WHO IS AN AFRICAN? ISSUES IN THE CONSTRUCTION OF AFRICAN IDENTITIES

Similar documents
African Philosophy. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

NORCO COLLEGE SLO to PLO MATRIX

Multicultural Foundations for Philosophy of Education: A Propaedeutic

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

Philosophic Sagacity: Aims and Functions 1

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

English (ENGL) English (ENGL) 1

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

Humanities Learning Outcomes

A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY. James Bartell

TEACHING A GROWING POPULATION OF NON-NATIVE ENGLISH SPEAKING STUDENTS IN AMERICAN UNIVERSITIES: CULTURAL AND LINGUISTIC CHALLENGES

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

6 The Analysis of Culture

African Philosophy and the Method of Ordinary Language Philosophy

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

AXL4201F - Debates in African Studies Intellectuals of the African Liberation First Semester, 2018 Tuesday 10-12pm Room 3.01 CAS

Reason and Sagacity in Africa: Odera Oruka s Contribution to Philosophy

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

English/Philosophy Department ENG/PHL 100 Level Course Descriptions and Learning Outcomes

The Culture-Oriented Bias of African Philosophical Inquiry

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Kent Academic Repository

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Aristotle on the Human Good

Watcharabon Buddharaksa. The University of York. RCAPS Working Paper No January 2011

Barry Hallen, 2006, African philosophy: The analytic approach

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

Historical/Biographical

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF. the oxford handbook of WORLD PHILOSOPHY. GARFIELD-Halftitle2-Page Proof 1 August 10, :24 PM

In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Page109. Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions

Revisiting the African-Africana philosophy of education debate: implications for university teaching

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

Block C1. (re) Arts Comparative and transnational studies of Asian and Asian American cultures with a focus on literature, film, and visual arts.

Instrumental Music Curriculum

The Question of Equilibrium in Human Action and the Everyday Paradox of Rationality

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Assess the contribution of symbolic interactionism to the understanding of communications and social interactions

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

Program General Structure

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Content or Discontent? Dealing with Your Academic Ancestors

1/9. The B-Deduction

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

t< k '" a.-j w~lp4t..

REVIEW ARTICLE BOOK TITLE: ORAL TRADITION AS HISTORY

Royce: The Anthropology of Dance

Values and Limitations of Various Sources

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

Zhu Xi's Reading of the Analects: Canon, Commentary, and the Classical Tradition (review)

COURSE: PHILOSOPHY GRADE(S): NATIONAL STANDARDS: UNIT OBJECTIVES: Students will be able to: STATE STANDARDS:

SOCI 421: Social Anthropology

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

On Interpretation and Translation

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

CHAPTER I INTRODUCTION

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

English English ENG 221. Literature/Culture/Ideas. ENG 222. Genre(s). ENG 235. Survey of English Literature: From Beowulf to the Eighteenth Century.

Deconstruction is a way of understanding how something was created and breaking something down into smaller parts.

The Existential Act- Interview with Juhani Pallasmaa

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

What is woman s voice?: Focusing on singularity and conceptual rigor

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

CRITIQUE OF PARSONS AND MERTON

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Normative and Positive Economics

Mass Communication Theory

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

[T]here is a social definition of culture, in which culture is a description of a particular way of life. (Williams, The analysis of culture )

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

BDD-A Universitatea din București Provided by Diacronia.ro for IP ( :46:58 UTC)

Objectivity: A Subject of Discourse in Historical Writing

History and Theory, Theme Issue 51 (December 2012), 1-5 Wesleyan University 2012 ISSN:

AP World History Analytical Acronyms

CARROLL ON THE MOVING IMAGE

Nicomachean Ethics. p. 1. Aristotle. Translated by W. D. Ross. Book II. Moral Virtue (excerpts)

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

Transcription:

