode of functioning and funding stood out as soon as the end of this decade. Moreover, although the number of scientists coming from biology, psychology and social sciences always remained at a similar level, the relative weight of the various research orientations changed: an excessive representation of the cybersciences among the presidents of the society is noticeable and symptomatic of a trend to marginalize the Bertalanffian project. This trend went with a movement which asserted itself in the mid-1960s and grew stronger during the following decade: a quest for respectability and institutionalization that progressively led a majority of members to prioritize a focus on systems researches applied to the solution of specific practical problems, to the detriment of an interest for general theoretical constructions and logical, methodological or philosophical questions. This is a major rift in the SGSR, which had ideological declinations and to which were superimposed several epistemological splits. The global analysis of the content of the 28 General Systems Yearbooks shows that the trend in question remains imperceptible in this publication of the SGSR. This manifests an effort of the editors of these volumes, Bertalanffy and Rapoport, to maintain a balance between the various currents, particularly in order that the project of general systemology could keep on being significantly represented in all its aspects: General Systems was the place of their resistance to a systems research having an instrumentalist inspiration and dedicated to a concrete and immediate action on the human world, which tended to take the place of a systems research mainly aimed at interpreting and understanding of the world in general. The trends to which Bertalanffy, Rapoport and Boulding were opposed did not express themselves either in the Behavioral Science journal directed by Miller, which played like General Systems the role of a forum of the SGSR and had essentially the same editorial line. However, the institutional background of this journal was decisive: the MHRI which, also directed by Miller, was the publication place of General Systems and Behavioral Science, turns out to have been an institution which, after having served the promotion of general systemology, became as early as the end of the 1950s the place of its subversion, in encouraging researches that contradicted the main ideals that Bertalanffy, Rapoport and Boulding judged as constitutive of the society. It is at the MHRI that the growing influence in the SGSR of operationalists, management scientists and systems analysts, took root; there also where system scientists like Miller and Gerard could, without engaging in soul-searching, confuse behavioral sciences with the sciences of the manipulation of the behavior (or behavior engineering ); and there that an alliance between the industrial-military complex and some kinds of systems researches was born, in the cold war context. Bertalanffy, Boulding and Rapoport vigorously but unsuccessfully reacted against the scientist inclinations, the technocratic temptations and the careerism of the concerned systems scientists, who represented according to them all the more a danger for the promotion of general systemology that they affiliated themselves to it. It appears that this project, after having been the initial catalyst of the SGSR, was quickly reduced to a current of the latter. This current most certainly remained significant, but it soon represented a minority, the member of which were condemned to The project of general systemology 861

12 K 42,6 862 reassert recurrently the specificity. Although it had promised to become a vehicle of the unification of sciences, the project instigated by Bertalanffy paradoxically did not even succeed in unifying a systems research of which the various currents remained unable to find durably in the SGSR the opportunity of a constructive coexistence. 4. The advancement of general systemology General systemology was nonetheless significantly developed during the period of existence of the SGSR, in a relative continuity with its original inspiration. Despite their very diverse points of view and aims, I regard them as complementary expressions of a single systemological hermeneutics, of which the structure and functions are schematized in Figure 1 where the arrows must be read as informs. General systemology has been represented as structured in four poles, two of them sharing the realm of ontological, logical and methodological questions. (1) Philosophical systemology One of its functions, mainly served by von Bertalanffy (1951b, 1956, 1962b, 1965, 1972) and Rapoport (1960, 1966, 1969, 1972, 1973a), was the elaboration of the anthropological, Formal sciences Mathematics Mathematical logic General systemology Basic theoretical systemology Uninterpreted general systems Transdisciplinarily interpreted general systems Systemological logic Systemological methodology Systems ontology Philosophical systemology Perspectivism Philosophy of science Philosophical anthropology Metaphysics Axiology Systemic technology Ideology Applied theoretical systemology Theoretical systemic models in the «sciences of the real» Resolution of systemically interpreted concrete problems Action social economical political Figure 1. Sciences of the real Physics, chemistry, biology, ecology, medicine, psychology, linguistics, economy, sociology, anthropology, political sciences Concrete problems physico-technological, ecological, social, economical, political

