Reviel Netz, The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics: A Study in Cognitive History

Similar documents
Sidestepping the holes of holism

From Pythagoras to the Digital Computer: The Intellectual Roots of Symbolic Artificial Intelligence

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

Many findings in archaeology bear witness to some math in

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Module 11. Reasoning with uncertainty-fuzzy Reasoning. Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

web address: address: Description

Humanities Learning Outcomes

The Object Oriented Paradigm

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Scientific Philosophy

Mathematics in Ancient Iraq: A Social History (review)

Logical Foundations of Mathematics and Computational Complexity a gentle introduction

On Language, Discourse and Reality

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Warm-Up Question: How did geography affect the development of ancient Greece?

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

AREA OF KNOWLEDGE: MATHEMATICS

Math in the Byzantine Context

Meaning, Use, and Diagrams

Reviewed by Annette Imhausen Johannes Gutenberg University, Mainz

Divine Ratio. Envisioning Aesthetic Proportion in Architecture and Art. HRS 290 Mack Bishop September 28, 2010

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

Background to Gottlob Frege

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

HISTORY 104A History of Ancient Science

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

The Debate on Research in the Arts

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

THE GOLDEN AGE POETRY

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

Curry s Formalism as Structuralism

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Non-Classical Logics. Viorica Sofronie-Stokkermans Winter Semester 2012/2013

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Truth, American Culture, and Fuzzy Logic

Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic

Cultural History of Mathematics

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Chapter 1 Overview of Music Theories

Free Ebooks A Beautiful Question: Finding Nature's Deep Design

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

I typed Pythagoras into a search terminal in the M.D. Anderson Library. Is Pavlovian the

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Objective vs. Subjective

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

AN ABSTRACT OF THE THESIS OF

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Department of Chemistry. University of Colombo, Sri Lanka. 1. Format. Required Required 11. Appendices Where Required

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

This work is simultaneously expansive and narrow in its scope. It is

ARISTOTLE (c BC) AND SIZE-DISTANCE INVARIANCE

observation and conceptual interpretation

Lectures On The History Of Philosophy, Volume 1: Greek Philosophy To Plato By E. S. Haldane, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

By Maximus Monaheng Sefotho (PhD). 16 th June, 2015

Permutations of the Octagon: An Aesthetic-Mathematical Dialectic

Correlation to Common Core State Standards Books A-F for Grade 5

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Tools for Thinking. Chapter Introduction. 2.2 Formal Systems. Always Be Prepared. Boy Scout Motto

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

The Concept of Nature

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: B. C. 3.

Greek Achievements. Key Terms Socrates Plato Aristotle reason Euclid Hippocrates. Plato

THE INDIAN KEYBOARD. Gjalt Wijmenga

TOWARDS A BEHAVIORAL PSYCHOLOGY OF MATHEMATICAL THINKING

Classical Studies Courses-1

PHILOSOPH ICAL PERSPECTI VES ON PROOF IN MATHEMATI CS EDUCATION

Ancient Greece --- LANDSCAPE

Fig. I.1 The Fields Medal.

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

Reflections on Kant s concept (and intuition) of space

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Special Issue on Ideas of Plato in the Philosophy of the 21st Century : An Introduction

Introduction Section 1: Logic. The basic purpose is to learn some elementary logic.

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

VISUALISATION AND PROOF: A BRIEF SURVEY

Introduction: A Musico-Logical Offering

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

Transcription:

Reviel Netz, The Shaping of Deduction in Greek Mathematics: A Study in Cognitive History. (Ideas in Context, 51). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999. Paperback edition 2003. Published in Studia Logica 80 (2005), 143 147. This book was extremely important at its appearance, and no less so today when available in paperback. It does not deal primarily nor systematically with the contents of Greek mathematics, impressing but well explored as this is (sometimes in anachronistic compromises with modern understanding, sometimes in less anachronistic presentation). Nor does it deal exclusively with deduction per se; what it offers is an investigation of the cognitive-structural factors which shaped the emergence of deductive mathematics, and a further exploration of the way this deduction directly concerned with particular objects only produced knowledge of general validity knowledge not just about the particular right triangle ABC of the diagram but about all right triangles. All of this is concerned with the form of Greek mathematics, that is, with that which makes Greek mathematics stand out as a historical novelty (becoming eventually the standard model for how mathematics should be configured). As Netz points out (p. 3), his project has some affinity with that of recent sociology of science, but the approach is different, asking not just what made science the way it was but what made science successful, and successful in a real intellectual sense not seeing deduction as a sociological construct [but] as an objectively valid form, whose discovery was a positive achievement ; in this he is even closer to Kuhn than he is aware of, but to the rather unknown Kuhn of 1961/63, 1 the one who emphasized the importance for shared training ( finger exercises ) and not just shared beliefs for the development of that paradigm which establishes a scientific community with a shared practice. Most of the argument, namely chapters 1 6, and most of the new insights which emerge, are based on very close attention to various features of the mathematical texts. The last chapter, The historical setting, goes beyond the texts and explores what we know about the development of the Greek mathematical enterprise in a wider historical context. Mathematical texts consist of lettered diagrams and words. That Greek mathematics (not only geometry) makes use of lettered diagrams is so familiar that we have forgotten to think about what it implies; that its words not only belong to a restricted lexicon but are also used within a highly formulaic language is also familiar for anybody reading them in Greek but with one exception (Germaine Aujac, credited for inspiration by Netz), nobody again has analyzed the air we breathe, and nobody seems to have been aware of how restricted and standardized the language is for instance, 1 The Function of Dogma in Scientific Research, first presented at an Oxford Symposium in 1961, in A. C. Crombie, (ed.), Scientific Change, 347 369 (London: Heinemann, 1963).

