Review. DuMMETT, MICHAEL. The elements of intuitionism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977, χ+467 pages.

Similar documents
Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Curry s Formalism as Structuralism

Scientific Philosophy

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

Constructive mathematics and philosophy of mathematics

cse371/mat371 LOGIC Professor Anita Wasilewska

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

Logical Foundations of Mathematics and Computational Complexity a gentle introduction

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Haskell Brooks Curry was born on 12 September 1900 at Millis, Massachusetts and died on 1 September 1982 at

Internal Realism. Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

1 Mathematics and its philosophy

Introduction Section 1: Logic. The basic purpose is to learn some elementary logic.

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Non-Classical Logics. Viorica Sofronie-Stokkermans Winter Semester 2012/2013

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Designing a Deductive Foundation System

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

An Introduction to Formal Logic

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

Appendix B. Elements of Style for Proofs

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Diversity in Proof Appraisal

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

On Judgements and Propositions

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

Fig. I.1 The Fields Medal.

TOWARDS A BEHAVIORAL PSYCHOLOGY OF MATHEMATICAL THINKING

Conclusion. 1) From the point of view of the Sudoku addict, the most striking results should be the following.

AN EXAMPLE FOR NATURAL LANGUAGE UNDERSTANDING AND THE AI PROBLEMS IT RAISES

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Do Not Claim Too Much: Second-order Logic and First-order Logic

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

PHILOSOPH ICAL PERSPECTI VES ON PROOF IN MATHEMATI CS EDUCATION

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Cambridge Introductions to Philosophy new textbooks from cambridge

On the imaginative constructivist nature of design: a theoretical approach

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

On The Search for a Perfect Language

This is an author produced version of Introduction from type theory and homotopy theory to univalent foundations.

Computability and Logic, Fifth Edition

STRUCTURES AND STRUCTURALISM IN CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

A Functional Representation of Fuzzy Preferences

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

Mario Verdicchio. Topic: Art

ABSTRACTS HEURISTIC STRATEGIES. TEODOR DIMA Romanian Academy

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Philosophy 405: Knowledge, Truth and Mathematics Spring Russell Marcus Hamilton College

Logica & Linguaggio: Tablaux

PRIOR ON THE LOGIC AND THE METAPHYSICS OF TIME

VISUALISATION AND PROOF: A BRIEF SURVEY

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Introduction: A Musico-Logical Offering

Qeauty and the Books: A Response to Lewis s Quantum Sleeping Beauty Problem

Formalising arguments

THE PROBLEM OF INTERPRETING MODAL LOGIC w. V. QUINE

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

TRUTH AND CIRCULAR DEFINITIONS

The Culpable Inability Problem for Synchronic and Diachronic Ought Implies Can

For French and Saatsi (eds.), Continuum Companion to Philosophy of Science

Frege s Philosophy. Course Outline and Selected Reading

Download Deductive Logic pdf

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Mathematical Realism in Jean Ladrière and Xavier Zubiri: Comparative Analysis of the Philosophical Status of Mathematical Objects, Methods, and Truth

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 10, No. 1. (Sep., 1949), pp

Author's personal copy

1/10. The A-Deduction

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Dan Nesher, Department of Philosophy University of Haifa, Israel

An Introduction to Description Logic I

INTRODUCTION TO AXIOMATIC SET THEORY

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

SENSE AND OBJECTIVITY IN FREGE'S LOGIC

Beliefs under Unawareness

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

Introduction. Bonnie Gold Monmouth University. 1 The Purpose of This Book

Supplementary Course Notes: Continuous vs. Discrete (Analog vs. Digital) Representation of Information

MATH 195: Gödel, Escher, and Bach (Spring 2001) Notes and Study Questions for Tuesday, March 20

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

Introduction It is now widely recognised that metonymy plays a crucial role in language, and may even be more fundamental to human speech and cognitio

Transcription:

Review DuMMETT, MICHAEL. The elements of intuitionism. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977, χ+467 pages. Over the last twenty years, Dummett has written a long series of papers advocating a view on meaning which has become known as "antirealism". Now, in the book under review, we are given a thorough treatment of a mathematical version of antirealism; the sort of version from which extensions to non-mathematical contexts take their departure. The book is, in fact, an expansion and revision of previously circulated lecture notes from the Mathematical Institute, Oxford and the new parts comprise 150 pages of mainly philosophical material on the claims of intuitionism. In the first two, out of seven, chapters some standard concepts of intuitionistic mathematics are introduced, in particular the notion of constructive proof, with the reading of mathematical truth as possession of constructive proof and the accompanying logical laws. The discussion of these matters is lucid, elegant and the most exhaustive in the literature. In these chapters, one also finds a treatment of the intuitionistic version of the real number continuum, where a real is a constructive Cauchy-sequence of rationale, as well as a description of the Gödel-Gentzen double-negation interpretation of classical formal systems into the corresponding intuitionistic formal system. When discussing the completeness of the intuitionistic continuum, viz., that every constructive Cauchy-sequence of intuitionistic reals has a constructive limit, Dummett rightly stresses the intuitionistic validity of the Axiom of choice. Indeed, from a constructive proof of Vx3yA(x, y), one immediately extracts a constructive function b such that VxA(x, b(xy), and therefore one is entitled to assert the implication Vx3yA(x, y)->3fvxa(x, f(xj). The traditional "constructivist" qualms over the Axiom of choice only arise on positions intermediate

