KONSTANTINOS KAVOULAKOS. University of Crete

Similar documents
By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Subjectivity and its crisis: Commodity mediation and the economic constitution of objectivity and subjectivity

Adorno - The Tragic End. By Dr. Ibrahim al-haidari *

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

A Fresh Look at Lukács: on Steven Vogel's Against Nature

Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION

Lukács and the Dialectical Critique of Capitalism Moishe Postone

Marx and Lukács: Reason and Revolution in the Philosophy of Praxis

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

Aesthetics and meaning

Critical Theory and the Historical Transformations of Capitalist Modernity

Idealism and Pragmatism: "Transcendent" Validity Claims in Habermas's Democratic Theory

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory

Basic positions and research questions of a philosophy of practice

Todd Hedrick

IX Colóquio Internacional Marx e Engels GT 4 - Economia e política

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

2 Rethinking the Communicative Turn

This thesis is protected by copyright which belongs to the author.

Critical Political Economy of Communication and the Problem of Method

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

t< k '" a.-j w~lp4t..

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Course Description. Alvarado- Díaz, Alhelí de María 1. The author of One Dimensional Man, Herbert Marcuse lecturing at the Freie Universität, 1968

Rethinking the Normative Content of Critical Theory

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Werner Bonefeld s new book falls within the left German tradition

CRITICAL THEORY. John Sinclair

Investigating subjectivity

(Ulrich Schloesser/ Humboldt-Universität zu Berlin)

Chapter 2: Karl Marx Test Bank

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by


HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

The concept of capital and the determination of the general and uniform rates of profit: a reappraisal

Philosophy in the educational process: Understanding what cannot be taught

Writing an Honors Preface

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Watcharabon Buddharaksa. The University of York. RCAPS Working Paper No January 2011

Lia Mela. Democritus University of Thrace. Keywords: modernity, reason, tradition, good, Frankfurt School, MacIntyre, Taylor

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

PRAGMATIZING CRITICAL THEORY S PROVINCE

Adorno s Critique of Heidegger in Why Still Philosophy (1962)

A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theory and Society.

Prof. Dr. Konstantinos Kavoulakos 04 October 1967 Hellenic (Greek) Meletiou Piga 8, Rethymno (Greece)

Sociological theories: the tradition and current notions pt II

observation and conceptual interpretation

HERMENEUTIC PHILOSOPHY AND DATA COLLECTION: A PRACTICAL FRAMEWORK

Critical Media Theory. Henrik Åhman Department of Informatics and Media

CRITIQUE AS UNCERTAINTY

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

What is Postmodernism? What is Postmodernism?

SECTION I: MARX READINGS

Adorno, (Non-)Dialectical Thought, (Post-)Autonomy, and the Question of Bildung A response to Douglas Yacek

Loggerhead Sea Turtle

8. The dialectic of labor and time

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

The Transcendental Force of Money: Social Synthesis in Marx

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Review by Răzvan CÎMPEAN

1) Review of Hall s Two Paradigms

Contradictions A Journal for Critical Thought Volume 1 number 2 (2017) Editorial

The Role of the Form/Content Distinction in Hegel's Science of Logic

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

After Modernity. Fall 2010

A discussion of Jean L. Cohen, Class and Civil Society: The Limits of Marxian Critical Theory, (Amherst: University of Mass. Press, 1982).

