Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements Andrea Sauchelli

Size: px
Start display at page:

Download "Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements Andrea Sauchelli"

Transcription

1 Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements Andrea Sauchelli The concept of functional beauty is analysed in terms of the role played by beliefs, in particular expectations, in our perceptions. After finding various theories of functional beauty unsatisfying, I introduce a novel approach which explains how aesthetic judgements on a variety of different kinds of functional objects (chairs, buildings, cars, etc.) can be grounded in perceptions influenced by beliefs. Cognitively rich accounts of aesthetic appreciation, particularly in art, are popular among contemporary aestheticians. This fertile background has allowed a new resurgence of theories focused on a kind of beauty called functional beauty (FB). 1 Despite this renewed interest, concerns about functionality have been difficult to reconcile with the idea that the aesthetic value of an object is grounded in a form of disinterested perception. However, even in theoretical accounts, such as Kant s analysis of beauty, which have been taken as cornerstones of formalist approaches to aesthetic appreciation and judgements, the concept of function does not disappear completely. 2 Leaving aside historical accounts of the concept of FB, in this essay I will explore recent theories on the connection between beauty and function in relation to everyday functional objects. After finding some of these theories unsatisfying, I propose my own explanation of the concept of FB. In particular, I show that by introducing the concept of expectation, we can obtain a theory that has the same explanatory power as the best theories in the field but that fares better against criticisms. In addition, I discuss the connection of my theory of FB with recent developments in the philosophy of perception. Finally, I address some possible criticisms. Internalist, Externalist, and Relative Accounts of Functional Beauty We can distinguish at least two ways in which function can be related to beauty: external and internal. Externalist accounts of FB usually establish the connection between function and beauty in the following way. They start with the idea that there are objects which 1 See Glenn Parsons and Allen Carlson, Functional Beauty (Oxford: OUP, 2008). 2 Of course, this is not true in all cases. For instance, Edmund Burke and more recently Roger Fry and Jerome Stolnitz maintained that aesthetic appreciation, and thus also attributions of beauty, are not related to considerations of the functionality of the object at issue. For a historical overview of the debate, see Parsons and Carlson, Functional Beauty, 1 30; Wladyslaw Tatarkiewicz, History of Aesthetics, vol. I (London: Continuum, [1970/4] 2005); and Paul Guyer, Beauty and Utility in Eighteen-Century Aesthetics, Eighteenth-Century Studies 35 (2002), British Journal of Aesthetics Vol. 53 Number 1 January 2013 pp DOI: /aesthj/ays057 British Society of Aesthetics Published by Oxford University Press on behalf of the British Society of Aesthetics. All rights reserved. For Permissions, please journals.permissions@oup.com

2 42 Andrea Sauchelli are clearly functional (i.e. buildings, cars, or furniture) and clearly possess aesthetic value (i.e. the Pantheon in Rome, the Ferrari 250 LM Berlinetta (1964), or Alberto Meda s Berenice lamp). They also usually maintain that if we were to know that one of these objects was not able to perform its function, then we would refrain from attributing beauty to it. For instance, if we knew that the Ferrari 250 LM Berlinetta was impossible to drive and incredibly unsafe (which is not true), we would not say that this object is beautiful as a car. Similarly, the Berenice lamp would not be classified as beautiful if we knew that it provided poor illumination (which is not true). More generally, according to externalist theories of FB, considerations of function do not contribute directly to a positive aesthetic judgement; rather, they constrain possible applications of the term beautiful when ascribed to functional objects. It is in this sense that function is external to judgements of beauty: the functional appropriateness of an object is a necessary but not sufficient condition for such an object to be considered beautiful. Kant s theory of adherent (or dependent) beauty is an example of this type of approach. More specifically, Paul Guyer has suggested that in various passages of his Critique of the Power of Judgement, Kant suggests that in judging an object with a function, the fact that the object is well-adapted to its function is a necessary condition for the eventual aesthetic pleasure we may obtain from it (which is, in his account, a necessary basis for our aesthetic judgements). 3 How this is possible within Kant s framework is controversial and does not directly concern us here. To sum up, an FB externalist maintains that functional considerations are relevant for judging an object aesthetically, because in cases where the object at issue has a specific function, it is necessary for such an object to fulfil its function in order to be judged as beautiful. There is also another way of reading the externalist constraint on the aesthetic value of a functional object. For instance, it can be argued that aesthetic appreciation, as it is usually understood, need not require that the object really fulfil its function, but only that it appear to be able to perform such a function. Given that aesthetic appreciation usually concerns the appearance of objects we may further clarify this approach by saying that an externalist theory of FB can just require that an object appear to be able to perform a function, for judging it as beautiful. An internalist theory of FB, however, denies that functional considerations contribute to aesthetic judgements only negatively or indirectly. More specifically, theories of this type suggest that an object can also be judged as beautiful by virtue of the way it looks in relation to its function. It would follow that when we judge a functional object, the appearance of a kind of interaction between our (even implicit) knowledge that such an object has a purpose and our perception that the function is relevant to its form would ground a positive (or negative) attribution of beauty. Obviously, this is just the sketch of a theory and many points need to be better clarified. 3 See Guyer, Beauty and Utility in Eighteen-Century Aesthetics, 122. The issue is much more complicated than that. In a subsequent paper, in fact, Guyer also claims that Kant s concept of adherent beauty can be reconciled with internalist accounts of functional beauty. See his Free and Adherent Beauty, BJA 42 (2002), Among others, Rachel Zuckert, Kant on Beauty and Biology (Cambridge: CUP, 2007), and Larry Shiner, On Aesthetics and Function in Architecture, JAAC 69 (2011), 31 41, argue for an internalist reading of Kant s concept of adherent beauty.

3 Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements 43 It has to be noted that an internalist theory of FB does not entail that: (1) beauty is always a relative concept, or a concept that can only be meaningfully applied under the condition that we know the kind of object we are judging; or (2) FB is the only possible kind of beauty (or relative beauty). A general internalist theory of FB does not entail that functionality (or its perception) is a necessary condition for beauty (in general) to emerge, or that functionality (or its perception) is a necessary condition for all the other ways of making the concept of beauty relative to a category. In other words, an internalist theory of FB is not committed to the strong thesis that beauty is to be explained solely in terms of utility. There is another important distinction to be made within the family of internalist theories of FB. Within this family, there are approaches where we make justified ascriptions of FB when the elements composing the object concur with the fulfilment of its function in virtue of their aesthetic merits. In other words, x is functionally beautiful when one or more of its (positive) aesthetic properties contributes to the fulfilment of its function. According to this kind of theory, the concept of FB can be understood as a case in which beauty is literally functional. Stephen Davies has argued in favour of such a theory. 4 Internalist theories of this kind suggest that x is functionally beautiful when the beauty of the parts of x contributes to its functionality. However, this is not the only way we can explain the idea that function can be internally related to beauty. In fact, according to another family of internalist theories, our perception of beauty related to function may also occur if we perceive that the non-aesthetic properties of an object contribute to the fulfilment of its function in a certain way. According to these other theories, we perceive FB in x when x functions beautifully or when x appears to function beautifully. The aforementioned types of internalist theories are not in contrast and can be taken as specifying two separate genres of FB. In this essay, however, I will focus on the view that a judgement of FB is grounded in a perception of the connection between non-aesthetic elements and their function: that is, a theory of FB of the x functions beautifully -type. Varieties of FB Glenn Parsons and Allen Carlson have proposed an elegant internalist theory of the x functions beautifully -type. Their basic idea is to apply Kendall Walton s theory of the structure of proper aesthetic judgements of works of art to the case of functional objects. In particular, Parsons and Carlson claim that our recognition of the aesthetic properties of an object is influenced by our knowledge of its function. We will see more in detail how this idea has been worked out, but first we need to point out another peculiarity of their approach: that is, the suggestion that FB has a richer phenomenology than so far recognized. From at least Xenophon s Socrates to the continental rationalists and the British empiricists, the aesthetic concept that specified the general idea of the relation between utility and aesthetic value was the property of looking fit or, in other words, the property of 4 See Stephen Davies, Aesthetic Judgments, Artworks and Functional Beauty, Philosophical Quarterly 56 (2006),

