Review of Li, The Confucian Philosophy of Harmony

Similar documents
On Interpretation and Translation

Zhu Xi's Reading of the Analects: Canon, Commentary, and the Classical Tradition (review)

CCCC 2006, Chicago Confucian Rhetoric 1

SINGAPORE MANAGEMENT UNIVERSITY SCHOOL OF SOCIAL SCIENCES PHIL207 INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL CHINESE PHILOSOPHY

Response to Seth D. Clippard, "Zhu Xi and the Instrumental Value of Nature"

Harmony from Confucian, Greek, Liberal, and Global Perspectives

Two Roads to Wisdom? Chinese and Analytic Philosophical Traditions, edited by Bo Mou (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 2001; pp. xvii, 381).

Tamar Sovran Scientific work 1. The study of meaning My work focuses on the study of meaning and meaning relations. I am interested in the duality of

Module A: Chinese Language Studies. Course Description

Mary Evelyn Tucker. In our search for more comprehensive and global ethics to meet the critical challenges of our

Yinyang and Dao. Yi Jing (I Ching) Taiji (Taichi) Yinyang

Chinese Intellectual History

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Review of: Ancient Middle Niger: Urbanism and the Self-Organizing Landscape, by Roderick J. McIntosh

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Yanming An Ph.D. Professor of Chinese and Philosophy Clemson University Clemson, SC (864) (O) August 20, 2015

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Kent Academic Repository

CHIN 385 Advanced Chinese Cultural Communication

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

The Philosophy of Harmony in Classical Confucianism

Humanities Learning Outcomes

On Harmony as Transformation: Paradigms from the / Ching

Writing an Honors Preface

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Ontological Categories. Roberto Poli

Trying Not to Try: The Art and Science of Spontaneity by Edward Slingerland (review)

In order to enrich our experience of great works of philosophy and literature we will include, whenever feasible, speakers, films and music.

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

UNIVERSITY OF CALIFORNIA PRESS ADVERTISING RATES & INFORMATION

Searching for the Way. Theory of Knowledge in Pre-modern and Modern China. Hong Kong: The Chinese University Press, Pp. xvi U.S. $52.00.

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Topic Page: Yin-yang. Hist ory. Basic Philosophy.

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Military Tradition in. Imperial China

Two Panel Proposals on Chinese Aesthetics

International School of Kenya Creative Arts High School Theatre Arts (Drama)

Theories of Truth in Chinese Philosophy: A Comparative Approach by Alexus McLeod (review)

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Far Eastern History I. Instructor: Daniel Asen Office hours: Wednesday 11:40am - 12:40pm, and by appointment, Conklin Hall 328

Aristotle on the Human Good

Review of Carolyn Korsmeyer, Savoring Disgust: The foul and the fair. in aesthetics (Oxford University Press pp (PBK).

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Educating for Virtuoso Living: Papers from the Ninth East-West Philosophers' Conference

CONFUCIANISM IS A LIVING tradition that contributes to contemporary


Myth and Philosophy in Plato s Phaedrus

SYLLABUSES FOR THE DEGREE OF MASTER OF ARTS

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

T.M. Porter, The Rise of Statistical Thinking, Princeton: Princeton University Press, xii pp

Non-Western Art History

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Visions Magazine General Submission Guidelines

DONG ZHONGSHU. Major Ideas

ENGLISH LANGUAGE AND LITERATURE (EMC)

Chapter 3 The Asian Contribution

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

The Question of Equilibrium in Human Action and the Everyday Paradox of Rationality

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Tentative Schedule (last UPDATE: February 8, 2005 ) Number Date Topic Reading Information Oral General Presentations Assignments

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Analysis of the Instrumental Function of Beauty in Wang Zhaowen s Beauty- Goodness-Relationship Theory

NORCO COLLEGE SLO to PLO MATRIX

Dramatic Theory and Criticism

Aristotle. Aristotle. Aristotle and Plato. Background. Aristotle and Plato. Aristotle and Plato

Leaving China An Artist Paints His World War II Childhood

Lectures On The History Of Philosophy, Volume 1: Greek Philosophy To Plato By E. S. Haldane, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel

POPULAR LITERATURE, AUTHORSHIP AND THE OCCULT IN LATE VICTORIAN BRITAIN

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

African Fractals Ron Eglash

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

The Meaning of Abstract and Concrete in Hegel and Marx

Style Matters : The Event of Style in Literature Book Review Elsa Fiott antae, Vol. 2, No. 1. (Mar., 2015), 58 62

[My method is] a science that studies the life of signs within society I shall call it semiology from the Greek semeion signs (Saussure)

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

ICOMOS Ename Charter for the Interpretation of Cultural Heritage Sites

Richard Wollheim on the Art of Painting

The Critical Turn in Education: From Marxist Critique to Poststructuralist Feminism to Critical Theories of Race

6AANB th Century Continental Philosophy. Basic information. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines. Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Nature's Perspectives