13 epistemological, ontological, logical and methodological foundations of the systemic knowledge of the real. Another function, especially developed in Boulding s (1956, 1961, 1966) and Rapoport s (1973b, 1974, 1976) works, was the discussion of the values conveyed by this knowledge and of the ways it can contribute to a practical transformation of the human world. The construction, on the basis of this knowledge, of an inductive metaphysics exposing a system cosmology, was also a part of philosophical systemology, to which Laszló (1972a, b) and Bunge (1968, 1979) significantly contributed. The latter two aspects have aroused more or less explicit affinities with definite ideological discourses (ecologism, pacifism and an internationalist view of political action). As a whole, philosophical systemology carried a very original humanism, insofar as it ultimately relied on mathematics and therefore depended for its coherence on the other poles of general systemology. However, the ontological, logical and methodological aspects of the systemological hermeneutics did not only partake of philosophical systemology. As a matter of fact, they constituted an interface between the latter and a second pole. The project of general systemology 863 (2) Basic theoretical systemology This pole was dedicated to become a guide for the construction of theoretical systemic models applicable in the sciences of the real. It sought to reach this goal in gathering in structural equivalence classes the existing theoretical models of various kinds of systems, in constructing purely formal general systems representing those classes, and then in theorizing those systems with the means provided by the formal sciences in order to derive systemic principles and laws that would a priori be applicable to all their particular interpretations. Bertalanffy, Rapoport and Ashby have contributed to the development of this pole, but the most significant contributions were Mesarović s, Rosen s and Klir s in the USA, and Delattre s and Le Moigne s in France (Mesarović, 1968; Mesarović and Takahara, 1975; Rosen, 1968, 1977; Klir, 1969, 1981; Delattre, 1971; Le Moigne, 1977). Another theoretical pole played an essential role of pivot. (3) Applied theoretical systemology It got its perspectives and means from (1) and (2), and informed them back while interacting permanently with the sciences of the real, to which it was supposed to provide theoretical models: it provided (2) with the necessary material for the construction of general systems and enabled (1) to maintain alive and fertile its contact with the sciences of the real. The procedure of systemic modeling constitutive of this applied theoretical systemology has been elaborated by Klir and Orchard (Klir, 1969; Orchard, 1972) and I have proposed a systematization of this procedure in my thesis (Pouvreau, 2013, pp ). Bertalanffy s theoretical models of global or relative growth, the various interpretations of his general organized system model in psychiatry, psychology and social sciences (von Bertalanffy, 1967; Katz and Kahn, 1966), and Richardson-Rapoport s mathematical model of arms race (Rapoport, 1957), are some typical products of applied theoretical systemology. In the end, the latter informed a fourth pole. (4) Systemic technology It was the place of concrete application of the considerations developed in the other systemological poles, in order to find efficient solutions to the practical problems to which contemporary civilization is confronted, once those problems are reinterpreted