4 44 Andrea Sauchelli looking apt for a function. 5 More specifically, the role of function in aesthetic judgements was supposed to be related solely to the intuition that an object perceived as looking fit (or appropriate) for its function may be judged beautiful in virtue of such a perception. However, this is not the only way in which a judgement of beauty can be informed by our knowledge (or belief) about the function of an object. Parsons and Carlson in fact argue that we should also include under the label of FB of the functioning beautifully -type two other aesthetic features: (1) visual tension and (2) elegance, gracefulness, and simplicity. 6 These three components of the concept of FB looking fit, visual tension, and elegance are explained, in Parsons and Carlson s account, by elaborating on Walton s theory of the appreciation of art. 7 More specifically, Walton claimed that the aesthetic properties possessed by a work of art depend not only on its non-aesthetic features but also on which non-aesthetic features are standard, variable, or contra-standard, relative to certain categories of art. These categories may include horror movies, impressionist paintings, Gothic cathedrals, and so on. According to Walton, a feature is standard with respect to a specific category of art when the feature is essential to a work of art belonging to that category. For example, having three dimensions is a standard feature of a work belonging to the category of Gothic architecture. On the other hand, a variable feature is not essential to the work belonging to a specific artistic category: for example, the property of having a certain tonality of red for a painting. A work having a contra-standard feature relative to a category tends to disqualify such a work from that category: for example, representational features in abstract paintings. Walton further suggests that the perception of a feature as standard does not involve being able to specify in all circumstances which feature makes us judge that a work belongs to a certain category. For instance, he says that someone familiar with Brahms, and thus able to recognize a musical piece in the style of Brahms, hears certain qualities in the piece that make it possible to perceive the music as an example of the category music in the style of Brahms, but this does not entail that the perceiver be able to point out explicitly the properties that grounded this recognition. Walton claims that our capacity to perceive works of art under certain categories depends on our past experiences, including familiarity with similar works, and possibly knowledge of art critics judgements. Given this account, Walton further claims that a complete ignorance of the categories under which a work is to be judged would entail the incapacity of judging its aesthetic properties, because of the absence of categories relative to which aesthetic properties of the work were supposed to be perceived. We would not be disturbed by Yves Klein s monochromatic paintings if we were not acquainted with the more general categories of coloured and classical paintings; the disquieting properties of Klein s paintings would not emerge if we did not perceive their non-aesthetic properties as contra-standard to the category of classical paintings. Even though Walton s claim that perception mediated by categorical knowledge is a necessary condition for correct 5 See Parsons and Carlson, Functional Beauty, These last three terms are understood as denoting the same concept. 7 See Kendall Walton, Categories of Art, Philosophical Review 79 (1970), Stephen Davies is critical of Parsons and Carlson s application of Walton s theory; see, for instance, Functional Beauty Examined, Canadian Journal of Philosophy 40 (2010),

5 Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements 45 aesthetic judgements on artworks may be too strict, there is general consensus regarding the importance of such knowledge for the appreciation of many of the aesthetic properties of works of art. Parsons and Carlson, elaborating on Walton s theory, claim that among the categories by which we can judge objects (not only works of art) there are those specified by functional purposes. Everyday objects such as forks, knives, and chopsticks function as tools for eating properly, and we commonly perceive them as objects that belong to such a functional category. Parsons and Carlson maintain that perceiving objects under functional categories influences our perception of the objects aesthetic properties. More specifically, if we perceive an object s non-aesthetic features as not being contra-standard but as indicative of functionality relative to a functional category, then we may perceive the object as looking fit. When the functional category used to perceive the object causes it to appear as having few contra-standard or variable features but only standard ones, then the object may appear elegant and graceful. The content and the distinctive aesthetic properties are given to a work through its variable features. We may perceive visual tension if the object still looks functional but also appears to have some contra-standard features relative to a specific functional category. A katana may look fit if we perceive the nonaesthetic properties of its blade as being suitable to its function of killing people, and as not having any contra-standard feature, such as a plastic blade. That same katana may also look elegantly simple when it is perceived as having only those non-aesthetic properties necessary to kill somebody (a sharp blade and a good handle). Viktor Schreckengost s lawn chairs, on the other hand, may be perceived as having a vibrant, surprising look, that is, as having an aesthetically pleasing visual tension. The perception of this aesthetic property would be based on the idea that a chair should provide a comfortable and stable place to sit (the proper function of a chair); in contrast, the peculiar shape of Schreckengost s chairs suggests a lack of stability (as they have no rear legs) that may cause us to perceive a surprising and vibrant look. This approach is elegant and seems to accommodate various intuitions about, for example, the source of attributions of visual tension to various functional objects. However, Larry Shiner has recently advanced a compelling objection to Parsons and Carlson s theory. 8 Although the problem he raises can be extended to other domains, Shiner focuses his attention on architecture. In particular, he points out that in the case of the exterior appearance of museums, there does not seem to be any standard form associated with the relative functional category of these buildings. Referring to functional categories would not solve the problem of providing a means to ground our perceptions of the non-aesthetic properties of such buildings as standard, variable, or contra-standard, because there is no strict connection between functional categories and forms. Functions can be realized in multiple ways, and thus a specific form need not be seen as standard in relation to a certain purpose. For example, it is not clear how we could determine whether Frank Gehry s titanium-covered Guggenheim Museum in Bilbao or the Uffizi Gallery in Florence had the standard shape for the functional 8 Larry Shiner, On Aesthetics and Function in Architecture, JAAC 69 (2011),