Course Syllabus. Ancient Greek Philosophy (direct to Philosophy) (toll-free; ask for the UM-Flint Philosophy Department)

Critical essays. Assessment criteria. Component 1: Portfolio (coursework) Written Assignments. Band Mark Descriptors Band Band

Reviews. Structures of Experience and Dispositions of Being

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

History of East Asia I. TTh 1:30-2:50 ATG 123

On Recanati s Mental Files

Welcome to Sociology A Level

Classical Chinese Popular Fiction & Drama in Translation (01:165: 242) Spring 2018 Monday/Wednesday 1:10 pm 2:30 pm HC-S126

The contribution of material culture studies to design

A Euclidic Paradigm of Freemasonry

Download History And Historians (7th Edition) Books

Transcription:

Wesleyan University From the SelectedWorks of Stephen C. Angle 2014 Review of Li, The Confucian Philosophy of Harmony Stephen C. Angle, Wesleyan University Available at: https://works.bepress.com/stephen-c-angle/ 7/

Chenyang Li, The Confucian Philosophy of Harmony. London and New York: Routledge, 2014. Pp. xviii + 197. $145 (hardback). ISBN 978-0415844741. Stephen C. Angle, Wesleyan University The core argument of Chengyang Li s new book is that harmony understood in particular through the categories of deep harmony and creative tension is the central idea of classical Confucianism. Part I contains five chapters that collectively explore the philosophical concept of harmony; the five chapters in Part II examine harmony in practice by looking at the ways that harmony structures Confucian thinking about person, family, society, world, and cosmos. The Confucian Philosophy of Harmony is a learned work, drawing on Li s familiarity with a broader corpus of early Confucian texts than is often found in works on Confucian philosophy. I believe that readers will be largely persuaded by Li s general picture of harmony, as well as by his contention that it is central to Confucianism. At the same time, there are some missed opportunities to dig deeper into the philosophical complexities raised by Confucian ideas of harmony. I will use part of this review to suggest areas where Li might owe us further reflections, including on ways in which his views in this book can dialogue with other scholarly treatments of related issues. Li s book makes a significant contribution to our understanding of Confucianism and of harmony, particularly if he and his readers are able to use the book as a platform for further investigation of its important topics. The method that Li employs is both reconstructive and constructive (2). Part of what he means by reconstructive is that he aims to assemble a wide range of disparate sources, dating largely from the Warring States era and before, into a single coherent view. Some of Li s key sources include the Book of History, Book of Poetry, Book of Changes, and Record of Ritual, as well as oracle-bone and bronze inscriptions, excavated bamboo and silk texts, and the Analects,

Mencius, and Xunzi. Li makes significant use of etymological analyses of key characters to unearth their early meanings. He sometimes draws on later commentaries, but is more reliant on modern Chinese scholarship to buttress his interpretations of particular words and passages. Indeed, a second reason for his use of reconstructive is that he feels that post-classical Confucians have not continued consistently to use harmony in the same way as their classical forebears, so it is time to restore its rightful name (10). Most of the book operates in this reconstructive vein, confining its sources and interlocutors to early texts, but in the final chapters, Li allows that classical ideas of harmony may have been unsatisfactory (in the case of gender issues) or too limited (in the cases of international and intercultural relations, and of human relations with our environment). Here Li engages in construction that expands his model of Confucian harmony by engaging with both later Chinese ideas and with various Western thinkers. As I stated at the outset, Li argues that one of the key characteristics of Confucian harmony is deep harmony, by which he means an integration of various forces and an ongoing process in a fluid yet dynamic world. [It] does not presuppose a given, fixed, underlying structure of the world (28). Li cites several early sources that describe the initial state of the universe as chaotic, and shows that Heraclitean ideas of harmony as opposed to the ultimately more influential Pythagorean views closely resemble Confucian views in this respect. As a result, Confucian harmony is not something that we discover ; since it is a multidimensional, inclusive, and dynamic creative process, without a pre-established foundation, we need to participate in a proactive way to generate harmony through collaboration (32). I believe this is correct and nicely articulated. I wish, though, that Li had engaged more explicitly with other recent efforts to draw out the sense in which Confucian ideas of harmony are

foundationless. For example, Michael Puett has argued that many early Chinese texts take as their starting point a fractured world of unrelated elements ; in this context, Innovation makes no foundational appeal to either the individual will or any transcendental ground; it is simply a question of endless ritualization in a world that is accepted to be endlessly fragmented (2006, 35). Would Li accept as radical a picture as this? In the chapter of Sagehood devoted to harmony, I also draw on the work of Scott Cook and others to bring out the way in which harmony is generative, open-ended, and even (in some sense) creative, while at the same time recognizing the existence of natural patterns and the possibility of perfection or getting-it-right (cheng 成 ) (Angle 2009, ch. 4). Later in the book, Li mentions the way in which music can feature authenticity and trueness (p. 50); it is not entirely clear how this fits with deep harmony. Li is certainly correct that the early Confucian view is very different from Plato, but on more nuanced issues it is sometimes difficult to see where he stands, vis-à-vis other positions that have been staked out in the scholarly secondary literature. Creative tension is the other central feature of Li s model of Confucian harmony. In emphasizing tension and still more in saying that a certain form of conflict is compatible with harmony (12) Li is taking a provocative position. He mentions Chung-ying Cheng s view that harmony is the absence of strife or conflict, which I take to be a more mainstream view; in Sagehood I argue that we should talk of complimentary differences rather than conflict. As far as I can tell, what Li means by tension is that two entities must be in competition with one another, and conflict refers to the kind of relationship in which one force aims to destroy or eliminate the other (12-13). I believe that Li has two different scenarios in mind. One emphasizes the generativity of harmony. Rather than see harmony as the once-andfor-all resolution of a competitive situation, he may be thinking (in a rather Hegelian way) that

