Ends of Enlightenment, by John Bender. Stanford: Stanford UP, Pp $ ISBN:

Similar documents
Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

George Levine, Darwin the Writer, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, 272 pp.

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Introduction and Overview

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Humanities Learning Outcomes

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Architecture is epistemologically

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Marilyn Francus, ENGL 635, Spring 2005, History of the Novel

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Peter Johnston: Teaching Improvisation and the Pedagogical History of the Jimmy

Book Review: Gries Still Life with Rhetoric

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Methods, Topics, and Trends in Recent Business History Scholarship

Categories and Schemata

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Art, Social Justice, and Critical Theory Colloquium:

Art, Mind and Cognitive Science

AP ENGLISH LITERATURE AND COMPOSITION 2014 SCORING GUIDELINES

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Vinod Lakshmipathy Phil 591- Hermeneutics Prof. Theodore Kisiel

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism?

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Dialogical encounter argument as a source of rigour in the practice based PhD

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

observation and conceptual interpretation

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

Glossary of Rhetorical Terms*

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

Representation and Discourse Analysis

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

BRANIGAN, Edward. Narrative Comprehension and Film. London/New York : Routledge, 1992, 325 pp.

Credibility and the Continuing Struggle to Find Truth. We consume a great amount of information in our day-to-day lives, whether it is

1/9. The B-Deduction

AP Studio Art 2006 Scoring Guidelines

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

HISTORY ADMISSIONS TEST. Marking Scheme for the 2015 paper

Research Projects on Rudolf Steiner'sWorldview

Investigating subjectivity

Durham Research Online

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

Post 2 1 April 2015 The Prison-house of Postmodernism On Fredric Jameson s The Aesthetics of Singularity

Theories and Activities of Conceptual Artists: An Aesthetic Inquiry

1. situation (or community) 2. substance (content) and style (form)

Ambiguity/Language/Learning Ron Burnett President, Emily Carr Institute of Art + Design

Introduction. Critique of Commodity Aesthetics

Editor s Introduction

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Hear hear. Århus, 11 January An acoustemological manifesto

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Nature's Perspectives

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Leverhulme Research Project Grant Narrating Complexity: Communication, Culture, Conceptualization and Cognition

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

THE DIFFERENT LANGUAGES OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

Your Name. Instructor Name. Course Name. Date submitted. Summary Outline # Chapter 1 What Is Literature? How and Why Does It Matter?

Royce: The Anthropology of Dance

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.

Transcription:

Ends of Enlightenment, by John Bender. Stanford: Stanford UP, 2012. Pp. 294. $25.95. ISBN: 978-0-8047-4212-2. Beyond its brief introduction, John Bender s Ends of Enlightenment contains nothing new. Instead, it is a collection of ten separate articles and book chapters some cowritten, all previously published from as early as 1987 and as recently as 2010. While it is unfortunate, or at least curious, that Bender does not revisit or revise some of his conclusions in light of more recent and sometimes more sophisticated interpretive trends, the book does testify to the impressively interdisciplinary breadth of his scholarly expertise; as a broad compendium of his various projects, it also exposes a number of subtending thematic continuities in his own thought and thus raises new and important questions concerning the connections and correlations among his apparently disparate subjects. Its strength, in other words, is its novel organization of his established conclusions. This is an almost performative illustration of the basic hypothesis that informs the whole book, namely, that intellectual systems are not logically prior to the substance they organize, but rather that modes and objects of thought are mutually constitutive: the organization of knowledge implicates, even determines, its effects. The few new pages that open Ends of Enlightenment situate this hypothesis with respect to Bender s long-standing scholarly agenda: to bring contemporary critical strategies to bear upon Enlightenment texts and the social formations they developed in order to incorporate the early novel into the pantheon of practical philosophy. To this end, he fashions himself after both David Hume and Michel Foucault. He is a self-described skeptical historicist whose use of empirical evidence frames the past in the manner of the vignette rather than of the grand narrative (17). Bender s, in other words, is a postmodern Enlightenment, which is to say, an Enlightenment reconceived not as a unified historical event but as a set of discrete, sometimes overlapping, and often contradictory narratives, most of them emerging in the eighteenth century and all of them orbiting around a common crisis of authority brought about by that period s epochal destabilization of traditional structures of Digital Defoe: Studies in Defoe & His Contemporaries 6, no. 1 (fall 2014) ISSN 1948-1802