that synonyms are very rare. Netz analyzes both, also extensive statistics at hand, thus coming to understand the cognitive metabolism sustained by them. Indeed, in fairly large samples from Euclid, Archimedes, Apollonios (and others), every word has been registered several times according to various parameters, and every letter in a diagram taken note of similarly. Along another dimension, mathematical texts are partially first-order (making the mathematics), partially second-order (speaking about mathematics). The second-order parts mostly contain no lettered diagrams, their lexicon is much larger and more varied, and they consist of real language, not formulae. Writing a mathematical text was clearly an activity which the Greek mathematician kept very distinct from writing anything else, even an introductory letter (or a definition!). Lettered diagrams and the use of a small array of formulae serve a common function: to reduce the fuzziness of geometrical space and of natural language arguing about it to finite mathematics. 2 For Netz, the details of the lettering (the order in which letters appear in proofs, the statistics of cases where, e.g., line AB returns as line BA) serve to demonstrate that the construction of the diagram precedes the writing of the final text of the proof, which can be understood as a secondary, written version of a tale told about the diagram. Of particular interest in a logicians context are Netz s conclusions concerning the function of definitions: as a rule they do not settle linguistic usage; they are part of the second-order discourse catering to the wish to say something on the what it is question, functioning as axioms, or expressing explicitly the extension of concepts (p. 103) not exactly according to Aristotle s book. Formulae are then the building blocks for the arguments of the proofs; but a formula is not in itself a premise. At the level of premises the notion of the tool box comes in (borrowed with explicit credit from Ken Saito). Greek mathematical treatises may contain explicit backward references to results obtained within the same treatise; but they never contain the references to, e.g., Elements I.47, familiar from modern translations. However, they presuppose a large number of propositions with which the reader is supposed to be familiar enough to recognize and accept them as true. Most of this tool box turns out to be contained in the Elements (minus book X), and a large proportion of the theorems from the Elements turn up as constituents of the tool box. The Data provide quite a few constituents. Propositions from more advanced treatises are extremely rare. 3 2 E.g., a point may be outside, on or inside a circle. According to the (admittedly medieval) manuscript evidence, diagrams were not meant to be metrically correct but as structure diagrams characterizing the situation. In arithmetic, dealing with a countable infinity of qualitatively distinct situations, things are more complex; Netz suggests that this may be one reason that the diagrams of arithmetical proofs represent numbers by lines, not by dot patterns. 3 This is fully confirmed by the outcome of Saito s tool box project, based on a different

The tool box constituents enter as premises in arguments, which in first-order mathematical texts are ordered as almost linear chains, with few interruptions and rare backward-looking arguments (stating the reasons after the conclusion they lead to); second-order texts containing mathematical proofs are shown to behave differently Netz analyzes Aristotle s geometrical discussion of the rainbow (Meteorology 373 a 6 30) and Archimedes Method. Once the tool box is accepted, the linear progression makes the proofs inescapable in a way (e.g.) philosophical texts never were. Inescapable but in the first instance only for the particular diagram dealt with. How does this type of argument on what is properly no more than a paradigmatic case produce theorems of general validity? Netz, continuing a line of thought inaugurated by Ian Mueller, 4 proposes an answer to the problem which should both be satisfying to us and coincide with that understanding of the matter which shines through the actual organization of the proofs (first a general enunciation, then a paradigmatic example formulated around a lettered diagram leading to a conclusion about this diagram, then a general conclusion repeating verbatim the enunciation). What guarantees general validity is repeatability for any other case. 5 Generality thus is not algorithmic, no quantifiers occur in the text; understanding it asks for mathematical intelligence (Mueller s term); however, as Netz points out (going beyond Mueller), even Hilbert s Grundlagen contains no explicit quantifiers, even readers of Hilbert have to be mathematically intelligent and see that they can be applied. The last chapter on the historical setting falls into three parts. The beginning of Greek mathematics (where mathematics is, as throughout the book, to be understood as mathematics based on explicit proof ) gives sound reasons for rejecting a gradual development beginning in the sixth century BC (e.g., sample but not yet finished when Netz s book was written see: http://www.greekmath.org/pappus_index_0.html (Pappos Collection, book VII) and http://www.greekmath.org/apollonius_index.html (Apollonios, Conics I-IV). 4 Philosophy of Mathematics and Deductive Structure in Euclid s Elements, 12 14. Cambridge, Mass., & London: MIT Press, 1981 5 We are thus not very far from what we read in Aristotle s Metaphysics XIII, 1078 a 16 21 (Aristotle, The Metaphysics, vol. II, transl. Hugh Tredennick, correction in ; Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press / London: Heinemann, 1935): Thus if we regard objects independently of their accidents and investigate any aspect of them as so regarded, we shall not be guilty of any error on this account, any more than when we draw a diagram on the ground and say that a line is a foot long when it is not; because the error is not in the premises. But Aristotle s theory of abstraction should not automatically be ascribed to the mathematicians; it rather represents his attempt to make sense of the practice of these. Moreover, Aristotle does not address the issue of generality explicitly any more than do the mathematicians.

