Educating for Virtuoso Living: Papers from the Ninth East-West Philosophers' Conference

Similar documents
Zhu Xi's Reading of the Analects: Canon, Commentary, and the Classical Tradition (review)

Valuable Particulars

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF. the oxford handbook of WORLD PHILOSOPHY. GARFIELD-Halftitle2-Page Proof 1 August 10, :24 PM

CCCC 2006, Chicago Confucian Rhetoric 1

Theories of Truth in Chinese Philosophy: A Comparative Approach by Alexus McLeod (review)

Humanities Learning Outcomes

SINGAPORE MANAGEMENT UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES PHIL207 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL CHINESE PHILOSOPHY

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

Trying Not to Try: The Art and Science of Spontaneity by Edward Slingerland (review)

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

On The Search for a Perfect Language

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Inter-subjective Judgment

Moral Judgment and Emotions

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

English/Philosophy Department ENG/PHL 100 Level Course Descriptions and Learning Outcomes

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Aesthetics and Cognition in Kant s Critical Philosophy

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Objects and Things: Notes on Meta- pseudo- code (Lecture at SMU, Dec, 2012)

observation and conceptual interpretation

WINONA STATE UNIVERSITY PROPOSAL FOR GENERAL EDUCATION PROGRAM COURSES

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

The Theory and Practice of Virtue Education Edited by Tom Harrison and David I. Walker *

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Assistant Professor in Philosophy, Cornell University (reappointed in 1969 to second 3-year term, resigned in 1970).

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Two Roads to Wisdom? Chinese and Analytic Philosophical Traditions, edited by Bo Mou (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 2001; pp. xvii, 381).

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Narrative Case Study Research

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Tradition and the Individual Poem: An Inquiry into Anthologies (review)

Review of Li, The Confucian Philosophy of Harmony

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Wendy Bishop, David Starkey. Published by Utah State University Press. For additional information about this book

Philosophy? BRANCHES OF PHILOSOPHY. Philosophy? Branches of Philosophy. Branches of Philosophy. Branches of Philosophy 1/18/2013

NORCO COLLEGE SLO to PLO MATRIX

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

China 300.1x. Chinese Thought: Ancient Wisdom Meets Modern Science Part 1: Introduction and Early Warring States (5 th -4 th c.

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Copyright Nikolaos Bogiatzis 1. Athenaeum Fragment 116. Romantic poetry is a progressive, universal poetry. Its aim isn t merely to reunite all the

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

6AANB021 Kant s Moral Philosophy 2014/15

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Pluralism in Practice

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

4 Embodied Phenomenology and Narratives

Practical Action First Critique Foundations *

Determinism and the Problem of Individual Freedom in Li Zehou s Thought

ENGL S092 Improving Writing Skills ENGL S110 Introduction to College Writing ENGL S111 Methods of Written Communication

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Translation's Forgotten History: Russian Literature, Japanese Mediation, and the Formation of Modern Korean Literature by Heekyoung Cho (review)

S/A 4074: Ritual and Ceremony. Lecture 14: Culture, Symbolic Systems, and Action 1

Face-threatening Acts: A Dynamic Perspective

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Categories and Schemata

Religion 101 Ancient Egyptian Religion Fall 2009 Monday 7:00-9:30 p.m.

On Interpretation and Translation

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Aesthetics is the Grammar of Desire

Arakawa and Gins: The Organism-Person-Environment Process

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

By Maximus Monaheng Sefotho (PhD). 16 th June, 2015

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

Moral Education of Children: Moral Act as Artistic Activity

Special Issue Introduction: Coming to Terms in the Muddy Waters of Qualitative Inquiry in Communication Studies

The Task of the Inheritor: A Review of Gerhard Richter s Inheriting Walter Benjamin

William J. Devlin and Shai Biderman (eds.), The Philosophy of David Lynch, Lexington: The University Press of Kentucky, 2011, 248 pp.