14 K 42,6 864 as systemic ones. Bertalanffy, Rapoport and Boulding recognized its legitimate place in general systemology, but always tended to remain suspicious of its productions, with regard to their values and in connection to their critics of technocratic orientations in systems research. The most emblematic contributions to systemic technology may be Miller s and Gerard s works laying the bases of internet (Brown et al., 1967; Heterick, 1998), and Mesarović s direction of the second report to the Club of Rome on limits to growth (Mesarović and Pestel, 1974). All the contributions to the development of general systemology appear as moments of a process of maturation of this project. But although the latter was partially actualized through those works, one cannot pretend that it reached its maturity. The study of its posterity (Pouvreau, 2013), from the mid-1970s onwards, nonetheless shows that the shortcomings concerning its exposition and its development were not essential causes. On the other hand, such causes can be detected in some unfavorable historical circumstances. The sudden explosion of the number of its critics in the 1970s can mainly be explained by the conjunction of three historical elements: the technocratic functions held by some system scientists during the previous decade and the negative judgment passed on their efficiency and their legitimacy; the ideological heterodoxy of the reports to the Club of Rome ; and a widespread will in the universities, especially in social sciences, to protect disciplinary territories judged as threatened by the intrusion of system scientists. As a matter of fact, very few criticisms were justified in principle: most of them originated either in a lack of knowledge of the works concerning general systemology, or in the lacks of precision and systematicity of the discourses of its defenders when they undertook to explain its meaning and foundations (shortcomings which can be corrected). But these criticisms mined the chances for a perennial development of general systemology, because they went with a trend, which became more and more in majority among the system scientists themselves, to marginalize this project because of a concern for respectability that those criticisms exacerbated. The end of this process which has in fact few to do with the real content of general systemology is that despite the SGSR, and maybe partly because of this society, it has not succeeded in institutionalizing itself. Conclusion However, the project initiated by Bertalanffy is not condemned to wander like a dead star. Its themes are still relevant, although it is widely forgotten as a historically situated project, as show contemporary systems biology and more generally widespread discourses on complex systems. The state of the contemporary world, from the scientific, philosophical, social, ecological, economical, political and ideological points of view, does not at all seem less favorable to a future of general systemology than the circumstances that permitted its ephemeral success more than half a century ago. Several requirements are nonetheless necessary in order to allow such a future to occur: that contemporary workers in systems research cultivate a precise memory of its history and, in particular, correctly judge the values and the scopes of the Bertalanffian project and of the works which contributed to its actualization; that they seriously re-examine this project on the basis of constructive responses to the few legitimate critics that have been formulated against it; that the multitude of various contributions to systems research at last finds its unity in the new systemological framework that may have been generated by these efforts; and finally, that a clear awareness emerges

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART Tatyana Shopova Associate Professor PhD Head of the Center for New Media and Digital Culture Department of Cultural Studies, Faculty of Arts South-West University

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT This article observes methodological aspects of conflict-contractual theory

More information

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Action Theory for Creativity and Process Action Theory for Creativity and Process Fu Jen Catholic University Bernard C. C. Li Keywords: A. N. Whitehead, Creativity, Process, Action Theory for Philosophy, Abstract The three major assignments for

More information

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics? Daniele Barbieri Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics? At the beginning there was cybernetics, Gregory Bateson, and Jean Piaget. Then Ilya Prigogine, and new biology came; and eventually

More information

THE EVOLUTIONARY VIEW OF SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS Dragoş Bîgu dragos_bigu@yahoo.com Abstract: In this article I have examined how Kuhn uses the evolutionary analogy to analyze the problem of scientific progress.

More information

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki 1 The Polish Peasant in Europe and America W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki Now there are two fundamental practical problems which have constituted the center of attention of reflective social practice

More information

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History Review Essay Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History Giacomo Borbone University of Catania In the 1970s there appeared the Idealizational Conception of Science (ICS) an alternative

More information

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it. Majors Seminar Rovane Spring 2010 The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it. The central text for the course will be a book manuscript

More information

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm Ralph Hall The University of New South Wales ABSTRACT The growth of mixed methods research has been accompanied by a debate over the rationale for combining what

More information

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS The problem of universals may be safely called one of the perennial problems of Western philosophy. As it is widely known, it was also a major theme in medieval

More information

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism James Sage [ jsage@uwsp.edu ] Department of Philosophy University of Wisconsin Stevens Point Science and Values: Holism & REA This presentation

More information

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Reviewed by Christopher Pincock, Purdue University (pincock@purdue.edu) June 11, 2010 2556 words