6 46 Andrea Sauchelli category associated with museums. It seems that both can fulfil their function, so we do not seem to have a specific ground for deciding which forms are variable, standard, or contra-standard in relation to the functional category to which the two buildings belong. Even though there are cases in which Parsons and Carlson s approach may be useful (e.g. cases of everyday objects such as knives and forks in which their shapes are all very similar), in this essay I offer an internalist theory of FB that can counter Shiner s objections. An Expectation-Based Account of FB One important aspect of Parsons and Carlson s theory that must be noted is that the phenomenology of FB includes not only the aesthetic property of looking fit, but also visual tension and simplicity, elegance and gracefulness. A better theory of our perception of aesthetic properties should provide an analysis of what lies behind the connection between functional categories and the perception of these properties. In other words, we need a deeper explanation of how such categories are used in our perceptual systems. If we intend to argue that non-aesthetic categories somehow set standards that are relevant for our aesthetic evaluations, we need an account of how this happens and its eventual philosophical consequences. For this reason, my theory is based on the idea that our knowledge (or beliefs) concerning the proper function of an object operates on our perception by creating expectations concerning how such an object will be shaped (or how its parts will be arranged). In other words, our perception of those aesthetic properties that belong to the phenomenology of FB is based on our expectations. The concept of expectation that I have in mind is to be understood in terms of beliefs, that is, dispositions to take something as being the case. More particularly, expectations relevant to our analysis are beliefs concerning how a certain function should or will be realized in a form in order for the resulting object to be suited to its function. These beliefs are the result of our previous experiences with objects appearing to have the same (or similar) functions. 9 Therefore, the central idea is that instead of fixed functional categories, it is more fruitful to use (or start with) the notion of expectation in explaining the perception of various aesthetic properties classified as types of FB. If we assume that the proper functions of a pair of football shoes are to allow us to run on the pitch and have good control of the ball, our knowledge of these functions when viewing a pair of football shoes would trigger an expectation of how the shoes will be shaped. Such an expectation is grounded in what we have experienced thus far, either by a previous use of this kind of shoe or by simply observing a football match on our (functional) sofa. If the shape of the shoe is similar to our expectations, this may trigger in us the perception of the aesthetic property of looking fit. Some theoretical clarifications are necessary at this point, and such clarifications require a brief, preliminary discussion of the concept of the cognitive penetrability of 9 My theory is neutral with respect to any specification of the concept of belief. It seems to me that in many cases our expectations about how an object will be shaped determine also how we think that an object should be realized for it to fulfil a certain purpose.

7 Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements 47 perception. 10 In the contemporary debate on this concept, we can distinguish at least two different positions. Philosophers such as Zenon Pylyshyn and Athanassios Raftopoulos deny that the information processed by the visual system is generally affected by higherorder processes, such as those usually related to cognition. Despite this, Raftopoulos admits that, at a certain stage (possibly when attention is also involved in the visual process), higher-order processes are involved in perception, such as when the visual indices attributed to the individuation of objects in the visual scene appear to be independent of what the thinker has in mind conceptually. Raftopoulos maintains that the competition between visual stimuli may be regulated by processes of attention which are, in turn, probably biased by expectations, among other processes. 11 Other philosophers argue, on the other hand, that perception can be biased by top down processes. Assessing the arguments for or against these various positions would go beyond the scope of this essay; however, some brief remarks are of vital importance for the whole project and for clarifying certain points that have been frequently overlooked. There appears to be empirical evidence suggesting that expectations and experiences influence our perceptions. It is a well-known phenomenon in studies of human perception that we can acquire perceptual skills through experience in various domains, such as face recognition or distinguishing birds. 12 Expectations can modify not only our vision but also our perception of pain. 13 In the domain of art, it is well known that art critics and artists help us recognize and appreciate patterns of colour or shapes that they have learnt to recognize and distinguish through perception. For example, music theorists are able to discern sophisticated non-aesthetic properties in musical performances that those with an untrained ear would never perceive at first hearing. However, our capacity to discern more properties in compositions (or paintings, movies, or any other art) which usually falls under the general concept of taste can be continuously refined through experience. Experience influences and modifies our perceptions. Taste enriches our perceptions through expectations that can be related, in turn, to an experience-based view of how a certain object should be shaped to perform a specific set of functions. The general point is that expectations, based on our previous experience regarding how objects 10 For recent discussions of this concept, see Zenon Pylyshyn, Is Vision Continuous with Cognition?, Behavioral and Brain Sciences 22 (1999), ; Athanassios Raftopoulos, Cognition and Perception: How Do Psychology and Neural Science Inform Philosophy? (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009); Susanna Siegel, Do Visual Experiences Have Content, in Bence Nanay (ed.), Perceiving the World (Oxford: OUP, 2010), , and Cognitive Penetrability and Perceptual Justification, Nôus (forthcoming); Dustin Stokes, Perceiving and Desiring: A New Look at the Cognitive Penetrability of Experience, Philosophical Studies (forthcoming); and Fiona Macpherson, Cognitive Penetration of Colour Experience, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research (forthcoming). 11 Raftopoulos, Cognition and Perception, See, for instance, C. M. Bukach, I. Gauthier, and M. J. Tarr, Beyond Faces and Modularity: The Power of an Expertise Framework, Trends in Cognitive Sciences 10 (2006), ; or J. W. Tanaka, T. Curran, and D. L. Sheinberg, The Training and Transfer of Real-World Perceptual Expertise, Psychological Science 16 (2005), See also I. Gautier, Perceptual Expertise, in Bruce Goldstein (ed.), Encyclopedia of Perception (Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications, 2010), Bruce Goldstein, Sensation and Perception, eighth edition (Belmont, CA: Wadsworth, 2010), 345.

8 48 Andrea Sauchelli with a particular function have been shaped, influence our perception of the object s nonaesthetic properties. In particular, these expectations or beliefs can be either met or not met in different ways. If this is not convincing, the thesis of the cognitive penetrability of perception can be interpreted as affirming that cognitive processes can at least influence the phenomenological character of our experiences of these processes, even if they are unable to influence our visualization of objects. 14 In fact, the thesis according to which perception can be penetrated by cognitive processes is not, strictly speaking, a necessary requirement for a general theory of FB and the connection between standards and aesthetic judgements. We can argue that knowledge of functional categories may operate at various levels: perceptual, experiential, and judgemental. More specifically, we can claim that the knowledge of categories may influence (1) the perception of what we see (thus, the discernment, through various senses, of different aesthetic properties), (2) the experience and phenomenological character of the objects in question (what it feels like to experience a certain object), and (3) proper aesthetic judgements concerning functional objects. If we maintain, with sceptics about the cognitive penetrability of perception, that the knowledge of categories cannot influence what we perceive, then we may still claim that our knowledge of certain categories may influence the character of our experience of a certain object. This latter claim, in its general form, appears to be extremely plausible. Think again about the process of becoming an expert in a certain musical genre. Even if we do not admit that musical experts are really able to perceive more qualities in the musical pieces they listen to, compared with untrained amateur, it still seems hard to deny that experts in this field have richer and better aesthetic experiences in virtue of their improved expertise. This may be explained in terms of an improved capacity to focus their attention on more relevant details or simply in terms of having an improved pleasant experience due to the recognition of certain previously studied patterns. 15 In addition to this, the phenomenon of the cognitive penetrability of the phenomenological character of experience can be demonstrated by episodes in which emotions and moods influence our experiences of what surrounds us. For example, it has been convincingly argued that moods deeply influence the character of our experiences of our surroundings. 16 Therefore, at least the phenomenological character of our experiences can be modified by higher-order cognitive processes. If this is the case, we can argue that the knowledge of categories can influence how we experience certain objects. Even if this latter point is denied, we can still argue that when we make proper aesthetic judgements concerning a functional object, we should take into account the type of object we are judging, if only because certain 14 This aspect of the thesis has been emphasized by various authors such as Susanna Siegel. See her Cognitive Penetrability and Perceptual Justification. 15 For discussion, see Michael Luntley, Understanding Expertise, Journal of Applied Philosophy 43 (2009), 41 56; Expectations without Content, Mind & Language 25 (2010), ; and Richard Carlson, Experienced Cognition (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates, 1997). 16 See Laura Sizer, Towards a Computational Theory of Mood, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51 (2000),