WHO IS AN AFRICAN? ISSUES IN THE CONSTRUCTION OF AFRICAN IDENTITIES Dr. Ibanga B. Ikpe University of Botswana Gaborone Botswana +267 355 2633 +267 7136 1563 IKPE@mopipi.ub.bw Introduction In his contribution to the debate in African philosophy, Paulin Hountondji refers to African philosophy as a set of texts, specifically the set of texts written by Africans and described as philosophical by the authors themselves. 1 Although Hountondji was responding views that he considers counterfeit to the philosophical enterprise, his comment has elicited a flurry of responses that attempt to demonstrate the inappropriateness of his characterization of African philosophy. The main arguments against his characterization have been that writing is not a prerequisite for philosophy especially since writing neither contributes to thought process nor to the rigor of philosophical argument. Hountondji has also been criticized for his view that one has to be African to write African philosophy. It has been argued that the universality of philosophy makes it inappropriate to attempt to exclude certain groups of people from contributing to a specific trend in philosophy and more especially as the same demand is not usually made of those who contribute to Chinese, British or American philosophy. Thirdly, Hountondji has been criticized for implying that mere declaration by an author that a piece of writing as philosophical is sufficient for the work to be deemed philosophical. Critics have observed that the intent of the author or any declarations by him concerning his work is not relevant to the classification of the work. Although much have been made of inappropriateness of Hountondji s characterization of African philosophy and Hountondji has tried to respond to his many critics, there has not 1 Hountondji, Paulin, African Philosophy: Myth and Reality, Bloomington, IND: Indiana University Press 1983p 1

been much interest in an important spinoff of the debate and that is the question as to who an African actually is. This question is especially important for today s Africa where the homogeneity that once characterized the African population is disappearing as people of Asian and European descent become naturalized Africans. It is also important given the growing trend for sections of the indigenous population strive to become more Western than the Westerners. But in saying that African philosophy consists in texts written by Africans, Hountondji seems to be in no doubt that as to who an African actually is. Also when his critics reject his assertion that an African identity is purely geographical, they do not also seem to be in doubt as to who is an African. What is, however clear is that, the image of the African constructed by Hountondji appear to be completely different from that of his critics and that different scholars in African philosophy tend to give different characterizations of the African. This paper is an attempt to explicate the Africaness that has been so taken for granted in African philosophy. It explores the different African identities that have been constructed in the course of African philosophy in a bid to determine whether any of such identities is authentically African. Of Literature and Identity An introduction to African philosophy usually starts with what has now become a perennial question concerning the existence of African philosophy and its peculiarities as a unique trend in philosophy. The answer to this question, though many and varied is ultimately been reduced to the four trends identified by Odera Oruka, viz. ethnophilosophy, philosophic sagacity, nationalistic ideological philosophy and professional philosophy. In all these various trends, reference is consistently made to Africa and the African and there is an assumption that these concepts are clearly understood by those participating in the debate and their audience. But whereas, as a geographical concept, Africa is quite easy to define and demarcate, the same cannot be said about African as an identity concept and the disparity in African identities used in philosophical literature makes this apparent. But the confusion is not limited to African philosophy. The same question has been posed at different times in the popular press, 2 prompting the further 2 Diallo, Garba, Who is an African? Available online at http://www.hollerafrica.com/showarticle.php?catid=1&artid=9 accessed on March 17, 2009. Also see 2

