Vagueness & Pragmatics

Similar documents
MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

For every sentences A and B, there is a sentence: A B,

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Scientific Philosophy

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

On Recanati s Mental Files

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Pragmatics - The Contribution of Context to Meaning

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

LOGICO-SEMANTIC ASPECTS OF TRUTHFULNESS

Types of perceptual content

Meaning 1. Semantics is concerned with the literal meaning of sentences of a language.

Symbolization and Truth-Functional Connectives in SL

Irony and the Standard Pragmatic Model

Non-Reducibility with Knowledge wh: Experimental Investigations

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

Verbal Ironv and Situational Ironv: Why do people use verbal irony?

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

A critical pragmatic approach to irony

Semantic Research Methodology

The ambiguity of definite descriptions

Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION. language such as in a play or a film. Meanwhile the written dialogue is a dialogue

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

RELATIVISM ABOUT TRUTH AND PERSPECTIVE-NEUTRAL PROPOSITIONS

Two-Dimensional Semantics the Basics

Pleasure, Pain, and Calm: A Puzzling Argument at Republic 583e1-8

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Part I: Graph Coloring

All Roads Lead to Violations of Countable Additivity

Review Jean Mark Gawron SDSU. March 14, Translation basics (you shouldnt get these things wrong):

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

How to Count Oranges

4 DETERMINERS AND PRONOUNS

Depictive Structure? I. Introduction

A Relevance-Theoretic Study of Poetic Metaphor. YANG Ting, LIU Feng-guang. Dalian University of Foreign Languages, Dalian, China

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: B. C. 3.

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Vowel sets: a reply to Kaye 1

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

A picture of the grammar. Sense and Reference. A picture of the grammar. A revised picture. Foundations of Semantics LING 130 James Pustejovsky

Rhetorical Questions and Scales

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

The Philosophy of Language. Grice s Theory of Meaning

winter but it rained often during the summer

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International Advanced Subsidiary and Advanced Level. Published

Introduction to Probability Exercises

Personal Narrative STUDENT SELF-ASSESSMENT

IF MONTY HALL FALLS OR CRAWLS

KEEP THIS STUDY GUIDE FOR ALL OF UNIT 4.

1. Introduction. Truth is a pretense. This bald statement might inspire incredulous stares, but my aim here is to deflect

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

Re-appraising the role of alternations in construction grammar: the case of the conative construction

TRANSLATIONS IN SENTENTIAL LOGIC

Characterizing quotation

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

MIRA COSTA HIGH SCHOOL English Department Writing Manual TABLE OF CONTENTS. 1. Prewriting Introductions 4. 3.

Ling 720 Implicit Arguments, Week 11 Barbara H. Partee, Nov 25, 2009

6.034 Notes: Section 4.1

How to write a scientific paper for an international journal

OKLAHOMA SUBJECT AREA TESTS (OSAT )

1. PSEUDO-IMPERATIVES IN ENGLISH Characterization.

Jokes and the Linguistic Mind. Debra Aarons. New York, New York: Routledge Pp. xi +272.

LESSON TWELVE VAGUITY AND AMBIGUITY

Lauderdale County School District Pacing Guide Sixth Grade Language Arts / Reading First Nine Weeks

Automatic Analysis of Musical Lyrics

AP LANGUAGE & COMPOSITION SUMMER ASSIGNMENT

Background to Gottlob Frege

AP English Literature and Composition 2010 Scoring Guidelines

Replies to the Critics

Self-reference. Sereny's presentation in "Godel, Tarski, Church, and the Liar,"' although the main idea is

Grammar is a way of thinking about language. Grammar is a way of thinking about language.