knowledge and power. Hume receives extensive treatment in the following chapters, but the clear methodological resonance with Foucault s work and legacy is only briefly noted; like his earlier Imagining the Penitentiary, Bender explains, some of the essays in this new collection were written under the sign of Foucault (15) in the same critical spirit, we might say, if not always according to the same investigative tactics or with Foucault s overtly political implications. Be that as it may, this is a welcome articulation of the value for eighteenth-century scholarship of what Bender (following Diderot) calls contemporaneity (3 4), and a reminder of the restrictions that the field s often antiquarian sensibilities can impose against its potential relevance to the present. In addition to these primary influences, and despite an extensive range of scholarly sources, a short list of contemporary texts orients Bender s various lines of inquiry. The several chapters concerning the historical correlation between the rise of modern science and the rise of the novel all lean upon the notion of virtual witnessing developed in Steven Shapin and Simon Schaffer s Leviathan and the Air- Pump; his account of the emergence of rational deliberation as a basic principle of social organization closely follows Jürgen Habermas s The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere (without, however, accounting for Foucault s famous disagreement with Habermas, which leaves us to wonder whether and how Bender conceives of his work as an implicit synthesis of the two); Dorrit Cohn s Transparent Minds orients his claims concerning the epistemological stakes of the early novel and the emergence of free indirect discourse; and behind much of this is a tacit and deferential elaboration of Ian Watt s basic premises joining empiricism with narrative realism in The Rise of the Novel. Indeed, these texts appear so regularly that in some cases the same passages are quoted in one chapter and the next, the same concepts defined and then severally repeated. This reminder of the text s inherent disunity and absence of revision seems both unfortunate and unnecessary, although they do demonstrate a deep conceptual consistency. Such consistency is not always patent, however, and requires that the reader establish and develop connections, or at times discern possible contradictions, across these essays. Example: the first chapter, which originally appeared in Clifford Siskin and William Warner s recent collection, This Is Enlightenment, follows Watt s notion of realism of assessment by tracing the development not only of empiricism (Watt s primary concern), but more specifically of inductive scientific reasoning, from Bacon, Newton, and Boyle to Defoe, Richardson, and Fielding. Here, Bender quotes Samuel Richardson describing to a friend the Air of Genuineness with which he wished to imbue his Clarissa, and borrows Catherine Gallagher s term ironic credulity to characterize how Richardson places his reader on a skeptical knife-edge between acceptance of his novelistic letters as real and awareness that they are fictions (30 31). In other words, Richardson wanted to compose a novel that was false but also probable, thereby illustrating and popularizing the growing power of what Bender 152

calls surrogate observation (28) to truth claims in the eighteenth century. Now, the same passage from Clarissa appears just ten pages later in chapter 2, the topic of which is (relatedly) the early novel and the history of the scientific method. This time, however, Richardson is quoted in the context of Hume s notorious skepticism from his Treatise on Human Nature; in lieu of ironic credulity, Bender now calls Richardson s fiction a provisional reality (41). Far from consolidating the new hegemony of the scientific method, novels like Clarissa posed a major threat to scientific authority and its assertions of material truth by revealing that, if strategically framed, any testimony to scientific fact might really be a work of fiction. Certainly, both claims can be true: Clarissa could reflect and reify the formal demands of inductive reasoning of ascending from particular observations to general truths and, precisely because it so effectively mimics this scientific frame, expose the potential for untruth intrinsic to every translation from the laboratory to the public. If this is so, it falls to the reader to reach such conclusions and to work out their implications. So be it. But this analytic gap also raises questions about theoretical consistency. Does the concept of ironic credulity not at least complicate that of provisional reality, or are they mere synonyms? Is Hume s link between probability and uncertainty really commensurate with Richardson s ironic skeptical knife-edge strategy? Is the oppositional articulation of science and fiction across the eighteenth century at odds with the latter s instrumental role in validating the new empiricism? If so, are there perhaps two competing tendencies in the early novel, one validating science and the other radically undermining its epistemological foundations? Chapter 5, The Novel as Modern Myth, further indicates why these are far from rhetorical questions. Bender groups Robinson Crusoe, Frankenstein, and Dracula together and speculates that their lasting power may result from their stylistic vaporization their use of verisimilitude to erase the fact of their historicity, the fact that they are recent fabrications, such that here fiction reflects or refracts reality in ways that essentially mirror the power and social function of myth. On this view, these metanovels modern myths in their revelation of unreality within the real (107) continue to captivate because of the exceptional degree to which they enable us to assume, through surrogate projection, the illusion of sharing the firsthand experience of others (106). This is an intriguing idea, to be sure, and one which Bender claims would install the gothic novel as the paradigm of novelistic discourse as such but which again begs the question of narrative realism s relation to scientific truth. For if these novels, these paragons of realism, attain the status of myth not despite their realism but because they are so nearly real, then what does this reveal about the early novel s filiation with the rise of materialism, naturalism, and induction? Would this imply a mythology at the heart of scientific knowledge, or at least of its contemporary valorization? What would this mean for the very idea of truth, after its Enlightenment iteration? Again, the strength of Ends of Enlightenment is its capacity to provoke such questions; its weakness, however, is that the essays 153