DAVID W. JOHNSON CURRICULUM VITÆ

Wittgenstein as a Philosopher of Technology: Tool Use, Forms of Life, Technique, and a Transcendental Argument

The Doctrine of the Mean

Vinod Lakshmipathy Phil 591- Hermeneutics Prof. Theodore Kisiel

Master List of Approved Courses for Philosophy and Values Effective Spring 2017_v6

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

II. Aristotle or Nietzsche? III. MacIntyre s History, In Brief. IV. MacIntyre s Three-Stage Account of Virtue

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Code : is a set of practices familiar to users of the medium

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

The Hong Kong Polytechnic University. Subject Description Form

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

The Self as an Object of Criticism: Richard Rorty s Denial of the Objectivity of Truth. Do Kien Trung, Kobe University, Japan

Block C1. (re) Arts Comparative and transnational studies of Asian and Asian American cultures with a focus on literature, film, and visual arts.

Philosophy East and West, Volume 65, Number 3, July 2015, pp (Review) DOI: /pew

days of Saussure. For the most, it seems, Saussure has rightly sunk into

Transcription:

Educating for Virtuoso Living: Papers from the Ninth East-West Philosophers' Conference Jay L. Garfield Philosophy East and West, Volume 57, Number 3, July 2007, pp. 285-289 (Article) Published by University of Hawai'i Press DOI: https://doi.org/10.1353/pew.2007.0030 For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/217392 No institutional affiliation (20 Nov 2018 20:15 GMT)

EDUCATING FOR VIRTUOSO LIVING: PAPERS FROM THE NINTH EAST-WEST PHILOSOPHERS CONFERENCE Jay Garfield Department of Philosophy, Smith College, and Central Institute of Higher Tibetan Studies, University of Melbourne Introduction The present issue of Philosophy East and West presents a selection of papers from the Ninth East-West Philosophers Conference held at the East-West Center in Honolulu in 2005. The theme of the conference was education, and given the large number of fine papers presented, the selection for this issue was no easy task. The papers we present here address a common topic the nature of moral education and the role of aesthetic experience in moral education and moral practice though from very different perspectives, and it is because of this variety of approaches to this topic that we present the group of essays gathered in this volume. The link between ethics and aesthetics has been explored extensively in Chinese moral theory. We see this connection exploited in the Daodejing and developed systematically in the Confucian tradition, as Professors Olberding and Thompson each emphasize in their contributions to this issue. This connection has also been remarked upon in the Western tradition. Kant s critical philosophy introduces this line of thought, and it is developed systematically by Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein. Schopenhauer argues that ethical and aesthetic experience has its roots in an immediate intuition of the world as it is in itself and reflects the deepest form of knowledge of reality. Nietzsche suggests that ethical reflection, if it is to be properly humanistic, can only be understood as a kind of aesthetic criticism of biography. Wittgenstein, developing Schopenhauer s views in the Tractatus, argues that ethics and aesthetics are one and the same. This idea is developed further in his Lecture on Ethics, in which ethical experience, the experience par excellence, is characterized in terms of aesthetic wonder at the existence and beauty of the world, before being meta-characterized as ineffable. The line of thought we see developed by Kant, Schopenhauer, and Wittgenstein focuses primarily on the transcendental dimension of values, and on the fact that when we engage in moral or aesthetic reflection, either in deliberation or in assessment, we address ourselves directly to values that cannot be reduced to, and which transcend, empirical description. In such reflection, according to this view, we encounter ourselves and the world in a noumenal rather than a phenomenal aspect. Nietzsche, of course, stands outside this consensus in his rejection of transcendental ontology and of transcendental values. While he shares with Schopenhauer and Wittgenstein the view that aesthetic and ethical engagement is the deepest and most primordial form of human engagement with the world and with ourselves as Philosophy East & West Volume 57, Number 3 July 2007 285 289 > 2007 by University of Hawai i Press 285