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Introduction. Critique of Commodity Aesthetics

Excerpt: Karl Marx's Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts

OF MARX'S THEORY OF MONEY

Durham Research Online

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

Realizing Philosophy: Marx, Lukács and the Frankfurt School

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

Critical Spatial Practice Jane Rendell

A Hegel-Marx Debate About the Relation of the Individual and Society

Habermas Discourse Ethics as the Foundation of Legitimate Laws

Contents. Notes on Contributors. 1 Introduction 1 Stefano Giacchetti Ludovisi. 2 Adorno s Global Subject 5 Deborah Cook

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

6 The Analysis of Culture

Marxism and. Literature RAYMOND WILLIAMS. Oxford New York OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

A RE-INTERPRETATION OF ARTISTIC MODERNISM WITH EMPHASIS ON KANT AND NEWMAN DANNY SHORKEND

Phenomenology Glossary

Critical Theory for Research on Librarianship (RoL)

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Transcription:

KONSTANTINOS KAVOULAKOS University of Crete PHILOSOPHICAL ANTHROPOLOGY OR PHILOSOPHY OF PRAXIS? AXEL HONNETH AND ANDREW FEENBERG ON LUKACS THEORY OF REIFICATION xel Honneth s Reification. A New Look at an Old Idea (2008) and Andrew Feenberg s Philosophy of Praxis (2014) represent two recent publications, which give a clear indication of the revived theoretical interest in a classical concept of critical theory. It is the concept of reification as was shaped by Georg Lukács in his legendary book History and Class Consciousness (1923), to whose analyses both theorists refer. Both contributions are of great importance for a new account of critical theory s basic theoretical tools: As is well known, the concept of reification played a crucial role in the tradition of critical theory from its initial formulations by Horkheimer and Adorno to Habermas s Theory of Communicative Action (1981). They become even more important if we consider the tendency of the younger generation of critical theorists, who are inspired by Habermas and his turn towards liberalism and pragmatism, to totally abandon this classical concept as irreversibly outdated. However, although Honneth and Feenberg share the conviction that the concept of reification is still worth reflecting upon, they choose different, even contrasting ways of reconstructing it. Thus I wish to make a short comment on the actuality and the theoretical credibility of their interpretations of the Lukácsian concept of reification. I shall start with the issue of the respective actuality of these interpretations and then I shall move on to some deeper philosophical questions raised by them. Honneth s interpretation of reification in terms of his theory of recognition has the unambiguous consequence of its de-radicalization. I shall come back to this aspect later for now it suffices to note Honneth s repeatedly expressed reservations about Lukács s radical critique of capitalist economy and modern bureaucracy, i.e. those social structures, which Lukács eminently associated with the phenomenon of reification. Following Habermas, Honneth connects the error of an overly radical critique of the differentiated structures of the so-called system with the idealist philosophical presuppositions of the philosophy of subject and the paradigm of production espoused by Lukács. Therefore he searches following another intellectual habit of Habermas for an unofficial version of the concept of reification that supposedly took the form of an oblivion of recognition in man s practical relation to his environment and above all to other human beings. This is of course a version that fits the communicative critical theory and especially the theory of recognition introduced by Honneth himself. When Honneth first published his Tanner Lectures on reification in German in 2005 his argument seemed much more convincing when it dogmatically presupposed a politically neutral, unquestionable efficacy of instrumental action and its systems. This presupposition