REVIEW 91 between the full-blooded platonism of the cumulative hierarchy and constructivism. Examples of such positions are those of Russell and Poincaré. The third chapter in the opinion of the reviewer, the best in the book is devoted to a meticulous examination of the intuitionistic properties of the quantifier-combinations V/3«and V/3g. The treatment is focussed on various notions of continuity very roughly, the n which exists given the ƒ depends only on a finite initial segment of the ƒ and Bar-induction an induction principle linking up the meaning of the prefix with a certain type of inductive definition. The famous Brouwer "proof of Bar-induction is given a novel and profound discussion. Using a counter-example of Kleene's, Dummett is able to pinpoint exactly where the Brouwerian argument goes astray; he shows that, as so often, the crux of the matter is intuitionistic invalidity of the distributive law Vx(A v Bx)->A v V xbx. This chapter, apart from the novel treatment of Brouwer's "proof, also contains a beautiful exposition of a host of original research-material by, e.g., Kleene, Kreisel, Howard, Troelstra, etc, which makes many otherwise rather inaccessible results readily available in a uniform notation. From there, Dummett goes on to treat the modern formal counterparts to Brouwer's "fully analysed" proofs, i.e., cut-free derivations in sequent calculi and normal derivations in natural deduction systems. The cut-elimination and normalisation theorems are proved by standard methods. This chapter, although the exposition is most competent, is strangely left hanging in the air: it is not made sufficiently clear why the theorems proved are of great interest. Apart from some well-known applications, Dummett makes no further use of the normal forms he has so laboriously derived, nor does he attempt to explain the "philosophical significance" of normalisation. This is a criticism which may be voiced against almost all proof-theoretical practicians. Kreisel, in particular, has tried to rectify the situation, but so far without conclusive success; we are still in want of the proper concepts with which to formulate the theorems that are established by the proof-theoretical transformation techniques. On the whole, this chapter could well have been replaced by some other left-out part of the meta-mathematics of intuitionism, as its content is easily available in many places.

92 REVIEW Next comes a rapid shift into the semantics of intuitionistic formal systems. The author starts out by introducing the Beth- and Kripkemodels via the topological interpretations and valuation systems. Pedagogically, this seems to the reviewer to be a mistake. In order to get an understanding of the semantics in question, a retreat to, say, the exposition by Fitting seems to be called for, because of the rather tortuous way the models are introduced in the book. The classical completeness of the Beth-tableaux is established along the usual pattern and then follows one of the high-spots of the book: a complete survey of the Gödel-Kreisel results on the incompleteness of first order intuitionistic predicate calculus. This survey will, like chapter III, save the reader much time and trouble in mastering an otherwise rather inaccessible area. One of the more interesting recent contributions to the subject is the Nijmegen-school results on completeness for deviant Beth-models (By allowing absurdity to be true at some nodes, De Swart and Veldman discovered a way to circumvent the Gödel-Kreisel result). Dummett devotes the rest of chapter V to various versions of these deviant models and discusses their (doubtful) intuitive rationale. The technicalities involved are quite complicated and perhaps do not belong in The "elements" of intuit ionism. Chapter VI is one of the more useful chapters: it contains surveys of current formal systems such as Kleene's FIM and Kreisel- Troelstra's CS with statements, though not proofs, of central metaresults. There is a fine guide to the jungle of realisability interpretations including the Kleene-slash. The chapter ends with a thoughtful analysis of Brouwer's theory of the creative subject and the difficulties which arise when one tries to incorporate statements about tense in mathematics. The final chapter is a lengthy philosophical treatment of the meaning theory underlying intuitionism, very much like Dummett's article in Logic colloquium '73 (Eds. Rose & Sheperdson, North- Holland, 1975). He also treats the notions of canonical argument and demonstrations; the former are the normative constructions used to define the meanings of the logical constants, whereas the latter are what is needed for the assertion of a statement. There arises the need to convince oneself that each demonstration can be brought to a