with Thales, Pythagoras, or the Pythagoreans 6 ); instead he suggests that the earliest mathematical author whom Eudemos really knows was indeed the first of his kind that is, that Greek mathematics was created around 440 BC, by Hippocrates, Oinopides, and a few others. Our first evidence for mathematics practically in Euclidean style is Aristotle. Demography looks at the mathematicians. All belonged to the elite Greek mathematicians were machines that transformed leisure into theorems (to paraphrase a familiar saying about modern mathematicians and coffee). Of such strange machines there were at most a thousand throughout Antiquity (a full millennium) statistical analysis of late ancient sources (Pappos, Proclos, Eutocios) shows that the total number of names known in their times will have been around 300; both numbers presuppose a very permissive definition of the term, encompassing anybody who at some moment in his life made a piece of explicitly reasoned mathematics. Even in the heyday of Greek mathematics, Archimedes was desolate when Conon died who would then be able to understand him? In later centuries, Augustine will certainly not have been alone in the experience to have to learn Euclid on his own, nobody he knew about being able to explain it to him (Confessions IV.xvi.30). Greek mathematics, though shaped by oral-type tales about lettered diagram, could only exist as an extremely literate undertaking. Papyri, inscription and the total surviving textual evidence also shows that interest in (theoretical) mathematics was utterly rare outside the Platonic and Aristotelian philosophical schools and the Galenic medical tradition (itself close to Aristotelianism). More popular was what Netz characterizes (p. 290) as the book which suddenly becomes a bestseller after being turned into a film in the version according to the film : that is, (Neo)Pythagorean and Neoplatonic numerology; but this is not explicitly reasoned mathematics (and hardly implicitly reasoned). But on the whole, as Netz concludes (p. 289), Greek culture, excluding the Platonic-Aristotelian tradition, knew no mathematics the quadrivium is a myth. Mathematics within Greek culture is where Netz comes closest to the concerns of the sociology of scientific knowledge, if not to prevailing approaches. Netz locates the mathematicians practice in the tense intersection between the agonistic debate culture of the public domain of the polis, the quiet retreat from politics common from Plato s time onward, an international intellectual network mimicking the institution of institutionalized friendship ; at the intersection between oral and literate culture, between democracy and aristocracy, between theoretical interest in the material world and productive application of insights (the former being ideologically acceptable to the elite, the latter a provocation of the banausic anxiety of the ancient upper classes (p. 303). The argument is much too complex to render within a single paragraph, but 6 Pythagoras fares worst of all: Pythagoras the mathematician perished finally AD 1962 (p. 272), the year Walter Burkert s Weisheit und Wissenschaft (Nürnberg: Hans Carl) was published.

well documented and certainly worth reading. 7 Not concentrating on the contents, the book contains very little technical mathematics. In spite of its concentration on vocabulary, most of it asks for no understanding of Greek. It is very well written (it shines through that Netz is also a publishing poet). The only reason it is difficult to read is that almost every sentence, indeed next to every clause, carries a message that asks for the reader s active thought. It can safely be recommended as a must to anybody who is genuinely interested in the relation between Greek mathematics and logic and not satisfied with the book according to the various films of standard philosophy of mathematics and standard historiography of mathematics. Jens Høyrup 7 For late Antiquity, it can be read withe advantage along with Serafina Cuomo, Pappus of Alexandria and the Mathematics of Late Antiquity (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2000). But is should be kept in mind that Cuomo s analysis includes mathematical practitioners and the colporteurs of the book according to the film, thus a much wider group.