of the inescapability of differentiated rational systems in the modern world mirrors nothing but a widespread prejudice of the Habermasian critical theorists during the last thirty years. It determines a fashionable way of posing the question of the tension between capitalism and democracy in terms of their complementarity and not so much in terms of their oppositeness. But it is exactly this efficacy which is increasingly called into question since the beginning of the global economic crisis in 2008 the very same year the English translation of Honneth s book appeared. In the aftermath of the bank-collapse and the resulting economic recession in the developed world we continue to experience the defaults of whole countries and the subsequent bailing-outs accompanied by the imposition of extremely neoliberal austerity measures that constantly make financial problems worse. This is especially the case in Europe. At the same time, formal democracy becomes an empty shell under which conservative, authoritarian, even fascist, political tendencies grow not to speak of the war scenes that are multiplying around the globe. Under these conditions it is no wonder there is an increasing number of voices demanding a new social economy and a real democracy. And one should add to that the culmination of the anxiety in view of the upcoming climate change and ecological crisis in general. Today s multifaceted crisis nourishes the feeling that we are not facing this or that particular problem but a general crisis of the dominant system and its rationality as a whole. Therefore, if in 2005 Honneth was in a position to claim that Lukács s radical critique of capitalist and bureaucratic rationality is outdated, today we are rather inclined to think that Honneth s moderate critique, which leaves the core principles of the global system untouched, is rapidly losing the ground to which it could be applied. The crisis and the new consciousness that grows out of it represent, as Lukács would like to have it, the first stage in a process of dereification through the practical resistance of those who are being destroyed by the dominant social structures and principles. Undoubtedly, this context renders an explication of crisis on the basis of a deeper inadequacy of these structures like the one detected by the theory of reification in its classical formulation more attractive and interesting. This is the case in Feenberg s reinterpretation of the Lukácsian concept of reification. Let us now turn our attention to the respective content of the two interpretations under discussion. As I have already suggested, Honneth lets the greatest part of Lukács s analyses on reification disappear from his reconstruction and highlights only some less important dimensions, that conform with his theory of recognition. He totally forgets Lukács s critique of commodity fetishism as real abstraction (Realabstraktion), and his consequent critique of abstract thought and calculative intellect, which permeate both the capitalist economy and the bureaucratic organizations. Thus, he deletes the part of Lukács s theory that inspired the critique of instrumental reason of the Frankfurt School. He shows no interest in Lukács s notion of crisis, his concept of totality on which the explanation of crisis is grounded, the notion of the historical tendencies and processes that should comprise human powers of resistance against reification. For him all these aspects and many others are part of an outdated, idealist way of thinking. What remains after cleaning up the concept of reification from the rust of the past? Only a thin notion of reification as a lack of existential involvement of the individual in his social interactions 523

with other individuals remains. This rather secondary dimension of the overall phenomenon of reification becomes its essence due to an eclectic reading of Lukács s notion of a contemplative attitude. However, by contemplative Lukács did not mean, first and foremost psychologically detached or neutral in opposition to humanly involved, as Honneth suggests. He rather described the passivity of subjects that take the social-historical world as unalterable in opposition to the active attitude of a subject that intervenes in the world in order to change its historically contingent necessities. As this meaning of activity is suspect of conveying outdated Fichtean insights, Honneth prefers to reduce reification to sentimentally indifferent instrumentalization of others or even the self, aiming at the realization of egoistic goals. Through references to Heidegger and Dewey, Honneth connects this individual stance with the distancing of the individual from a fundamental dimension of being-in-theworld, namely its multifaceted participatory involvement and the recognition of otherness. Thus reification is oblivion of a fundamental anthropological dimension of our lives. As the historical understanding of reification drastically gives way to anthropology, it remains unclear what could be done in the interest of emancipation against the oblivion of recognition. Let us turn to Feenberg s reading, which could also be characterized as eclectic. However, I believe that it remains essentially faithful to the true spirit of Lukács s classic book and at the same time it offers substantial updating of some of its core theses. Therefore, in what follows I will not distinguish Feenberg s position from Lukács analyses, nor from my own understanding of them. Against Honneth s approach, Lukács opposed philosophical anthropology, which he justifiably viewed as abstract and ahistorical. Thus it is very unlikely that when he spoke of reification he had an anthropological concept of recognition in mind. In this respect, his analyses are clear enough: Reification must be understood as a historically changing, socially mediated phenomenon, which permeates the totality of social life at a certain stage of its historical development; namely in modern capitalist society. This totality shows, in fact, a specific distortion, whose cause is not some mysterious oblivion of certain human reciprocal attitudes but the historically contingent prevalence of a specific, inadequate form of objectivity. Drawing on this fundamental epistemological concept of Neokantian philosophy, with which he was very well acquainted during his time of study in Heidelberg, Lukács seeks to theoretically grasp the fundamental social mediation of man s relation to the world. Thus, contrary to the Neokantians, for Lukács the form of objectivity becomes a social-historical and therefore historically changeable category of both the epistemic and the practical spheres of experience and human life. Through these modifications the form of objectivity becomes the conceptual basis for a metacritique of the established forms of cognition and action. According to Feenberg, this element of metacritique is typical of a certain kind of philosophizing, namely the philosophy of praxis. On the basis of the concept of the form of objectivity, theory turns its attention towards social totality with its unitary organization of epistemic and practical activities. At the same time, it acknowledges the root of the crisis and fragmentation of this totality, since the form of objectivity proves to be inadequate for and in conflict with the content it forms and organizes. Indeed, the content overflows the form and questions its adequacy. 524