question as to whether there is an identity crisis in Africa and if not, what truly constitutes an African identity. The African philosophical trend that is commonly referred to as ethno-philosophy is usually looked upon as portraying African philosophy as a description of communal thought. It is mirrored in the works of such scholars as Placid Temples 3, Alexis Kagamé 4, John Mbiti 5 and Robin Horton. 6 What has been identified by many commentators on African Philosophy to be common to these scholars has been their attempt to reduce African philosophy to what Hountondji refers to as a collective, spontaneous, unreflective and implicit worldviews, accepted, consciously or unconsciously, by all Africans in general or, more especially, by all the members f a particular ethnic group or a particular African society. 7 The African that is referred to in these various philosophies is usually black and a native of one of the many ethnic nationalities of sub-saharan Africa. This African is also traditional, either in the sense of being shielded from Western influence or in the sense of rejecting such influence as in the case of the évolués that first generated the interest of Temples. In more recent literature, such a concept of Africans is often abstracted from the more contemporary African through a process of projecting into a past where the African was pure and untouched by Western influence. The African of ethno-philosophy is also communal not merely by virtue of the communal nature of African traditional society but because the philosophical ideas espoused by him are communal both by origin and by letter. This African is also illiterate and therefore cannot document his own thoughts but even if he were, literacy would not have made much difference to his outlook. This African is also unreflective and merely mouths the dogmas of society without subjecting it to ratiocination but rather accepting the absoluteness of such dogmas. He is also intellectually unconscious in the sense alluded to by Temples when he says, we do not claim, of course, that the Bantu are capable of formulating a Vandu, Chippla, On white Africans available online at http://www.thenewblackmagazine.com/view.aspx?index=401 accessed on March 17, 2009 3 Temples, P. Bantu Philosophy, Paris: Presence Africaine, 1959, 4 Kagamé, A. La Philosophie Bantou-Rwandaise de L être 5 Mbiti, J. M. African Religions and Philosophy 6 Horton, R. African Traditional Thought and Western Science in Patterns of thought in Africa and the West : essays on magic, religion and science, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1998 7 Hountondji, Paulin. Op.cit., p.101 3

philosophical treaties, complete with an adequate vocabulary. It is our job to proceed to such a systematic development. It is we who will be able to tell them, in précised terms, what their inmost concept of being is. They will recognize themselves in our words... 8 Another trend in African philosophy that is close to ethno-philosophy was developed by Odera Oruka and is commonly referred to as philosophical sagacity. It came as a reaction to Hountondji s insistence that writing is a prerequisite for philosophy and Oruka s belief that literacy is not a necessary condition for philosophical thought. It is different from ethno-philosophy in the sense that it is non-holistic but rather consists in the thought of individual philosophic sages who are rationally critical and who recommend as far as communal pressure allows, only those aspects of beliefs and values that pass their rational scrutiny. 9 This is without prejudice to the existence of folk sages whom he identifies as being well versed in the common-place culture, customs and beliefs of his people. Like ethno-philosophy, this trend in African philosophy also defines the African in peculiar but interesting ways. Like the African in ethno-philosophy, the African of philosophical sagacity is black and also a native of one of the many ethnic nationalities of sub-saharan Africa. This African is also traditional, not in the sense that they have not been influenced by the inevitable moral and technological culture from the West but because their own outlook and cultural well-being remains that of traditional Africa. 10 This African is illiterate, not merely because of some historical accident that left Africans without a writing culture, but also because the absence of writing is celebrated and held to contribute some uniqueness to the philosophy. The African of philosophic sagacity though living in a communal society does not subscribe to communal thought but is individualistic and didactic in his thought. He is intellectually conscious and capable of moving beyond the first-order level of philosophical enquiry to the second-order level that involves critiquing the popular wisdom of his community. His intellectual consciousness notwithstanding, this African, while incapable of documenting his own thought is capable of formulating philosophical treaties as well as recognizing the systematic presentation of the philosophical ideas of others. 8 Temples, Placides, Bantu Philosophy, Paris: Presence Africaine, 1959, p25 9 Oruka, H. Odera, Sage Philosophy, Leiden: E. J. Brill, 1990, p. 31 10 Ibid. p.28 4