More information

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC This part of the book deals with the conditions under which judgments can express truths about objects. Here Kant tries to explain how thought about objects given in space and

More information

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden PARRHESIA NUMBER 11 2011 75-79 PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden I came to Paul Redding s 2009 work, Continental Idealism: Leibniz to

More information

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism Early Modern Philosophy In the sixteenth century, European artists and philosophers, influenced by the rise of empirical science, faced a formidable

More information

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY Mizuho Mishima Makoto Kikuchi Keywords: general design theory, genetic

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

1/10. The A-Deduction

1/10. The A-Deduction 1/10 The A-Deduction Kant s transcendental deduction of the pure concepts of understanding exists in two different versions and this week we are going to be looking at the first edition version. After

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Karin de Boer Angelica Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011 Cybernetics and Human Knowing. Vol. 18, nos. 3-4, pp. 151-155 The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage Siegfried J. Schmidt 1 Over the last decades Heinz von Foerster has brought the observer

More information

The Debate on Research in the Arts

The Debate on Research in the Arts Excerpts from The Debate on Research in the Arts 1 The Debate on Research in the Arts HENK BORGDORFF 2007 Research definitions The Research Assessment Exercise and the Arts and Humanities Research Council

More information

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics REVIEW A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics Kristin Gjesdal: Gadamer and the Legacy of German Idealism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. xvii + 235 pp. ISBN 978-0-521-50964-0

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis Keisuke Noda Ph.D. Associate Professor of Philosophy Unification Theological Seminary New York, USA Abstract This essay gives a preparatory

More information

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics REVIEW An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics Nicholas Davey: Unfinished Worlds: Hermeneutics, Aesthetics and Gadamer. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2013. 190 pp. ISBN 978-0-7486-8622-3

More information

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS NIKOLAY MILKOV THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS The Philosopher must twist and turn about so as to pass by the mathematical problems, and not run up against one, which would have to be solved before

More information

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

More information

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton This essay will explore a number of issues raised by the approaches to the philosophy of language offered by Locke and Frege. This

More information

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology We now briefly look at the views of Thomas S. Kuhn whose magnum opus, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1962), constitutes a turning point in the twentiethcentury philosophy

More information

Culture and Art Criticism

Culture and Art Criticism Culture and Art Criticism Dr. Wagih Fawzi Youssef May 2013 Abstract This brief essay sheds new light on the practice of art criticism. Commencing by the definition of a work of art as contingent upon intuition,

More information

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden Seven remarks on artistic research Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden 11 th ELIA Biennial Conference Nantes 2010 Seven remarks on artistic research Creativity is similar

More information

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS) Both the natural and the social sciences posit taxonomies or classification schemes that divide their objects of study into various categories. Many philosophers hold

More information

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative 21-22 April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh Matthew Brown University of Texas at Dallas Title: A Pragmatist Logic of Scientific

More information

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile Web: www.kailashkut.com RESEARCH METHODOLOGY E- mail srtiwari@ioe.edu.np Mobile 9851065633 Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is What is Paradigm? Definition, Concept, the Paradigm Shift? Main Components

More information

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn The social mechanisms approach to explanation (SM) has

More information

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT Maria Kronfeldner Forthcoming 2018 MIT Press Book Synopsis February 2018 For non-commercial, personal

More information

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education The refereed journal of the Volume 9, No. 1 January 2010 Wayne Bowman Editor Electronic Article Shusterman, Merleau-Ponty, and Dewey: The Role of Pragmatism

More information

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Sidestepping the holes of holism Sidestepping the holes of holism Tadeusz Ciecierski taci@uw.edu.pl University of Warsaw Institute of Philosophy Piotr Wilkin pwl@mimuw.edu.pl University of Warsaw Institute of Philosophy / Institute of

More information

Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order

Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order Christopher Alexander is an oft-referenced icon for the concept of patterns in programming languages and design [1 3]. Alexander himself set forth his