Thus, reification is a total social phenomenon caused by the inadequacy of the social form of mediation of an untamed and chaotic material. It results out of the violent imposition of form on material content, the otherness of which is violated and suppressed. At the same time the social form engaged in everyday practice appears as a natural fact, as an unalterable condition of human experience and praxis in general this is what Lukács meant when he explicated reification as taking social relations as things. Thus the inadequate form of social mediation is naturalized and its domination is fostered and perpetuated this is the case in periods of normal social life, when the resistance of the material is easily broken down. If the philosophy of praxis confined itself to describing this naturalization it would turn into a bare diagnosis of the final establishment of a dystopia; this is how the later Frankfurt School is often interpreted. Therefore theorists of the Frankfurt School s second generation felt obliged to distance themselves, not only from such a diagnosis, but also from the conceptual framework upon which it rests. The shortcomings of the so-called paradigm of production supposedly block the theoretical grasping of the emancipative potential of modern social structures like individualism and its legal institutionalization, formal democratic institutions etc. It is certainly true that the philosophy of praxis is not so much concerned with justifying existing institutions it rather aims at pointing out the ability of human action to alter them in such a way that they better correspond to the social needs and contents they are supposed to organize. This process of transforming social institutions stands at the centre of Feenberg s considerations on the dialectical mediation between reified structures and the active resistance of men. Their dialectical interplay, which is more or less missing from Honneth s theory, is an essential part of Lukács s holistic understanding of the dialectical interdependence between form and content. Feenberg justifiably stresses in his reconstruction the non-identity of form and content and the relative independence of the latter, in the light of which reification must be viewed as a historically finite social phenomenon that can be abolished in its present form: Firstly through the consciousness of its historical contingency, and secondly through conscious human intervention and modification of the fundamental form of objectivity and its institutional incarnations that effect reification. Non-identity has a further anti-dogmatic meaning that discredits a great number of the critiques of Lukács s theory formulated, among others, also by Honneth: De-reification is not a final praxis of rational production of the object. As Lukács noted in 1923, it has to be viewed as a dynamic process of unbroken alternation of ossification, contradiction and movement (HCC, 199). Thus, within the Lukácsian perspective we should abandon the idea of a completely transparent and de-reified social condition and envisage a future in which a contradictory democratic control over all the fields of social life would at least be rendered possible. In my opinion, the philosophy of praxis in the form suggested by Feenberg represents a cogent and viable alternative to the de- radicalized anthropological interpretation of reification. Konstantinos Kavoulakos is Associate Professor of Social and Political Philosophy, Philosophy of Culture, Department of Philosophy and Social Studies, Philosophical Faculty at the University of Crete. He received his Ph.D. in Social and Political Philosophy from the Panteion University of 525

Athens. His primary research interests are located in the areas of modern and contemporary social and political philosophy, Kant and German Idealism, philosophy and critique of culture, philosophy of history, theories on democracy, and critical theory. His current work is focused on an investigation of the 20th century tradition of critical social thought from a contemporary perspective. Among a number of books he has written or edited, he is the author of Ästhetizistische Kulturkritik und Ethische Utopie: Georg Lukács Neukantianisches Frühwerk (2014) and Tragedy and History. The Critique of Modern Culture in the Early Work of Georg Lukács (2012). 526