9 Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements 49 aesthetic terms appear to be dependent for their proper application on standards dictated by the types of objects being judged. 17 Now that the foundations for the account have been laid, I can introduce its details; in general, if the expectations triggered by our knowledge of an object s purpose are perceived as being satisfied, possibly in a clever way, then the object may be perceived as looking fit. We may perceive simplicity, elegance, and gracefulness when we perceive the arrangement of the parts of an object to conform to our expectations, to contribute to the fulfilment of the function of the object in a clever and ingenious way (similarly to looking fit), and to avoid any unnecessary element in the arrangement of the parts of the object. We may perceive visual tension (1) when the object fails to meet expectations regarding how certain elements should be arranged, given its expected function, but (2) the object is still able to perform its function. The details of the theory can be rephrased in terms of the influence of categories, understood as including sets of expectations, on experience and aesthetic judgements. If our expectations are somehow satisfied, the resulting experience may trigger the recognition of the property of looking fit in the object in question, and this would also hold true for all the other categories. Let us take Ludwig Mies van der Rohe s Barcelona chairs as an example. It is usually said that their design, inspired by the curule chairs used during the Roman Republic, is rather elegant and simple. We may explain such an attribution by saying that, in looking at the Barcelona chairs, we perceive forms and shapes (non-aesthetic properties) that are easily associated with what we have experienced as satisfying a chair s function (usually that of providing a stable, raised surface used to sit on by one person). In addition, we do not perceive anything not aimed at this function. This perception may justify an ascription of elegance and simplicity to the chairs. My theory does not predict that we ascribe an aesthetic property to an object in every case where it is fit for its function or displays any positive or negative relation to its function. Rather, I take for granted that such attributions may occur, and I offer an explanation for them. I think that, in many cases, considerations of utility are not always sufficient to arouse an aesthetic interest in an object and that there are objects that, to arouse in us an aesthetic interest, require other features. For example, certain objects of everyday use (forks, chopsticks, etc.), even if perceived as functional and fit for their function, seldom arouse an aesthetic interest. Objects of everyday use displaying visual tension are more inclined to catch our attention, owing to the fact that they display forms and shapes that are perceived as unusual. Similarly, for attributions of elegance, it is not sufficient for an object simply to appear to have all and only the expected functional properties to be perceived or experienced or judged as elegant. Rather, the composition of its parts should be perceived as clever and ingenious to stimulate aesthetic interest. The functional categories mentioned in Parsons and Carlson s theory and mentioned in my account of FB can thus be understood as including codifications of expectations 17 For discussion, see Frank Sibley, Adjectives, Predicative and Attributive, Aesthetic Judgements: Pebbles, Faces, and Fields of Litter, and Some Notes on Ugliness, all collected in John Benson, Betty Redfern, and Jeremy Roxbee Cox (eds), Approach to Aesthetics (Oxford: OUP, 2001); and Rafael De Clercq, Aesthetic Ideals, in Kathleen Stock and Katherine Thomson-Jones (eds), New Waves in Aesthetics (London: Palgrave Macmillan, 2008),

10 50 Andrea Sauchelli regarding specific functions. I do not mean to suggest that functional categories, intended as explicit sets of conditions, should be eliminated altogether from an explanation of attributions of FB; what is suggested is rather that we would better understand functional categories as not fixed and crystalline but as including codified expectations too. For example, certain scholars in design studies, each with a common or similar education (including a set of standardized samples), may start to classify a set of objects as apt for a certain function (perhaps in virtue of rational considerations regarding technical aspects). The shape of a certain chair may be codified as standard in relation to its specific function. Consequently, a tendency will eventually emerge to codify structures with a similar shape as standard for a certain function. This, in turn, generates expectations regarding how certain groups of functional objects should be designed to perform certain functions. If an object displays such a design, it may be perceived as looking fit (or as any other type of FB). Functional categories can thus be understood, in certain cases, as codifications of expectations. In this way, we can provide a better explanation of the connection between the perception of aesthetic properties and background knowledge, an aspect not completely addressed in previous theories. In addition, my approach is immune to Shiner s objections to Parsons and Carlson s theory. Specifically, even if functions can be realized in various designs, it can be maintained that various aesthetic properties may be perceived in different objects by virtue of the relationship between our expectations and their design. For instance, if we find Gehry s museum to display visual tension, we can explain this by noting that our perception is probably grounded in our experiences with more classical designs for museums (e.g. the Galleria degli Uffizi). We are not forced to say that Gehry s museum in Bilbao has features that go against its function to accommodate the intuition that it has a shocking appearance. We can say, rather, that it looks shocking because of what we have experienced before. Finally, I will specify another theoretical requirement of the internalist theory of FB that I have proposed. We may say that my internalist theory of FB requires that the concept of beauty depends for its meaning, in specific cases, on the specification of the category of the object thought of as beautiful. 18 For instance, in certain cases, an attribution of beauty to an object can be seen as relative to a certain set of items. Let us consider the case of aesthetic judgements about horses. We can judge that Varenne, a famous harness racing horse, is a beautiful horse, in the sense that Varenne is beautiful as a horse. Specifying the category at issue makes it possible to understand the way the concept of beauty has been employed in the aesthetic judgement. From this, however, it does not follow that my theory of FB implies that all attributions of aesthetic value to an object should be necessarily seen as based on or grounded in the concepts through which we have perceived the object. We can maintain, for example, that attributions of visual tension are aesthetic judgements that rely on expectations regarding the shape of certain objects and that, at the same time, when we perceive a rose, we do not have to be interested in its functional category (the reproductive organ of a plant) to perceive its beauty. My theory does not 18 Similar ideas can be found in Sibley s discussion of attributive uses of the adjective beautiful. See Adjectives, Predicative and Attributive, , n. 18 for references.

11 Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements 51 imply that the concept of beauty should be explained solely in terms of function or that ascriptions of beauty should always be grounded in conceptualizations or expectations of the object of our aesthetic judgements. In fact, my thesis simply explains the application of a certain range of aesthetic judgements, that is, aesthetic judgements somehow related to functional considerations. Objections and Replies It may be argued that in relying on the concept of expectation, we exclude the possibility of sensible disagreement between people ascribing to objects different kinds of properties belonging to the phenomenology of FB. For instance, it can be maintained that our perception of visual tension would assume an irremediably temporal aspect; only people in the past (and thus having certain expectations) would perceive Viktor Schreckengost s lawn chairs as having a vibrant look. Now that we are somehow familiar with chairs lacking rear legs, seeing chairs with such a feature would not be based on expectations that would ground a perception of visual tension. If this is the case, there would be no basis for a rational disagreement between a past critic saying that the chair has the aesthetic property of having a vibrant look and a contemporary critic who denies such an attribution. More generally, our perception of certain kinds of FB would be grounded in related features solely on the basis of the perceptual history of the perceiver (that is, a certain subject s set of perceptual experiences), and thus aesthetic judgements of FB would be too subjective to be a matter of serious dispute. There are many ways to reply to this critique. For example, we may claim that there are certain recurring features of our perceptual systems that justify the objectivity of certain aesthetic judgements. 19 Even though our perception of certain features is moulded and informed by our acquired capacity of distinguishing features, this does not mean that the cognitive system can be influenced without limits. In particular, there is a range of variability in specific cognitive abilities, determined by individual differences, but this variability is still within a specific range. 20 From this, it may be argued that the perception of certain aesthetic properties can be grounded in features of our minds which are stable to a degree that may justify beliefs expressed through aesthetic judgements. Unless we change the cognitive system of human beings, it is likely that, within certain specific ranges, we all have similar cognitive and perceptual systems. Therefore, it is likely that, even if our perception of aesthetic properties is based on expectations, it does not follow that aesthetic judgements based on different perceptual histories are doomed to be completely beyond rational dispute. Another possible strategy to counter the objection that appealing to expectations would make aesthetic judgements unquestionable is to focus our attention on the structure of 19 See, for instance, Colin Ware, Information Visualization: Perception for Design, second edition (Burlington, MA: Morgan Kaufmann Publishers, 2004), which is a study dedicated to, among other things, how to optimize the display of information, taking into account general features of our cognitive systems. 20 See, for instance, Goldstein, Sensation and Perception, 13 8, for an introduction to various methodologies of the measurement of variation in the recognition of perceptual stimuli.