subjects and agents, he emphasizes not its transcendent nature, but its immanence, and the fact that in aesthetic and ethical life we are engaged directly and perceptually with the particular and with the concrete. This Nietzschean line of thought is taken up in ethics in the West by contemporary moral particularists (Dancy 2004, Baier 1985, 1994, Garfield 2000), who emphasize that our moral knowledge is acquired by reflective consideration of the appropriate affective and behavioral responses to particular episiodes, individuals, or situations, and that moral generalizations are never exceptionless, at best encoding post hoc summaries of moral knowledge that is always embedded and always epistemically and motivationally prior to the generalizations we might employ as descriptive shorthands. It is taken up in a different way by aesthetic mulitplists (Krausz 1993, 2000), who argue that the interpretation of a work of art or the proper performance of a piece of music is not a matter that can be codified, but that multiple interpretations or performances have equally good claim to be correct, with educated aesthetic judgment, as opposed to a set of rules, required for criticism. These strains in recent Western philosophy have led many to the view of moral education as a process not of teaching golden rules, moral theories, or game theory, but rather as the cultivation of a particular kind of moral character (Baier 1994, Sprod 2001). The character to be cultivated, according to this view, is not simply a set of virtues, understood as dispositions to act in particular ways, but also skills in moral perception, and affective sets. Moral cultivation is seen from this perspective to be a cultivation, inter alia, of a kind of aesthetic response to interpersonal situations, and of a virtuoso, not merely a virtuous, skill in navigating moral situations. All of this is rather new in Western moral thought. But, as the present set of essays make clear, it is a line of thought not at all new in world philosophical history, and hardly particular to the West. For this reason, contemporary Western ethical and aesthetic theory may have a good deal to learn from Asian and African moral and aesthetic thought. Each of these essays makes this point. Amy Olberding, in The Educative Function of Personal Style in the Analects, emphasizes that Confucian moral education, like musical education and inspired by the model of education in the arts, aims at the cultivation of a moral and social expert, and one with a distinctive personal style. A good piano teacher, Olberding points out, comes to her own craft with a style and functions for her student in part as a model. A good student ends up with a style, one that will reflect in some ways the style of her teacher, but which, if she is really good, will be her own. Her virtuosity will consist neither in her adherence to a set of performance rules she has learned from her teacher, nor in a replication of her teacher s style, but in her ability, in her own distinctive way, to respond appropriately and creatively to the music she performs in the situations in which she performs it. And this is how the Confucian imagines that moral education goes for human beings. The moral and interpersonal styles of our moral educators are not incidental to moral upbringing. They function as important exemplars, not to be replicated, but to be used in the cultivation of our own styles, and our own moral and aesthetic standards. This 286 Philosophy East & West

allows for a range of creative human moral and aesthetic responses, but ones appropriately constrained by conventions, traditions, and the demands of morality. Kirill Thompson, in The Archery of Wisdom in the Stream of Life: Wisdom in the Four Books with Zhu Xi s Reflections, develops this general perspective with more specificity and with attention to the development of this framework by Zhu Xi. Most importantly, Thompson emphasizes that Zhu Xi interprets wisdom as comprising a number of skills, including preeminently those of hitting the mark, appropriateness, discretion, and the utmost propriety in a common situation. As Thompson puts it, Zhu saw the purpose of moral education as less to achieve a purely rational grasp of higher, abstract forms than to cultivate a nuanced, holistic, responsive sensitivity to the immanental patterns of change and transformation.... These patterns were for Zhu always to be experienced embodimentally and responded to situationally. We hence see in this articulation of Confucian moral theory a concern for the development of a creative, virtuoso ability to see what is necessary in the particular situation, and to respond appropriately to the particular demands of each situation. In this model, ethical and aesthetic cultivation are intimately related, and are irreducibly particularist in character. Chenyang Li s Li as Cultural Grammar: On the Relation between Li and Ren in Confucius Analects might at first appear to be a counterpoint to these readings of Confucian moral theory and of the purpose and nature of Confucian moral education. Using a Chomskyan metaphor of linguistic mastery, Li reads li as cultural grammar, and ren as cultural mastery. On this account, the final goal of Confucian moral education is ren, cultural mastery, but the means of the attainment of ren is the mastery of li, which is the proximal goal of moral education. One might think, because of the emphasis in li on ritual and propriety and because of the fact that grammars are encoded in sets of rules, that Li s position is inconsistent in spirit with those of Olberding and Thompson. Not so. While it represents a different perspective on the kind of aesthetic, virtuoso particularism they advance, there is deep agreement on the structure of moral knowledge and moral education. We can see this affinity if we attend more carefully to the role that natural language grammars play in our linguistic lives and if we attend to the nature of real linguistic mastery. While grammars may be represented by linguists as sets of rules, and while it may be that at some level they are represented in our minds as set of rules, nobody has ever learned a grammar by learning a set of rules, and nobody knows how to articulate any such set of rules. We learn the grammar of our natural languages by being socialized into them, and we do this on the basis of our experience of examples of correct performance, coupled with innate but inarticulable abilities to extrapolate from these examples. The role of exemplars and of our human ability to respond appropriately to examples is essential. Indeed, mastery of grammar is necessary for the mastery of language. But mastery of language cannot amount simply to the regular production of grammatically correct sentences and the failure to produce ungrammatical sentences. That makes it both too easy and too hard. To master language is to say appropriate and interesting things, and no grammar can specify what these are. This kind of mastery is Jay Garfield 287