collected here are largely preliminary understandable for a stand-alone article or book chapter and therefore evade the deeper conceptual precision that one would expect from a complete volume. Despite these drawbacks, the theoretically preliminary chapters prove useful to establishing the grid of historical phenomena into which Bender can install his more patient readings of specific texts. Chapter 4 (co-written with Robin Valenza) considers Hume s reasons for trading the technical philosophical precision of his Treatise on Human Nature for the less sophisticated but more popular style of his later essays and Enquiries, and evaluates what is lost in the translation from a specialized discourse into the conversible world of the new public sphere. The earlier chapters outlining the strategies by which experimental science dealt with the same problem of maintaining intellectual rigor while also convincing a general public of the validity of its experimental results provide an excellent general background against which this specific, and especially compelling, case is illuminated. Chapter 3 clusters William Hogarth s experimental aesthetic sensibility apropos of non-human objects, Habermas s position on the value of experiment to the emergence of a rational public sphere, and Martin Heidegger s notion of facticity. The last of these is a rather clumsy addition facticity and instrumental rationality are far from consistent; the only footnote to Heidegger s work refers readers to Being and Time in its entirety, a citation which is, to say the least, not helpful; and the argument seems to gain nothing from this ontological intrusion. But pairing Hogarth with Habermas does paint a clear image of Habermas s version of Enlightenment, which clarifies later chapters addressing novelistic contributions to this culture of rational deliberation, idealized though it may be. This prepares the claim in chapter 6 that Tom Jones is governed by an ideal of intelligent, broadly educated sociability that lies at the heart of Fielding s achievement as an author no less than of the eighteenth century itself (116). These two chapters also lay the groundwork for the volume s final essay, a collaboration with David E. Wellbery which considers the resurgence of rhetoric in the twentieth century, after the Enlightenment s communicative rationalism had rendered its classical form obsolete. Chapters 7 and 8, on Oliver Goldsmith s The Vicar of Wakefield and William Godwin s Caleb Williams, respectively, nuance the theoretical framework Bender first developed in Imagining the Penitentiary, but also exemplify the skeptical historicism outlined above: both essays excavate in each novel a tension between its apparent, explicit ideological commitments and the emergent ideologies, especially of modern subjectivity and its attendant mechanisms of social control, to which the texts unknowingly contribute. Chapter 9 reveals a similar tension in Choderlos de Laclos s Les liaisons dangereuses between an increasingly archaic use of love as a means of acquiring social status and a new ideal of romantic love, though here this tension is the organizing principle around which the novel s whole plot circulates, and not, as in the other novels, an accident of historical myopia. 154

This brief, necessarily fragmentary summary perhaps indicates the chief difficulty that Ends of Enlightenment presents to its readers. On the one hand, almost all the essays are thoughtful, provocative, and worth reading, separately or together; on the other hand, and because they were never meant to form a unified work, their reproduction here introduces new problems, questions, tensions, and occasional confusions. While elaborating his operative notion of contemporaneity, Bender writes that Enlightenment repeated itself in the twentieth century and is doing so still today, but with the differences inevitably present in return and with the productive dissonance that belated repetition entails (4). Ends of Enlightenment, too, is a differential repetition at times belated, at times dissonant, but ultimately productive. Even the title announces a plurality of possible conclusions, objectives, or limits to the idea and reality of Enlightenment. Throughout, the book demands that we contend with the ambiguities and inconsistencies that a skeptical historicism means to uncover, though not to resolve. Nathan Gorelick Utah Valley University WORKS CITED Bender, John. Imagining the Penitentiary: Fiction and the Architecture of Mind in Eighteenth-Century England. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 1987. Print. Cohn, Dorrit. Transparent Minds: Narrative Modes for Representing Consciousness in Fiction. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1978. Print. Gallagher, Catherine. The Rise of Fictionality. The Novel. 2 vols. Ed. Franco Moretti. Princeton: Princeton UP, 2006. 1:336 63. Print. Habermas, Jürgen. The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere. 1962. Trans. Thomas Burger. Cambridge: Polity P, 1989. Print. Shapin, Steven, and Simon Schaffer. Leviathan and the Air-Pump: Hobbes, Boyle, and the Experimental Life. Princeton: Princeton UP, 1985. Print. Siskin, Clifford, and William Warner, ed. This is Enlightenment. Chicago: U of Chicago P, 2010. Print. Watt, Ian. The Rise of the Novel: Studies in Defoe, Richardson and Fielding. London: Chatto and Windus, 1957. Print. 155