More information

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says, SOME MISCONCEPTIONS OF MULTILINEAR EVOLUTION1 William C. Smith It is the object of this paper to consider certain conceptual difficulties in Julian Steward's theory of multillnear evolution. The particular

More information

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN Erasmus Journal for Philosophy and Economics, Volume 7, Issue 1, Spring 2014, pp. 161-165. http://ejpe.org/pdf/7-1-ts-2.pdf PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN PhD in economic

More information

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology University of Chicago Milton Friedman and the Power of Ideas: Celebrating the Friedman Centennial Becker Friedman Institute November 9, 2012

More information

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE] Like David Charles, I am puzzled about the relationship between Aristotle

More information

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes Testa, Italo email: italo.testa@unipr.it webpage: http://venus.unive.it/cortella/crtheory/bios/bio_it.html University of Parma, Dipartimento

More information

On The Search for a Perfect Language

On The Search for a Perfect Language On The Search for a Perfect Language Submitted to: Peter Trnka By: Alex Macdonald The correspondence theory of truth has attracted severe criticism. One focus of attack is the notion of correspondence

More information

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

The Shimer School Core Curriculum Basic Core Studies The Shimer School Core Curriculum Humanities 111 Fundamental Concepts of Art and Music Humanities 112 Literature in the Ancient World Humanities 113 Literature in the Modern World Social

More information

Capstone Design Project Sample

Capstone Design Project Sample The design theory cannot be understood, and even less defined, as a certain scientific theory. In terms of the theory that has a precise conceptual appliance that interprets the legality of certain natural

More information

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE Jonathan Martinez Abstract: One of the best responses to the controversial revolutionary paradigm-shift theory

More information

On the history of Ludwig von Bertalanffy s General Systemology, and on its relationship to cybernetics

On the history of Ludwig von Bertalanffy s General Systemology, and on its relationship to cybernetics International Journal of General Systems Vol. 36, No. 3, June 2007, 281 337 On the history of Ludwig von Bertalanffy s General Systemology, and on its relationship to cybernetics Part I: elements on the

More information

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory. Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory Paper in progress It is often asserted that communication sciences experience

More information

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Anca-Gabriela Ghimpu Phd. Candidate UBB, Cluj-Napoca Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle Paper contents Introduction: motivation

More information

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment First Moment: The Judgement of Taste is Disinterested. The Aesthetic Aspect Kant begins the first moment 1 of the Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment with the claim that

More information

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy 1 Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy Politics is older than philosophy. According to Olof Gigon in Ancient Greece philosophy was born in opposition to the politics (and the

More information

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Croatian Journal of Philosophy Vol. XV, No. 44, 2015 Book Review Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192 Philip Kitcher

More information

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS Association for Information Systems AIS Electronic Library (AISeL) AMCIS 2003 Proceedings Americas Conference on Information Systems (AMCIS) December 2003 A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique

More information

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS) Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS) 1 Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS) Courses LPS 29. Critical Reasoning. 4 Units. Introduction to analysis and reasoning. The concepts of argument, premise, and

More information

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb CLOSING REMARKS The Archaeology of Knowledge begins with a review of methodologies adopted by contemporary historical writing, but it quickly

More information

A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault

A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault By V. E. Koslovskii Excerpts from the article Structuralizm I dialekticheskii materialism, Filosofskie Nauki, 1970, no. 1, pp. 177-182. This article

More information

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation Cogent Science in Context: The Science Wars, Argumentation Theory, and Habermas. By William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009. Pp. 355. Cloth, $40. Paper, $20. Jeffrey Flynn Fordham University Published

More information

Philosophical foundations for a zigzag theory structure

Philosophical foundations for a zigzag theory structure Martin Andersson Stockholm School of Economics, department of Information Management martin.andersson@hhs.se ABSTRACT This paper describes a specific zigzag theory structure and relates its application