enabled both by grammatical mastery and growing into the more complex skills encoded by pragmatics and a mastery of the human condition. These in turn, as Li notes, are taught through language, and so require, but are not exhausted by, grammatical mastery. Moreover, linguistic mastery requires that one occasionally, sometimes self-conciously, violate the rules of grammar. Much conversation, rhetoric, and poetry requires just such devices, and the failure to master them is a failure to attain linguistic mastery. So, according to Li s account as well, a properly Confucian understanding of moral cultivation is the cultivation of a kind of virtuosity that requires exquisite sensitivity to the characteristics of particular situations. These three essays just mentioned all address aspects of Confucian moral theory. Two others in this issue take us into new cultural territory, and indeed into territory not often explored in the pages of this journal. Douglas Allen s Mahatma Gandhi on Violence and Peace Education explores the nature of violence and of nonviolence, the location of violence and nonviolence in education itself, and the special role of education in the promotion of nonviolence as a human virtue and as a social fact. One might expect, given Gandhi s own emphasis on the reality of an absolute truth, and on the importance of insistance on that truth (satyagraha) that a Gandhian account of education and moral development would be far from the aestheticized, particularist account that we encountered in the Confucian contributions to this issue. Indeed, there are marked, and important, differences between the Gandhian and Confucian view of moral education and of morality, and these will be apparent to even the most casual reader. But Allen emphasizes that there is another dimension to Gandhi s vision of nonviolence and of nonviolent education, and it is here that this program makes real contact with the Confucian program. Allen writes, Recognizing the specificity and complexity of our contextualized situatedness, we recognize that peace education allows us to grasp relative, partial truths. Our approach should be tolerant and open to other points of view; others have different relative perspectives and different glimpses of truth that we do not have. Even if the truth the insistance on which is the goal of Gandhian education is absolute, the moral sensitivity and understanding of human situations that must be cultivated by actual teachers in actual students will be a kind of perception and attunement that can only be understood as a set of situationally grounded skills. Philosophy East and West has oriented itself traditionally on a very East-West axis, attending principally to the philosophical traditions of Europe and its colonies in North America and Australia on the one hand and those of Asia on the other. Africa has not often been apparent in this journal, and the philosophy and intellectual traditions of Africa and its diaspora have attracted little attention here. Albert Mosley s The Moral Significance of the Music of the Black Atlantic begins to redress this omission. Mosley emphasizes to a greater degree than any of the other contributors to this discussion the explicit connection between aesthetics and ethics, and between performance and appreciation on the one hand and ethical conduct and assessment on the other. His discussion of the importance of improvisation and of the interaction between performer and audience in African and African-American music to the development of moral vision and sensibility demonstrates that the con- 288 Philosophy East & West

nection between aesthetics and morality need not be merely tacit in high discourse, or the stuff of academic metaphysics. This connection is indeed explicit and central in these cultures and indicates once more the importance of broad philosophical vision that encompasses the philosophical perspectives of all of the world s cultures. Philosophy East and West presents these essays to our readers as a sample of the offerings of what was a marvelously diverse and intellectually rich conference. This thread of argument is but one in an extraordinary tapestry. More will be available when a volume of selected essays from the conference emerges. Notes 1 I thank Ms. Nikoleta Papadopoulos for assistance in preparing this volume and Nalini Bhushan for comments on this introduction. References Baier, A. 1985. Postures of the Mind: Essays on Mind and Morals. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.. 1994. Moral Prejudices: Essays on Ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Dancy, J. 2004. Ethics Without Principles. New York: Oxford University Press. Garfield, J. 2000. Particularity and Principle: The Structure of Moral Knowledge, in B. Hooker and M. Little, eds., Moral Particularism. New York: Oxford University Press. Krausz, M. 1993. Rightness and Reasons. Ithaca: Cornell Univeristy Press.. 2000. Limits of Rightness. Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield. Sprod, T. 2001. Philosophical Discussion in Moral Education: The Community of Moral Inquiry. New York: Routledge. Jay Garfield 289