12 52 Andrea Sauchelli aesthetic judgements and, in particular, proper aesthetic judgements. Suppose that we are somehow interested in determining whether a certain object of design possesses the aesthetic property of visual tension, and we wish to express an aesthetic judgement about it. In order to be able to express a proper aesthetic judgement that can be debated, we need to adjust ourselves to the conditions within which such an object was conceptually located. As a consequence, we can say that a proper aesthetic judgement regarding the vibrant look of an object should make reference to the conditions in which the object was produced. This may require an imaginative exercise, an attempt to picture oneself in a situation where perhaps it is not completely possible to imagine ourselves. For example, in judging Schreckengost s lawn chair, we may try to imagine ourselves in a situation where we have never before experienced the design of a chair without rear legs. Or, let us take the example of Antonio Sant Elia s architectural projects. To see or perceive the novelty and originality of his drawings, we may need to imagine ourselves as living in Italy at the beginning of the twentieth century. This imaginative exercise, I admit, may not be completely possible in all cases, but it can be maintained that if we are interested in expressing a proper aesthetic judgement about an object we may need to re-create as much as possible the perceptual conditions under which such an object was first introduced. For instance, we may read about the reactions to the object by the people who lived at that time in order to understand how that object was perceived and eventually assessed. Again, from the fact that judgements of FB are based on expectations, it does not seem to follow that such judgements are irremediably outside the field of reasonable disagreement. Why should we appeal to codified sets of expectations to make a correct or proper aesthetic judgement on the FB of an object? I believe that the reason has to do with the requirement that correct attributions of FB need to be grounded in a proper aesthetic understanding of the object. In turn, such an understanding is connected to an informed experience of the object. 21 For instance, designers have particular problems in mind and a specific public that is supposed to find their solutions functional and appropriate. In order to understand their work, we need to understand what the various designers intend to achieve. Among the conditions of success for their projects, in fact, we should count the way in which they address the expectations shared by whoever is expected to experience their work. Given that designers have in mind a specific public, we may expect that the resulting experience of the work will be enhanced if we are able to determine what they are trying to achieve. The reason is that the resulting design has been optimized to achieve that specific result. Ideally, if the object is really worth our attention, the aesthetic experience augmented by awareness of the sets of expectations that the designer wants to address is enriched. For this reason I believe that an ascription of FB should appeal to expectations and that judgements of FB based on such knowledge are more appropriate than those ignoring them. 21 See Roger Scruton, The Aesthetic of Architecture (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1979/80), ch. 4, for the idea that informed experience can be a crucial component of the aesthetic understanding of an object.

13 Functional Beauty, Perception, and Aesthetic Judgements 53 Conclusions I have argued here that aesthetic value can be related to function. More specifically, I have proposed a theory that explains ascriptions of various kinds of FB in terms of expectations. Instead of employing the notion of functional categories, I have maintained that we should focus our attention on the concept of expectation. My theory can be seen as an attempt to clarify the basis for certain kinds of aesthetic judgements: in particular, positive aesthetic evaluations of objects grounded in the relationship between these objects and their function(s). The relevance of this approach is crucial if we want to expand contemporary aesthetics domain of interest to, among other things, objects of design and, more generally, objects of everyday use. I have not here taken a stance on the proper appreciation of nature and whether specifications of the concept of FB can be applied to this domain as well. Despite not having addressed these issues explicitly, the concept of FB is an extremely useful tool that can be employed in a variety of different cases in environmental aesthetics if we understand this field as including the study of the built environment (architecture or urban design) or, more generally, an appreciation of objects of design. It must be remembered that this category is incredibly vast and can include graphic design (such as the specification and organization of systems of information), and the design of particular identities of large corporations (from their logos to their advertising strategies). By expanding our aesthetic interest to the field of objects of use (using a broad sense of object ) and providing a solid philosophical and psychological foundation upon which to construct theoretical frameworks, we may better understood the aesthetic appreciation of what surrounds us. Andrea Sauchelli Department of Philosophy, Lingnan University andrea.sauchelli@gmail.com andreasauchelli@ln.edu.hk

Reflections on a sofa-bed : functional beauty and looking fit

Reflections on a sofa-bed : functional beauty and looking fit Lingnan University, Hong Kong From the SelectedWorks of Prof. DE CLERCQ Rafael 2010 Reflections on a sofa-bed : functional beauty and looking fit Rafael DE CLERCQ, Lingnan University, Hong Kong Available

More information

Image and Imagination

Image and Imagination * Budapest University of Technology and Economics Moholy-Nagy University of Art and Design, Budapest Abstract. Some argue that photographic and cinematic images are transparent ; we see objects through

More information

FUNCTIONAL BEAUTY, ARCHITECTURE, AND MORALITY: A BEAUTIFUL KONZENTRATIONSLAGER?

FUNCTIONAL BEAUTY, ARCHITECTURE, AND MORALITY: A BEAUTIFUL KONZENTRATIONSLAGER? The Philosophical Quarterly ISSN 0031-8094 doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9213.2011.00020.x FUNCTIONAL BEAUTY, ARCHITECTURE, AND MORALITY: A BEAUTIFUL KONZENTRATIONSLAGER? BY ANDREA SAUCHELLI Some works of architecture

More information

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment First Moment: The Judgement of Taste is Disinterested. The Aesthetic Aspect Kant begins the first moment 1 of the Analytic of Aesthetic Judgment with the claim that

More information

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by Conclusion One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by saying that he seeks to articulate a plausible conception of what it is to be a finite rational subject

More information

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography Dawn M. Phillips 1 Introduction In his 1983 article, Photography and Representation, Roger Scruton presented a powerful and provocative sceptical position. For most people interested in the aesthetics

More information

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5 PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5 We officially started the class by discussing the fact/opinion distinction and reviewing some important philosophical tools. A critical look at the fact/opinion

More information

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

What is the Object of Thinking Differently? Filozofski vestnik Volume XXXVIII Number 3 2017 91 100 Rado Riha* What is the Object of Thinking Differently? I will begin with two remarks. The first concerns the title of our meeting, Penser autrement

More information

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Perceptions and Hallucinations Perceptions and Hallucinations The Matching View as a Plausible Theory of Perception Romi Rellum, 3673979 BA Thesis Philosophy Utrecht University April 19, 2013 Supervisor: Dr. Menno Lievers Table of contents