More information

observation and conceptual interpretation

observation and conceptual interpretation 1 observation and conceptual interpretation Most people will agree that observation and conceptual interpretation constitute two major ways through which human beings engage the world. Questions about

More information

Japan Library Association

Japan Library Association 1 of 5 Japan Library Association -- http://wwwsoc.nacsis.ac.jp/jla/ -- Approved at the Annual General Conference of the Japan Library Association June 4, 1980 Translated by Research Committee On the Problems

More information

SOCI 421: Social Anthropology

SOCI 421: Social Anthropology SOCI 421: Social Anthropology Session 5 Founding Fathers I Lecturer: Dr. Kodzovi Akpabli-Honu, UG Contact Information: kodzovi@ug.edu.gh College of Education School of Continuing and Distance Education

More information

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE Introduction Georg Iggers, distinguished professor of history emeritus at the State University of New York,

More information

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail. This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail. Author(s): Arentshorst, Hans Title: Book Review : Freedom s Right.

More information

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception 1/6 The Anticipations of Perception The Anticipations of Perception treats the schematization of the category of quality and is the second of Kant s mathematical principles. As with the Axioms of Intuition,

More information

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY Overall grade boundaries Grade: E D C B A Mark range: 0-7 8-15 16-22 23-28 29-36 The range and suitability of the work submitted As has been true for some years, the majority

More information

The Object Oriented Paradigm

The Object Oriented Paradigm The Object Oriented Paradigm By Sinan Si Alhir (October 23, 1998) Updated October 23, 1998 Abstract The object oriented paradigm is a concept centric paradigm encompassing the following pillars (first

More information

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May, Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May, 119-161. 1 To begin. n Is it possible to identify a Theory of communication field? n There

More information

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna christian.damboeck@univie.ac.at a community of scientific specialists will do all it can to ensure the

More information

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal Cet article a été téléchargé sur le site de la revue Ithaque : www.revueithaque.org Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal Pour plus de détails sur les dates de parution et comment

More information

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of language: its precision as revealed in logic and science,

More information

Nature's Perspectives

Nature's Perspectives Nature's Perspectives Prospects for Ordinal Metaphysics Edited by Armen Marsoobian Kathleen Wallace Robert S. Corrington STATE UNIVERSITY OF NEW YORK PRESS Irl N z \'4 I F r- : an414 FA;ZW Introduction

More information

INTUITION IN SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS

INTUITION IN SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS INTUITION IN SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS MATHEMATICS EDUCATION LIBRARY Managing Editor A. J. Bishop, Cambridge, U.K. Editorial Board H. Bauersfeld, Bielefeld, Germany H. Freudenthal, Utrecht, Holland J. Kilpatnck,

More information

Leverhulme Research Project Grant Narrating Complexity: Communication, Culture, Conceptualization and Cognition

Leverhulme Research Project Grant Narrating Complexity: Communication, Culture, Conceptualization and Cognition Leverhulme Research Project Grant Narrating Complexity: Communication, Culture, Conceptualization and Cognition Abstract "Narrating Complexity" confronts the challenge that complex systems present to narrative

More information

Why Intermediality if at all?

Why Intermediality if at all? Why Intermediality if at all? HANS ULRICH GUMBRECHT 1. 173 About a quarter of a century ago, the concept of intertextuality sounded as intellectually sharp and as promising all over the international world

More information

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013): Book Review John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel Jeff Jackson John R. Shook and James A. Good, John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. New York:

More information

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna Kuhn Formalized Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna christian.damboeck@univie.ac.at In The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (1996 [1962]), Thomas Kuhn presented his famous

More information

Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in Wang Zhaowen s Beauty- Goodness-Relationship Theory

Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in Wang Zhaowen s Beauty- Goodness-Relationship Theory Canadian Social Science Vol. 12, No. 1, 2016, pp. 29-33 DOI:10.3968/7988 ISSN 1712-8056[Print] ISSN 1923-6697[Online] www.cscanada.net www.cscanada.org Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in