REVIEW 93 canonical argument. On the formal level this is quite similar to the normalisation procedure for arbitrary derivations. Dummett then relates these notions to the Beth-trees in a novel way and ends the book with a survey of choice sequences. The philosophical position of Dummett on intuitionistic logic was subjected to a sympathetic scrutiny by Prawitz, "Meaning and proofs" (Theoria 43, (1977), pp. 1 xx), and I will here only raise some points which have not been covered either by Prawitz or Dummett. As Prawitz rightly stresses, the demand of harmony between the grounds for asserting, and the consequences following from, an utterance is closely related to a Gentzen-inversion principle and the removal of maxima from natural deduction derivations. At the Kiel conference in 1974, Marcel Crabbé caused something of a commotion among proof theorists when he produced a counterexample to normalisation for what seems a reasonable formalisation of the set-theoretic Aussonderung-axiom. We introduce restricted comprehension-terms and rules for them: from the two premisses tea and F(t) infer te{xea:f(x)} and from this conclusion either premiss may be inferred. An inversion principle is immediate. However, form the relativised Russell-class A a = def {jcea:x^jf}. In the most straightforward way one proves that /? a a, which derivation will contain a maximum. A few removals of maxima bring us back to the original derivation again and harmony is blocked. Against the background of the Prawitz-Dummett arguments, it is interesting to note the following: -f the system is very weak (Aussonderung + existence of a set) + the logic used is intuitionistic (even minimal) + full type theory (an incomparably stronger system) admits normalisation and harmony. What then is there in this conception of a set that precludes harmony? The most likely cause seems to the reviewer to be the explicit suppression of an implicitly understood type structure: an object is always given as an object of a certain kind or type. This is true also of settheory but the formalisms currently used do not reflect this fact, whereas the formalism of an even cumulative type theory does. The matter is in need of a detailed investigation and it is a pity that neither

94 REVIEW Prawitz nor Dummett addresses himself to the issue. Another point worth mentioning deals with the meaning of implication. We usually say that a proof of an implication is a construction which transforms constructions proving the antecedent into constructions proving the consequent. On page 399, Dummett flirts with the Kreisel-idea of having another construction included as well which should prove that the first indeed does what it is supposed to do. To the reviewer this cornes close to demanding that one should prove that a proof is a proof, which one cannot. A proof has to be understood as a proof of its conclusion it cannot be proved to be a proof of that conclusion. In a non-mathematical version of antirealism, the analogous demand would require us to have senseimpressions verifying other sense-impressions verifying certain elementary sentences, etc. The reviewer for one would not like such a theory. Furthermore it should be remarked that it is not clear that the argument based on the proof-theoretical meaning theory, with its presupposition of normalisation and harmony, actually justifies intuitionistic analysis. The reviewer is willing to accept that systems adequate for a formalisation of Bishop's Constructive mathematics, e.g., Martin-Lofs type theory, can be justified using the Dummett argument. He cannot see, however, how to proceed to the intuitionistic notion of choice sequence within the Dummett framework. A final, non-related point: Dummett is quite sceptical about the possible interest of eclecticism, i.e., the position which seeks to develop interesting meaning-theories for both platonism and constructivism. If the former can be made to work, the latter would be uninteresting. Kreisel, who is branded as an eclectic by Dummett, points out in conversation that philosophically eclecticism is at least as interesting as either of the two alternatives: it gives a way to link the external mathematical universe of platonism with the idealistic universe of intuitionism, "which gives rich possibilities for speculative metaphysics and should delight a professional philosopher". Almost as interesting to discuss as the contents of the book is perhaps (the possible reasons for) the exclusion of some topics from the book. The most regrettable is Dummett's intentional omission of Gödel's Dialectica interpretation. Of all the subjects within intui-

REVIEW 95 tionistic meta-mathematics this is the one where there remains a great need for an elegant survey. Dummett had a great opportunity here and would that he had taken it in the style of chapter III! The book would have been improved by a shortening of the semantics chapter, and the possible exclusion of chapter IV, and the addition of a chapter on functional interpretations. Another remarkable omission lies in the fact that Dummett nowhere in close to 500 pages on intuitionism refers to the works of Per Martin-Löf. He twice in the text refers to the "intended interpretation" and mentions the Kreisel-Goodman theory of constructions. A reference to the type theory of Martin-Löf would have been well-motivated here. Also in the normalisation chapter, Martin-Lofs old conjecture that identity between proofs can be explicated as congruence of normal forms ought to have been mentioned. Finally there is the point alluded to above that the type theory of Martin-Löf may well be the natural mathematical home for Dummett's meaning theoretical views, in spite of the differences between their respective positions on meaning theory. Dummett states in the preface that he wanted to write a book which would help the beginner to attack more specialized research papers within the field by people like Kleene, Troelstra, Kreisel, etc. In this task he succeeds completely throughout most of the book. In spite of the reservations about chapters IV and V, the reviewer's overall impression is one of admiration. The book remains a tremendous achievment and will for many years to come be the book on intuitionism. Göran Sundholm Worcester & Magdalen Colleges, Oxford