More information

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)? Kant s Critique of Judgment 1 Critique of judgment Kant s Critique of Judgment (1790) generally regarded as foundational treatise in modern philosophical aesthetics no integration of aesthetic theory into

More information

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Cosmos and History: The Journal of Natural and Social Philosophy, vol. 7, no. 2, 2011 REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY Karin de Boer Angelica Nuzzo, Ideal Embodiment: Kant

More information

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright Forthcoming in Disputatio McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright In giving an account of the content of perceptual experience, several authors, including

More information

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts Normativity and Purposiveness What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts of a triangle and the colour green, and our cognition of birch trees and horseshoe crabs

More information

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience Introduction Naïve realism regards the sensory experiences that subjects enjoy when perceiving (hereafter perceptual experiences) as being, in some

More information

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery Nick Wiltsher Fifth Online Consciousness Conference, Feb 15-Mar 1 2013 In Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery,

More information

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

AESTHETICS. Key Terms AESTHETICS Key Terms aesthetics The area of philosophy that studies how people perceive and assess the meaning, importance, and purpose of art. Aesthetics is significant because it helps people become

More information

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document Boulder Valley School District Department of Curriculum and Instruction February 2012 Introduction The Boulder Valley Elementary Visual Arts Curriculum

More information

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN zlom 7.5.2009 8:12 Stránka 111 Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN 0826486320 Aesthetics and Architecture, by Edward Winters, a British aesthetician, painter,

More information

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

In his essay Of the Standard of Taste, Hume describes an apparent conflict between two Aesthetic Judgment and Perceptual Normativity HANNAH GINSBORG University of California, Berkeley, U.S.A. Abstract: I draw a connection between the question, raised by Hume and Kant, of how aesthetic judgments

More information

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008 490 Book Reviews between syntactic identity and semantic identity is broken (this is so despite identity in bare bones content to the extent that bare bones content is only part of the representational

More information

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception 1/8 The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception This week we are focusing only on the 3 rd of Kant s Paralogisms. Despite the fact that this Paralogism is probably the shortest of

More information

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism THE THINGMOUNT WORKING PAPER SERIES ON THE PHILOSOPHY OF CONSERVATION ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism by Veikko RANTALLA TWP 99-04 ISSN: 1362-7066 (Print) ISSN:

More information

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982), Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982), 12 15. When one thinks about the kinds of learning that can go on in museums, two characteristics unique

More information

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 17 November 9 th, 2015 Jerome Robbins ballet The Concert Robinson on Emotion in Music Ø How is it that a pattern of tones & rhythms which is nothing like a person can

More information

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS Let us then suppose the mind to be, as we say, white paper, void of all characters, without any ideas; how comes it to be furnished? Whence comes

More information

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS The problem of universals may be safely called one of the perennial problems of Western philosophy. As it is widely known, it was also a major theme in medieval

More information

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information: This article was downloaded by: [University Of Maryland] On: 31 August 2012, At: 13:11 Publisher: Routledge Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer

More information

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation Cogent Science in Context: The Science Wars, Argumentation Theory, and Habermas. By William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009. Pp. 355. Cloth, $40. Paper, $20. Jeffrey Flynn Fordham University Published

More information

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008. Reviewed by Christopher Pincock, Purdue University (pincock@purdue.edu) June 11, 2010 2556 words

More information

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative 21-22 April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh Matthew Brown University of Texas at Dallas Title: A Pragmatist Logic of Scientific

More information

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art Session 5 September 16 th, 2015 Malevich, Kasimir. (1916) Suprematist Composition. Gaut on Identifying Art Last class, we considered Noël Carroll s narrative approach to identifying

More information

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics Georgia State University ScholarWorks @ Georgia State University Philosophy Theses Department of Philosophy 7-18-2008 The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics Maria

More information

Aesthetic properties in Allen Carlson s theory for the appreciation of nature: Focusing on the functions of categories

Aesthetic properties in Allen Carlson s theory for the appreciation of nature: Focusing on the functions of categories The Japanese Society for Aesthetics Aesthetics No.21 (2018): 13-22 Aesthetic properties in Allen Carlson s theory for the appreciation of nature: Focusing on the functions of categories The University

More information

Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain. Bennett Helm (2002) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman

Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain. Bennett Helm (2002) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain Bennett Helm (2002) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman Introduction Helm s big picture: Pleasure and pain aren t isolated phenomenal bodily states, but are conceptually

More information

Triune Continuum Paradigm and Problems of UML Semantics

Triune Continuum Paradigm and Problems of UML Semantics Triune Continuum Paradigm and Problems of UML Semantics Andrey Naumenko, Alain Wegmann Laboratory of Systemic Modeling, Swiss Federal Institute of Technology Lausanne. EPFL-IC-LAMS, CH-1015 Lausanne, Switzerland

More information

Practical Action First Critique Foundations *

Practical Action First Critique Foundations * Practical Action First Critique Foundations * Adrian M. S. Piper Both European and Anglo-American philosophical traditions of Kant scholarship draw a sharp distinction between Kant s theoretical and practical

More information

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge Stance Volume 4 2011 A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge ABSTRACT: It seems that an intuitive characterization of our emotional engagement with fiction contains a paradox, which

More information

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind *

A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind * A Confusion of the term Subjectivity in the philosophy of Mind * Chienchih Chi ( 冀劍制 ) Assistant professor Department of Philosophy, Huafan University, Taiwan ( 華梵大學 ) cchi@cc.hfu.edu.tw Abstract In this

More information

On The Search for a Perfect Language

On The Search for a Perfect Language On The Search for a Perfect Language Submitted to: Peter Trnka By: Alex Macdonald The correspondence theory of truth has attracted severe criticism. One focus of attack is the notion of correspondence

More information

Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens

Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens At its best, philosophising about value is a fine balancing act between respecting the way in which value strikes us,

More information

The Nature of Art. Introduction: Art in our lives

The Nature of Art. Introduction: Art in our lives The Nature of Art Lecture 1: Introduction: Art in our lives A rt plays a large part in making our lives infinitely rich. Imagine, just for a minute, a world without art! (You may think "So what?", but

More information

Aesthetic Formalism, Reactions and Solutions

Aesthetic Formalism, Reactions and Solutions Hekmat va Falsafe (Wisdom and Philosophy) vol.6, no.4, 2011, pp. 101-112 Aesthetic Formalism, Reactions and Solutions Khosrow Bagheri Noaparast Mohammad Zoheir Bagheri Noaparast Abstract It seems necessary

More information

THE EVOLUTIONARY VIEW OF SCIENTIFIC PROGRESS Dragoş Bîgu dragos_bigu@yahoo.com Abstract: In this article I have examined how Kuhn uses the evolutionary analogy to analyze the problem of scientific progress.