within our always-changing world, finding a harmonious balance among a set of differences is typically unstable, tending to generate new tensions and thus to push toward new harmonies. Second, in at least one place Li seems content with an arrangement that looks like a scientific equilibrium: wolves eat sheep, weeding out the weaker sheep, but not so many that the sheep are eliminated. On the population level, Li writes, the wolves and sheep are in harmony (13). I find this intriguing but am not sure that historical Confucians would accept this as an instance of harmony. Li himself cites the idea of each getting its due, which according to Cheng Yi means when each gets what it deserves, there is peace; when they do not get it, there is conflict (14). I believe that if each element fully internalizes the complete situation fully takes the whole world into account as part of understanding what its due would be, which I take it is what Li s harmony consciousness is striving for (see below) then the ideal of harmony would be one in which there is no conflict or disharmony (Angle 2009, 214). Harmony occurs when all parties accept that the solution is what is called for by the situation with respect to each of them, and none are completely discounted (see Li on the harmony of musical notes, 48, and my discussion of Slote s balanced caring cases in 2009, 79f.). Where does that leave the wolves and sheep? I submit that they are in a form of equilibrium that falls short of harmony. Stepping back from the central questions of deep harmony and creative tension and ranging more broadly over the book, I find that there are many points in which I am in complete agreement with Li, and some in which I at least feel the need for more argument. Li s discussion of quan 權 ( weighing or discretion ) contains some of each. His explanation of when and how discretion can be applied, and what constraints it must honor, is excellent (131-2). I cannot agree, though, with his claim that quanli 權利, the Chinese term used to translate rights, means accorded benefit after appropriate weighing (133). There are both historical/contextual and

philosophical reasons for understanding the quan in quanli as referring to a proper kind of power, and as not being readily subject to situational weighing or discretion as indeed Li seems to realize, when he says that a right is more like jing than quan (133, and see generally Angle 2002). Another issue emerges in Li s discussion of the relation between harmony and ritual propriety. This is an important topic and for the most part Li handles it very well, bringing out the balance of differentiation and unification that lie at the heart of both harmony and ritual. To some degree, though, Li forces himself to reinvent the wheel by not drawing on some of the best recent scholarship on Confucian ritual propriety. One example will suffice: at several points in his chapter, Li could have constructively made use of Daniel Bell s argument that ritual is uniquely well-suited to bring together people of differing status into a constructive whole that does not collapse the differences (Bell 2008). If we turn to Li s discussion of harmony within the family, we find another place in which the book s arguments could have been strengthened through more engagement with recent secondary literature. Li criticizes traditional Confucian views of relations between men and women, and takes a few steps toward articulating Confucian resources useful for building a more equal relationship between husband and wife (110). As he surely knows, though, much work has been done in this area already; drawing on Sin Yee Chan s arguments, for instance, would have helped Li develop precisely the kind of constructive, modern vision of harmony that he is after (Chan 2000). One of the reasons that Li did not engage more with my positions in Sagehood, no doubt, is his feeling that the ancient understanding of harmony was largely lost in Song-Ming Neo- Confucianism (173n21). Without denying that there are many differences between Classical and Neo-Confucianism, I would resist seeing such a strong differentiation on the issue of harmony, but I do not have the space to make out such an argument here. Instead, let me conclude by

thanking Chenyang Li for authoring such a rich and provocative book. Harmony is an immensely important issue within Confucianism, and if Li has not provided the final word on its every contour, he has nonetheless provided us with clearly articulated positions, and in many cases important steps forward, on a whole range of issues.

Works Cited Angle, Stephen C. Human Rights and Chinese Thought: A Cross-Cultural Inquiry. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2002.. Sagehood: The Contemporary Significance of Neo-Confucian Philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press, 2009. Bell, Daniel A. Hierarchical Rituals for Egalitarian Societies. China s New Confucianism: Politics and Everyday Life in a Changing Society. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2008. 38-55. Chan, Sin Yee. Gender Relationship Roles in the Analects and the Mencius. Asian Philosophy. 2:1 (2000): 115-132. Puett, Michael J. Innovation as Ritualization: The Fractured Cosmology of Early China. Cardoza Law Review. 28 (2006): 23-36.