More information

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Commentary Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002 Laura M. Castelli laura.castelli@exeter.ox.ac.uk Verity Harte s book 1 proposes a reading of a series of interesting passages

More information

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May, Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May, 119-161. 1 To begin. n Is it possible to identify a Theory of communication field? n There

More information

The Historicity of Understanding and the Problem of Relativism in Gadamer's Philosophical Hermeneutics

The Historicity of Understanding and the Problem of Relativism in Gadamer's Philosophical Hermeneutics Cultural Heritage and Contemporary Change Series I, Culture and Values, Volume 27 Series IIA, Islam, Volume 11 The Historicity of Understanding and the Problem of Relativism in Gadamer's Philosophical

More information

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN: Andrea Zaccardi 2012 ISSN: 1832-5203 Foucault Studies, No. 14, pp. 233-237, September 2012 REVIEW Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé,

More information

Categories and Schemata

Categories and Schemata Res Cogitans Volume 1 Issue 1 Article 10 7-26-2010 Categories and Schemata Anthony Schlimgen Creighton University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Part of the

More information

Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality

Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality Catherine Bell November 12, 2003 Danielle Lindemann Tey Meadow Mihaela Serban Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality Simmel's construction of what constitutes society (itself and as the subject of sociological

More information

Carlo Martini 2009_07_23. Summary of: Robert Sugden - Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics 1.

Carlo Martini 2009_07_23. Summary of: Robert Sugden - Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics 1. CarloMartini 2009_07_23 1 Summary of: Robert Sugden - Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics 1. Robert Sugden s Credible Worlds: the Status of Theoretical Models in Economics is

More information

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful The Unity of Art 3ff G. sets out to argue for the historical continuity of (the justification for) art. 5 Hegel new legitimation based on the anthropological

More information

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska Introduction It is a truism, yet universally acknowledged, that medicine has played a fundamental role in people s lives. Medicine concerns their health which conditions their functioning in society. It

More information

Renaissance Old Masters and Modernist Art History-Writing

Renaissance Old Masters and Modernist Art History-Writing PART II Renaissance Old Masters and Modernist Art History-Writing The New Art History emerged in the 1980s in reaction to the dominance of modernism and the formalist art historical methods and theories

More information

6 The Analysis of Culture

6 The Analysis of Culture The Analysis of Culture 57 6 The Analysis of Culture Raymond Williams There are three general categories in the definition of culture. There is, first, the 'ideal', in which culture is a state or process

More information

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314 Note: The following curriculum is a consolidated version. It is legally non-binding and for informational purposes only. The legally binding versions are found in the University of Innsbruck Bulletins

More information

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free Intersect, Vol 10, No 2 (2017) Challenging the View That Science is Value Free A Book Review of IS SCIENCE VALUE FREE? VALUES AND SCIENTIFIC UNDERSTANDING. By Hugh Lacey. London and New York: Routledge,

More information

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas Freedom as a Dialectical Expression of Rationality CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas I The concept of what we may noncommittally call forward movement has an all-pervasive significance in Hegel's philosophy.

More information

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers History Admissions Assessment 2016 Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers 2 1 The view that ICT-Ied initiatives can play an important role in democratic reform is announced in the first sentence.

More information

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995. The Nature of Time Humberto R. Maturana November 27, 1995. I do not wish to deal with all the domains in which the word time enters as if it were referring to an obvious aspect of the world or worlds that

More information

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason THE A PRIORI GROUNDS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE THAT a concept, although itself neither contained in the concept of possible experience nor consisting of elements

More information

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002) Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002) 168-172. Your use of the HUME STUDIES archive indicates your acceptance

More information

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst 271 Kritik von Lebensformen By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN 9783518295878, 451pp by Hans Arentshorst Does contemporary philosophy need to concern itself with the question of the good life?

More information