More information

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN Book reviews 123 The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN 9780199693672 John Hawthorne and David Manley wrote an excellent book on the

More information

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic 1 Reply to Stalnaker Timothy Williamson In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic as Metaphysics between contingentism in modal metaphysics and the use of

More information

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason THE A PRIORI GROUNDS OF THE POSSIBILITY OF EXPERIENCE THAT a concept, although itself neither contained in the concept of possible experience nor consisting of elements

More information

iafor The International Academic Forum

iafor The International Academic Forum A Study on the Core Concepts of Environmental Aesthetics Curriculum Ya-Ting Lee, National Pingtung University, Taiwan The Asian Conference on Arts and Humanities 2017 Official Conference Proceedings Abstract

More information

Valuable Particulars

Valuable Particulars CHAPTER ONE Valuable Particulars One group of commentators whose discussion this essay joins includes John McDowell, Martha Nussbaum, Nancy Sherman, and Stephen G. Salkever. McDowell is an early contributor

More information

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction Introduction Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] As Kant emphasized, famously, there s a difference between

More information

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver Truth and Tropes by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver Trope theory has been focused on the metaphysics of a theory of tropes that eliminates the need for appeal to universals or properties. This has naturally

More information

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15) Michael Lacewing Kant on conceptual schemes INTRODUCTION Try to imagine what it would be like to have sensory experience but with no ability to think about it. Thinking about sensory experience requires

More information

The Effects of Web Site Aesthetics and Shopping Task on Consumer Online Purchasing Behavior

The Effects of Web Site Aesthetics and Shopping Task on Consumer Online Purchasing Behavior The Effects of Web Site Aesthetics and Shopping Task on Consumer Online Purchasing Behavior Cai, Shun The Logistics Institute - Asia Pacific E3A, Level 3, 7 Engineering Drive 1, Singapore 117574 tlics@nus.edu.sg

More information

Criterion A: Understanding knowledge issues

Criterion A: Understanding knowledge issues Theory of knowledge assessment exemplars Page 1 of2 Assessed student work Example 4 Introduction Purpose of this document Assessed student work Overview Example 1 Example 2 Example 3 Example 4 Example

More information

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality Spring Magazine on English Literature, (E-ISSN: 2455-4715), Vol. II, No. 1, 2016. Edited by Dr. KBS Krishna URL of the Issue: www.springmagazine.net/v2n1 URL of the article: http://springmagazine.net/v2/n1/02_kant_subjective_universality.pdf

More information

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism THIS PDF FILE FOR PROMOTIONAL USE ONLY 6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism Representationism, 1 as I use the term, says that the phenomenal character of an experience just is its representational

More information

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth Mauricio SUÁREZ and Albert SOLÉ BIBLID [0495-4548 (2006) 21: 55; pp. 39-48] ABSTRACT: In this paper we claim that the notion of cognitive representation

More information

What s Really Disgusting

What s Really Disgusting What s Really Disgusting Mary Elizabeth Carman 0404113A Supervised by Dr Lucy Allais, Department of Philosophy University of the Witwatersrand February 2009 A research report submitted to the Faculty of

More information

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

The Teaching Method of Creative Education Creative Education 2013. Vol.4, No.8A, 25-30 Published Online August 2013 in SciRes (http://www.scirp.org/journal/ce) http://dx.doi.org/10.4236/ce.2013.48a006 The Teaching Method of Creative Education

More information

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers Cast of Characters X-Phi: Experimental Philosophy E-Phi: Empirical Philosophy A-Phi: Armchair Philosophy Challenges to Experimental Philosophy Empirical

More information

Types of perceptual content

Types of perceptual content Types of perceptual content Jeff Speaks January 29, 2006 1 Objects vs. contents of perception......................... 1 2 Three views of content in the philosophy of language............... 2 3 Perceptual

More information

Editorial Policy. 1. Purpose and scope. 2. General submission rules

Editorial Policy. 1. Purpose and scope. 2. General submission rules Editorial Policy 1. Purpose and scope Central European Journal of Engineering (CEJE) is a peer-reviewed, quarterly published journal devoted to the publication of research results in the following areas

More information

Ashraf M. Salama. Functionalism Revisited: Architectural Theories and Practice and the Behavioral Sciences. Jon Lang and Walter Moleski

Ashraf M. Salama. Functionalism Revisited: Architectural Theories and Practice and the Behavioral Sciences. Jon Lang and Walter Moleski 127 Review and Trigger Articles FUNCTIONALISM AND THE CONTEMPORARY ARCHITECTURAL DISCOURSE: A REVIEW OF FUNCTIONALISM REVISITED BY JOHN LANG AND WALTER MOLESKI. Publisher: ASHGATE, Hard Cover: 356 pages

More information

Second Grade: National Visual Arts Core Standards

Second Grade: National Visual Arts Core Standards Second Grade: National Visual Arts Core Standards Connecting #VA:Cn10.1 Process Component: Interpret Anchor Standard: Synthesize and relate knowledge and personal experiences to make art. Enduring Understanding:

More information

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective DAVID T. LARSON University of Kansas Kant suggests that his contribution to philosophy is analogous to the contribution of Copernicus to astronomy each involves

More information

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension Bahriye Selin Gokcesu (bgokcesu@hsc.edu) Department of Psychology, 1 College Rd. Hampden Sydney, VA, 23948 Abstract One of the prevailing questions

More information

Against Metaphysical Disjunctivism

Against Metaphysical Disjunctivism 32 Against Metaphysical Disjunctivism PASCAL LUDWIG AND EMILE THALABARD We first met the core ideas of disjunctivism through the teaching and writing of Pascal Engel 1. At the time, the view seemed to

More information

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press. Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press. Australasian Journal of Philosophy 84 (4) 640-642, December 2006 Michael

More information

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility> A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of Ryu MURAKAMI Although rarely pointed out, Henri Bergson (1859-1941), a French philosopher, in his later years argues on from his particular

More information

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics

Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics 472 Abstracts SUSAN L. FEAGIN Emotions from the Perspective of Analytic Aesthetics Analytic philosophy is not what it used to be and thank goodness. Its practice in the late Twentieth and early Twenty-first

More information

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that Wiggins, S. (2009). Discourse analysis. In Harry T. Reis & Susan Sprecher (Eds.), Encyclopedia of Human Relationships. Pp. 427-430. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage. Discourse analysis Discourse analysis is an

More information

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION Submitted by Jessica Murski Department of Philosophy In partial fulfillment of the requirements For the Degree of Master of Arts Colorado State University

More information

GLOSSARY for National Core Arts: Visual Arts STANDARDS

GLOSSARY for National Core Arts: Visual Arts STANDARDS GLOSSARY for National Core Arts: Visual Arts STANDARDS Visual Arts, as defined by the National Art Education Association, include the traditional fine arts, such as, drawing, painting, printmaking, photography,

More information

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton This essay will explore a number of issues raised by the approaches to the philosophy of language offered by Locke and Frege. This

More information

Aesthetics For Life. W1: What is Aesthetics? Dr. Meagan Louie. Ratto di Prosperina -Gian Lorenzo Bernini. The unexamined life is not worth living.