Longman Academic Writing Series 4

Picking out Irony in Robert Frost s. After Apple Picking

Disquotation, Conditionals, and the Liar 1

Subjective attitudes and counterstance contingency *

English III Honors 2018 Summer Assignment

Charles Ball, "the Georgian Slave"

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Grade 3 ELA Unit 2 Pretest (Teacher Edition) Assessment ID: dna ib Root Beer

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Possible Ramifications for Superiority

1 Introduction. Radim Belohlavek and George J. Klir

Transcription:

Vagueness & Pragmatics Min Fang & Martin Köberl SEMNL April 27, 2012 Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 1 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Why are true sentences not assertable? 1 Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Why are true sentences not assertable? Truth and assertability of sentences A first idea to compute assertability Flaws in the theory so far Refining the theory The power of the theory 2 P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack Closeness to Truth Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Comparison to Alternatives Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 2 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Why are true sentences not assertable? Logical equivalent sentences need not be equiassertable It may be the case that (1) is not assertable but that (2) is, although they seem to be logically equivalent: (1) Louis is bald or Louis is not bald. (2) It is not the case that Louis is bald and that he is not bald. We want to find a pragmatic explanation why this is the case. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 3 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Why are true sentences not assertable? What possibilities do we have to resolve the problems? Semantics: Logical equivalent sentences are not equiassertable. So we would have to leave classical logic. Keep classical logic und work on pragmatic side: (3) Katie had several drinks and drove home. is assertable if: Katie had several alcoholic drinks and drove home shortly afterwards. The need for a pragmatic explanation of assertability There may be situations in which a sentence is true without being assertable. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 4 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Truth and assertability of sentences A notion of different contents of a sentence (4) Katie had several drinks and drove home. Assertable iff sentence and implicatures are true and speakers believes in truth. The content of a sentence For a sentence S we define its semantic content T (S) as the set of all situations in which S is true objective pragmatic content O(S) as the set of all situations in which S is assertable subjective pragmatic content A(S, x) as the set of all situations in which x is convinced that everything needed for S to be assertable is true Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 5 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Truth and assertability of sentences How the objective pragmatic content is not computed Grice suggested: the objective pragmatic content is the set of all situations where the sentence is true and all implicatures are satisfied. This implies that O(S) is always a subset of T (S) for any sentence S. (5) If Katie had several drinks and drove home, then she broke the law. Sentence (5) is always assertable Sentence (5) is false if Katie drove home first, drank at home and did not break the law in any way Hence T (5) is a subset of O(5), which is just the other way round as Grice wanted it to be. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 6 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness A first idea to compute assertability How the objective pragmatic content is computed The former observations suggest that the objective pragmatic content of a sentence is tied more closely to the objective pragmatic content of its components than to its semantic content: COP: Compositionality of Objective Pragmatic Content The objective pragmatic content of a compound sentence is a function of the objective pragmatic contents of its constituents, with the function given by the operator or connective used to form the compound. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 7 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness A first idea to compute assertability Application to vague predicates The objective pragmatic content tells us when we can assert sentences. When we want to assert a sentence like a is F where F is a vague predicate, a has to be determinately F. The objective pragmatic content and coincide for the supervaluationistic theory. (6) Louis is bald or he is not bald. (Louis is bald) or (Louis is not bald) (7) It is not the case that Louis is bald and that he is not bald. It is not the case that (Louis is bald) and that (Louis is not bald) Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 8 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness A first idea to compute assertability Does this also work for the subjective pragmatic content? (8) Either X will be the next prime minister or Y will be the next prime minister. If we use a similar hypothesis as COP for the subjective pragmatic content, a person can assert (8) only if she also would assert to one of its two disjuncts. But we clearly do not want this. So a similar ansatz cannot work in this case. Note however that this does not say anything negative about COP. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 9 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness A first idea to compute assertability Application of COP to Quantifiers Application of COP to (9) Q F s are Gs [Qx : Fx]Gx delivers: (10) [Qx : Fx]( Gx) Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 10 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness A first idea to compute assertability Does this explain Sorites Paradox? Let P(n) mean a man with exactly n cent is poor and N(n) that n is a natural number. Suppose that P(0) is true. Since the induction step [ n N(n)](P(n) P(n + 1)) is false, its negation [ n N(n)](P(n) P(n + 1)) has to be true. But is it also assertable? (Let us abbreviate P(n) P(n + 1) by B(n)) (11) [ n N(n)] B(n) is false, but its negation (12) ([ n N(n)]( B(n))) is true, hence we can assert No number is the poor borderline. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 11 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Flaws in the theory so far Does COP get everything right? We may assent to disjunctions although none of its disjuncts is determinately true: (13) That is red or orange. We may assent to contradictions (if Louis is a penumbral case of baldness): (14) It is not the case that Louis is bald, but nor is it the case that he is not bald. Our current version of COP is not able to explain this. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 12 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Refining the theory A first change to COP We need to do some alterations to COP to adjust it to the application to vague predicates: POP V : Pragmatic determination of Objective Pragmatic content Let S be a sentence that has no differences between its semantic and objective pragmatic contents other than those caused by vagueness. Then there is a sentence S generated by adding operators to S so that every term in it apart from sentential connectives is inside the scope of a operator and O(S) = T (S ). Which such sentence S satisfies this condition on an occasion where S is used is determined by pragmatic features of utterance and occasion. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 13 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Refining the theory Explaining the data Suppose Louis is a borderline case of baldness. Louis is bald or Louis is not bald. (Louis is bald or Louis is not bald) (Louis is bald) or (Louis is not bald) It is not the case that Louis is bald and that he is not bald. (It is not the case that Louis is bald and that he is not bald) It is not the case that (Louis is bald and he is not bald) It is not the case that (Louis is bald) and that (he is not bald) Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 14 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Refining the theory Explaining the data (11) It is not the case that Louis is bald, but nor is it the case that he is not bald. may have (according to POP) one of the following as its objective pragmatic content: Bl Bl Bl Bl Bl Bl ( Bl Bl) If the context chooses the first interpretation, the sentence is assertable. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 15 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Refining the theory The final theory We need a theory as general as COP but keeping advantages of POP V : POP: Pragmatic Determination of Objective Pragmatic Content The objective pragmatic content of a compound sentence is a function of the objective pragmatic contents of its sub-sentences that are treated as simple, with the function given by the operator or connective used to form the compound. The choice of which sub-sentences are treated as simple is determined by the syntactic features of the sentence and the context. The objective pragmatic content of sentences treated as simple is determined by a direct application of broadly Gricean rules. For a simple sentence to be assertable we want it following Gricean maxims to be determinately true. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 16 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Refining the theory Explaining the theory The choice of which sub-sentences are treated as simple is determined by the syntactic features of the sentence [... ]. (15) If Katie had several drinks and she drove home, then she broke the law. (16) If, last night, Katie had several drinks and she drove home, then she broke the law. (17) If Katie had several drinks last night and she drove home last night, then she broke the law. In (16) the time reference is added to the conjunction as a whole, in (17) it is added to each of the conjuncts. They stop sharing an unuttered constituent, there is less temptation to treat the conjunction as a simple sentence. Now, its objective pragmatic content is just the conjunction of the objective pragmatic contents of its conjuncts, we lose the information about the temporal order of the events. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 17 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness The power of the theory Rivals to POP: Intuitionistic logic Intuitionistic Logic may explain why we accept the Law of Non-Contradiction It is not the case that Louis is bald and that he is not bald. and disject the Law of Excluded Middle Louis is bald or Louis is not bald. but it cannot explain why we assent to contradictions as It is not the case that Louis is bald, but nor is it the case that he is not bald. Note however that intuitionistic logic is combinable with POP. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 18 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness The power of the theory Rivals to POP: Many-valued logic Utterances are assertable if they have a high truth-value. may explain why instance of the Law of Excluded Middle may not be assertable. cannot explain why instances of the Law of Non-Contradiction are assertable. In fact: He is bald and he is not bald. may have a truth-value of 0.5. It is not the case that he is bald and he is not bald. then also only has a truth-value of 0.5 although being perfectly assertable. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 19 / 48

Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness The power of the theory Sorites revisited Different possibilites to state the induction step (in decreasing persuasive force). (18) It is not the case that P(n) and not P(n + 1). (19) If P(n) then P(n + 1). (20) Either it is not the case that P(n) or P(n + 1). POP tells us that (18) may be even assertable when n is a borderline case of poorness. But this does not hold for (20). It is hard to find any theory using classical logic accounting for these differences. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 20 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack 1 Weatherson: Pragmatics and Vagueness Why are true sentences not assertable? Truth and assertability of sentences A first idea to compute assertability Flaws in the theory so far Refining the theory The power of the theory 2 P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack Closeness to Truth Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Comparison to Alternatives Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 21 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack What do we mean by pragmatic slack? Consider the truth conditions of this sentence: John to Peter: Mary arrived at three o clock. People speak with varying degrees of precision. For most practical purposes, it suffices to be close enough to the truth. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 22 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack Examples - Exactly three o clock If (21) is literally true only if Mary arrived precisely at 3:00, then it seems truth-conditionally equivalent to (22). (21) Mary arrived at three o clock. (22) Mary arrived at exactly three o clock. But of course they do not mean the same thing. Suggestion (21) allows greater slack than (22) in determining just how close to the truth is close enough for practical purposes. Thus, particular words, such as exactly, seem to be able to influence the amount of slack associated with the sentence. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 23 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack Examples - All the townspeople I (23) The townspeople are asleep. It seems that (23) involves a near-universal quantification, so that this paraphrase seems plausible: (24) More-or-less all townspeople are asleep. But this assumption leads to a problem: (25) is contradictory while (26) is not. (25) Although the townspeople are asleep, some of them are awake. (26) Although more-or-less all townspeople are asleep, some of them are awake. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 24 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack Examples - All the townspeople II So maybe (23) is universally quantified after all? But then how can we account for the difference between (23) and (27)? (27) All townspeople are asleep. It seems that (23) allows exceptions (i.e. awake people) as is appropriate for the utterance context. Even though the sentence would then be literally false, it is still close enough to the truth to serve its purpose. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 25 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack (23) The townspeople are asleep. (27) All townspeople are asleep. Examples - All the townspeople III Suggestion (23) and (27) are truth-conditionally equivalent, they only differ in the deviation from the truth they permit the pragmatic situation to license (i.e. all allows less slack). Note: Just because the sentence allows pragmatic slack does not mean that every pragmatic situation will exploit the slack that the sentence makes available. Consider an experiment on sleeping behaviour where loose speaking is not appropriate: The subjects are asleep. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 26 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack Examples - Perfectly spherical I Scalar adjectives admit modification by degree adverbials such as very. But some adjectives do not allow such modification. (28) This ball is very round. (29)? This ball is very spherical. Very makes direct reference to the scale of the adjective, e.g. it may raise the cutoff point. So is spherical non-scalar? But then, are any objects really spherical? And how can we explain the intensifying effect in (30)? (30) This ball is perfectly spherical. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 27 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Slack Examples - Perfectly spherical II Suggestion Spherical is non-scalar, but we may use it with pragmatic slack to refer to not-truly-spherical objects if it is close enough to truth for practical purposes. Perfectly reduces the acceptable level of deviance from the truth allowed by the pragmatics. Slack regulators The amount of acceptable slack is both determined by the pragmatics of the utterance context and the appearance of particular words within the utterance (these are called slack regulators). Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 28 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Closeness to Truth Dimensions to closeness to truth little hope for a generic metric for the notion of closeness to truth therefore consider several dimensions of closeness How close does the sentence come to getting the time right? How close does it come to getting the shape of the ball right? different slack regulators make reference to different dimensions of closeness Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 29 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Closeness to Truth Pragmatically relevant details and distinctions Just how close is close enough? It is not the degree of closeness per se important, but whether pragmatically relevant details and distinctions are represented. Say we want to attack a town and wait for the townspeople to fall asleep. Three people are still awake. They might be vigilant guards on the lookout, or harmless insomniacs counting sheep. Thus, the number of awake townspeople matters less than the effect they may have on our attack. Close enough to the truth Let us suppose that close enough to the truth means close enough not to obscure pragmatically relevant details or distinctions. What is relevant? This part of the analysis is left vague. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 30 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Halos - General idea Each expression is assigned a denotation (with respect to a model). The pragmatic context associates this denotation with a set of objects of the same logical type as the denotation itself. Each object in this set differs from the denotation only in some pragmatically ignorable respect (the denotation itself is also included in the set). This set may be totally or partially ordered, such that the denotation forms a natural endpoint of the ordering. The relative position of the elements of a set according to such an ordering gives us a way of judging closeness to the truth. This set together with its ordering relation is called the pragmatic halo of an expression. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 31 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Halos Pragmatic Halos - Complex expressions the width of the halo of a complex expression partly depends on the appearance or absence of a slack regulator this suggests some kind of compositional procedure in halo assignment for complex expressions apply the normal semantic rules to all possible combinations of elements drawn from the halos of the immediate parts of a complex expression ordering in the constituent halos is preserved in the halo of the complex expression Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 32 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Semantics of Slack Regulation slack regulators readjust the pragmatic halo of the expression they combine with in our examples: tightening elimination of those elements ordered furtherest away from the core of the halo formed by the given expression preliminary assumptions about the semantics verbs and predicates have a hidden argument place for eventualities (i.e. events, states and processes) sentences denote set of eventualities rather than truth values a sentence is true if its denotation is non-empty Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 33 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Three o clock - Denotation Let at three o clock denote the set of eventualities that occur at time i (where i is the time denoted by three o clock). Let intransitive verbs denote relations between individuals and eventualities, so that arrive matches each individual x with events of x arriving. Mary arrived then denotes the set of Mary s arrivals (tense ignored). Mary arrived at three o clock then yields, by intersecting the denotation sets of its immediate parts, the set of Mary s arrivals which occur at three o clock. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 34 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Three o clock - Pragmatic Halo For illustration s purposes let s assume that the pragmatic halo of three o clock is the set {i, j, k}, ordered according to the ordering relation. Let us further assume that this is the only expression in the sentence with a non-trivial halo. The pragmatic halo, according to the principles set so far, would then contain the set of Mary s arrivals at i, the set of her arrivals at j, and the set of her arrivals at k, i.e. {{x x is an arrival by Mary at i}, {x x is an arrival of Mary at j}, {x x is an arrival of Mary at k}} Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 35 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Three o clock - Closeness to Truth Close enough to true A sentence is close enough to true for a context C iff its halo relative to C contains at least one non-empty element. Suppose Mary actually arrived at k. With the denotation given above, the sentence is false (its denotation is the empty set). But its halo (given above) relative to C is the following: {,, {e}} where e is the event of Mary s arrival. Thus, this set contains at least one non-empty element and the sentence is close enough to true for its context C. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 36 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Exactly three o clock - Pragmatic Halo The pragmatic halo of exactly three o clock should include those elements of the halo of three o clock which are closest to i, eliminating outlying elements. The intensity of the contraction of the halo depends on the given context. The denotation of exactly is an identity function on times, therefore the halo is a set of functions on times. Each of these should differ from the identity function only in pragmatically ignorable ways, i.e. functions that match a given time t onto a time differing from t in ignorable ways. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 37 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Exactly three o clock - Pragmatic Halo To calculate the halo of exactly T we apply the functions in the halo of exactly to the centerpoint of the halo of T, and then take the union of the resulting values. Note: We have to make sure that the halo really contracts (rather than expands). Thus, we should stipulate that the functions in the halo of exactly should map a given time t onto a subhalo of the halo of t. So the halo of exactly T should always be a subset of the halo of T. If a time y is in the halo of exactly T, so should every time between y and T, as well as T itself. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 38 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Exactly three o clock - Closeness to Truth Suppose that the halo of exactly three o clock contains i, j, but not k. Let us further assume (as before) that Mary only arrived once and that this was at k. The pragmatic halo of the whole sentence Mary arrived at exactly three o clock is then {, } = { }. Since this set does not have any non-empty members, the sentence is not close enough to true for our context - as opposed to Mary arrived at three o clock, despite using the same denotations and halos. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 39 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation All the townspeople - Denotation Let us assume that both the noun phrases the townspeople and all the townspeople denote the set of townspeople collectively. It will serve as an argument to the predicate are asleep. We will also assume that predicates can take sets of eventualities as arguments, and stipulate that a set of individuals X will stand in the sleep relation to a set of eventualities Y iff every member of X stands in the sleep relation to a member of Y, and vice versa. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 40 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation All the townspeople - Pragmatic Halo The halo of the townspeople should be a set of sets of individuals which differ from the set of the townspeople only in pragmatically ignorable ways, ordered according to closeness to the actual set of townspeople (we may use the subset relation for determining closeness). We will treat all to denote the identity function (like exactly). Its halo therefore should be a set of functions that approximate the identity function. We derive the halo of all the N by gathering the results of those functions applied to the denotation of the N into a set. As before, we will stipulate that every set in the halo of all the N is also in the halo of the N. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 41 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation All the townspeople - Closeness to Truth (23) The townspeople are asleep. (27) All townspeople are asleep. There are contexts in which (23) is close enough to true while (27) is not, even though they are truth-conditionally equivalent. Note that in this theory, we explicitly allow contradictory sentences to function pragmatically as though they were true. (25) Although the townspeople are asleep, some of them are awake. However, (25) is not only contradictory, it is also quite odd pragmatically. The first clause will never be close enough to true for its context if the context is one in which the second clause is assertable. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 42 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Perfectly spherical We need semantics for perfectly that manipulate scales for those predicates that provide them (e.g. scalar adjectives), in addition to manipulating pragmatic halos. Let us suppose that scalar adjectives such as round denote different sets of individuals depending on the context. If the denotation of round relative to a context C 1 is a subset of its denotation in C 2, we say that C 1 is stricter than C 2. The truth-conditional contribution of perfectly involves an implicit quantification over contexts: An object is perfectly round iff it falls into the denotation of round in all contexts (even in the strictest). Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 43 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Semantics of Slack Regulation Perfectly spherical - Pragmatic Halo Spherical denotes the set of perfect spheres. Its halo, thus, should be a set of sets that differ from the set of perfect spheres in pragmatically ignorable ways (e.g. by containing not-perfectly-spherical objects). A partial ordering is imposed on this halo. Let the halo of perfectly be a set of functions approximating its denotation, i.e., each function maps a given set X onto a set that differs from what the denotation of perfectly maps X onto only in pragmatically ignorable ways. The halo of perfectly spherical is derived by gathering the the values given by these functions when applied to the endpoint of the halo of spherical into a set. Any set in the halo of perfectly spherical is also in the halo of spherical. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 44 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Comparison to Alternatives Alternatives - Standards of truth We may try to relativise truth to standards of precision. The townspeople are asleep is true relative to one standard of precision even if there are three people awake, but false relative to a stricter standard. The utterance situation determines which standard of precision is in force. Slack regulators then help determine the truth value relative to a given standard. (23) The townspeople are asleep. (27) All townspeople are asleep. (27) is true relative to a given standard s iff (23) is true relative to every standard s. Therefore, (23) and (27) are no longer logically equivalent. Thus, slack regulators now have a truth-conditional effect. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 45 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Comparison to Alternatives Its side effects (31) Absolutely all the townspeople are asleep. Absolutely appears to be a slack regulator here. Do we really want to claim that it is truth-conditionally distinct from (27)? Furthermore, this approach does not solve one of our original problems: How do we explain that (25) is contradictory? (25) Although the townspeople are asleep, some of them are awake. We have to distinguish between authentic semantic vagueness and mere pragmatic looseness of speech. In the former, the extensions of predicates do not have well-defined borders, whereas in the latter they do. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 46 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Comparison to Alternatives Alternatives - Supervaluational approach If John is a borderline case of baldness, then a sentence like John is bald is analysed as not having a determinate truth value. A sentence is simply true if it is true relative to all ways of drawing the border (precisification). Lewis: Even though a sentence may not evaluate to true in all precisifications we may still want to consider it as if it is simply true, provided it is true for enough precisifications. Exactly how many ways of drawing the border count as enough varies according to the context and depends on the standard of precision in force. It may also be manipulated with slack regulators. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 47 / 48

P. Lasersohn: Pragmatic Halos Comparison to Alternatives Objection against it Lewis s system allows for contextual variation in whether a sentence is true enough only when the sentence is truth-conditionally vague, i.e. when the sentence receives an indeterminate truth value. Sentences which are simply false will never be true enough. We cannot capture the intuition that Mary arrived at three o clock can be false while it can still be pragmatically treated as though it were true. For Lewis, this kind of contextual variation only occurs because of undefined border area in the extension of a predicate, not because we ignore certain kinds of pragmatically irrelevant falsehood. Min Fang & Martin Köberl (SEMNL) Vagueness & Pragmatics April 27, 2012 48 / 48