Aesthetics For Life. W1: What is Aesthetics? Dr. Meagan Louie. Ratto di Prosperina -Gian Lorenzo Bernini. The unexamined life is not worth living. Aesthetics For Life W1: What is Aesthetics? The unexamined life is not worth living. - Attributed to Socrates Ratto di Prosperina -Gian Lorenzo Bernini Outline 1 What is Aesthetics? 1.1 Aesthetics and

More information

A Kantian Critique of Positive Aesthetics of Nature

A Kantian Critique of Positive Aesthetics of Nature JONATHAN PARKER A Kantian Critique of Positive Aesthetics of Nature I. INTRODUCTION Readers of Kant s Critique of Judgment can readily observe that upon introducing aesthetic judgment, Kant then proceeds

More information

SHORT TERM PITCH MEMORY IN WESTERN vs. OTHER EQUAL TEMPERAMENT TUNING SYSTEMS

SHORT TERM PITCH MEMORY IN WESTERN vs. OTHER EQUAL TEMPERAMENT TUNING SYSTEMS SHORT TERM PITCH MEMORY IN WESTERN vs. OTHER EQUAL TEMPERAMENT TUNING SYSTEMS Areti Andreopoulou Music and Audio Research Laboratory New York University, New York, USA aa1510@nyu.edu Morwaread Farbood

More information

observation and conceptual interpretation

observation and conceptual interpretation 1 observation and conceptual interpretation Most people will agree that observation and conceptual interpretation constitute two major ways through which human beings engage the world. Questions about

More information

Journal for contemporary philosophy

Journal for contemporary philosophy ARIANNA BETTI ON HASLANGER S FOCAL ANALYSIS OF RACE AND GENDER IN RESISTING REALITY AS AN INTERPRETIVE MODEL Krisis 2014, Issue 1 www.krisis.eu In Resisting Reality (Haslanger 2012), and more specifically

More information

Literature: An Introduction to Reading and Writing

Literature: An Introduction to Reading and Writing Literature: An Introduction to Reading and Writing by Roberts and Jacobs English Composition III Mary F. Clifford, Instructor What Is Literature and Why Do We Study It? Literature is Composition that tells

More information

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars By John Henry McDowell Cambridge, Massachusetts and London, England: Harvard University

More information

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign? How many concepts of normative sign are needed About limits of applying Peircean concept of logical sign University of Tampere Department of Mathematics, Statistics, and Philosophy Peircean concept of

More information

"The mind is a fire to be kindled, not a vessel to be filled." Plutarch

The mind is a fire to be kindled, not a vessel to be filled. Plutarch "The mind is a fire to be kindled, not a vessel to be filled." Plutarch -21 Special Topics: Music Perception Winter, 2004 TTh 11:30 to 12:50 a.m., MAB 125 Dr. Scott D. Lipscomb, Associate Professor Office

More information

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART Tatyana Shopova Associate Professor PhD Head of the Center for New Media and Digital Culture Department of Cultural Studies, Faculty of Arts South-West University

More information

PART ONE: PHILOSOPHY AND THE OTHER MINDS

PART ONE: PHILOSOPHY AND THE OTHER MINDS PART ONE: PHILOSOPHY AND THE OTHER MINDS As we have no immediate experience of what other men feel, we can form no idea of the manner in which they are affected, but by conceiving what we ourselves should

More information

c. MP claims that this is one s primary knowledge of the world and as it is not conscious as is evident in the case of the phantom limb patient

c. MP claims that this is one s primary knowledge of the world and as it is not conscious as is evident in the case of the phantom limb patient Dualism 1. Intro 2. The dualism between physiological and psychological a. The physiological explanations of the phantom limb do not work accounts for it as the suppression of the stimuli that should cause

More information

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy 1 Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy Politics is older than philosophy. According to Olof Gigon in Ancient Greece philosophy was born in opposition to the politics (and the

More information

Improving Piano Sight-Reading Skills of College Student. Chian yi Ang. Penn State University

Improving Piano Sight-Reading Skills of College Student. Chian yi Ang. Penn State University Improving Piano Sight-Reading Skill of College Student 1 Improving Piano Sight-Reading Skills of College Student Chian yi Ang Penn State University 1 I grant The Pennsylvania State University the nonexclusive

More information

Writing an Honors Preface

Writing an Honors Preface Writing an Honors Preface What is a Preface? Prefatory matter to books generally includes forewords, prefaces, introductions, acknowledgments, and dedications (as well as reference information such as

More information

Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in Wang Zhaowen s Beauty- Goodness-Relationship Theory

Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in Wang Zhaowen s Beauty- Goodness-Relationship Theory Canadian Social Science Vol. 12, No. 1, 2016, pp. 29-33 DOI:10.3968/7988 ISSN 1712-8056[Print] ISSN 1923-6697[Online] www.cscanada.net www.cscanada.org Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in

More information

DAT335 Music Perception and Cognition Cogswell Polytechnical College Spring Week 6 Class Notes

DAT335 Music Perception and Cognition Cogswell Polytechnical College Spring Week 6 Class Notes DAT335 Music Perception and Cognition Cogswell Polytechnical College Spring 2009 Week 6 Class Notes Pitch Perception Introduction Pitch may be described as that attribute of auditory sensation in terms

More information

Expressive performance in music: Mapping acoustic cues onto facial expressions

Expressive performance in music: Mapping acoustic cues onto facial expressions International Symposium on Performance Science ISBN 978-94-90306-02-1 The Author 2011, Published by the AEC All rights reserved Expressive performance in music: Mapping acoustic cues onto facial expressions

More information

Space is Body Centred. Interview with Sonia Cillari Annet Dekker

Space is Body Centred. Interview with Sonia Cillari Annet Dekker Space is Body Centred Interview with Sonia Cillari Annet Dekker 169 Space is Body Centred Sonia Cillari s work has an emotional and physical focus. By tracking electromagnetic fields, activity, movements,

More information

Aristotle on the Human Good

Aristotle on the Human Good 24.200: Aristotle Prof. Sally Haslanger November 15, 2004 Aristotle on the Human Good Aristotle believes that in order to live a well-ordered life, that life must be organized around an ultimate or supreme

More information

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism phil 93515 Jeff Speaks April 18, 2007 1 Traditional cases of spectrum inversion Remember that minimal intentionalism is the claim that any two experiences

More information

Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement

Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement Peter Desain, Henkjan Honing and Renee Timmers Music, Mind, Machine Group NICI, University of Nijmegen mmm@nici.kun.nl, www.nici.kun.nl/mmm In this

More information

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Journal Code: ANAL Proofreader: Elsie Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp anal_580-594.fm Page 22 Monday, October 31, 2005 6:10 PM 22 andy clark

More information

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD Unit Code: Unit Name: Department: Faculty: 475Z022 METAPHYSICS (INBOUND STUDENT MOBILITY - JAN ENTRY) Politics & Philosophy Faculty Of Arts & Humanities Level: 5 Credits: 5 ECTS: 7.5 This unit will address

More information

Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology, Blackwell, 1985, pp THEORIES OF PERCEPTION

Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology, Blackwell, 1985, pp THEORIES OF PERCEPTION Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology, Blackwell, 1985, pp. 144-174. 10.2 THEORIES OF PERCEPTION There are three main families of theories of perception: direct realism,

More information

On Recanati s Mental Files

On Recanati s Mental Files November 18, 2013. Penultimate version. Final version forthcoming in Inquiry. On Recanati s Mental Files Dilip Ninan dilip.ninan@tufts.edu 1 Frege (1892) introduced us to the notion of a sense or a mode

More information

Emotion, an Organ of Happiness. Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University

Emotion, an Organ of Happiness. Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University Emotion, an Organ of Happiness Ruey-Yuan Wu National Tsing-Hua University Introduction: How did it all begin? In view of the success of modern sciences, philosophers have been trying to come up with a

More information