Oruka also identifies nationalist-ideological philosophy as a trend in African philosophy and consists in the attempt by African nationalist such as Kwame Nkrumah, Julius Nyerere Leopold Senghor and others to abstract a unique political theory from traditional African cultures. It flows from the belief that traditional Africa has something unique to offer the contemporary world and that if contemporary Africa is organized following the traditional and sometimes communal model, it could avoid some of the pitfalls of contemporary Western and Eastern societies. Although traditional Africa plays an important role in this philosophical trend, there appears to be an acceptance that contemporary society is evolving and is no longer traditional. This notwithstanding, the African identity constructed in this philosophical trend is still black and native to one of the ethnic nationalities of sub-saharan Africa. It does not appear to include the black African Diaspora even when African scholars in the Diaspora have been active in articulating these theories. The interventionist tone of nationalistic-ideological philosophy and its commitment to restoring Africa to its communal past, seem to suggestion that the African of this philosophical trend is no longer traditional nor is he communal. The articulation of this philosophy and the process through which its objectives are to be achieved suggests that the African of this philosophical trend is at least functionally literate and therefore capable of appreciating the philosophy. He I also reflective, in the sense of being able to compare the philosophical ideal of the new ideology to his current muddled existence that resulted from the incorporation of Western and Eastern ideals into the polity. The African of this philosophical trend is expected to possess the philosophical sophistication of the sage and be adept in joggling the values of traditional Africa with the needs of a modern nation-state. To this end, he not only expected to be well grounded in the traditions of Africa but also sufficiently familiar with the workings of a modern nation-state. The fourth trend in African philosophy is identified by Oruka as professional philosophy and its proponents consist chiefly of Peter Boudunrin, Paulin Hountondji, Kwasi Wiredu, and Odera Oruka. It conceives of African philosophy as contemporary philosophy done by Africans that have received professional training in philosophy. According to Peter 5

Bodunrin, it is the philosophy done by African philosophers whether it be in the area of logic, metaphysics, ethics or history of philosophy. 11 Although Bodunrin mentions the desirability of some sort of African context in the philosophy, such a context is not necessary and therefore does not define the philosophy. Hountondji thus argues that the defining criterion for African Philosophy is the geographical origin of its authors, rather than an alleged specificity of its content. 12 Although the above seems to suggest that being an African is simply a matter of being born in Africa, the stated purpose of defining an African by geography, viz., demystifying Africanity, by reducing it to fact simply the fact, and in itself, perfectly neutral, of belonging to Africa by removing the mystic halo of values arbitrarily grafted upon this fact by ideologists of African identity, 13 suggest that there is more to the African identity. On closer examination, the African in this trend is in reality black and a member of one of the ethnic nationalities of sub- Saharan Africa; it is not clear that Africans in the Diaspora are included in this definition. This African is not only literate but trained in the philosophical traditions of the West and therefore highly skilled in the art of argumentation and criticism. He is individualistic in his approach to knowledge and reflective in his philosophical musings. The only difference between him and his Western counterpart appears to be his tribal origins and his black skin. Although these variations in what it means to be African have been adopted by the different trends in African philosophy, the different identities could be said to be variations of two competing identities. On the one hand, an African identity that is constructed by Western anthropologist based on their interaction with Africans during the colonial era or some period prior to it. This African is traditional and black, untainted by western influences and usually a member of the one of the ethnic nationalities of sub- Saharan Africa. He is also illiterate but though he lives in a purely communal society may not necessarily be communal in thought. He is more likely to be unreflective and to merely mouths the dogmas of society without subjecting them to ratiocination but even if he is, such reflection would be basic and therefore devoid of the sophistication that is the 11 Bodunrin, Peter, The Question of African Philosophy, Philosophy vol. 56, 1981 p.162 12 Hountondji, Op.cit., p.66 13 Hountondji, Op.cit. p.xii 6

hallmark of contemporary philosophical thought. He is intellectually unconscious but even where he is intellectually conscious, he is still be incapable of formulating philosophical treaties and documenting same independent of an interlocutor. On the other hand, there is a second identity of the African that is more contemporary and is an amalgam of the African referred to in the nationalist-ideological philosophy and the African of professional philosophy. The identity here is a more recent construct and as such the African is no longer traditional, but may need to be sufficiently familiar with African traditions. He is however still black, and has traceable roots to one of the ethnic nationalities of sub-saharan Africa. He is often highly educated or at least sufficiently literate to understand and reflect upon theoretical ideals and their application to contemporary life. Where he lacks philosophical training, a distinct philosophical streak usually makes up for this and imbues him with peculiar insights into issues and processes that govern everyday existence. In short, the distinction between the two identities is basically the distinction between the traditional and the modern and the question that arises is as to which is the authentic African identity. Of Africans and Identity Debates concerning the true African identity are not new but have been part of the literary corpus on Africans for over a century. From the pre-logical identities of the early anthropologists through the noble savage of Rousseau, the African identity has been constructed and reconstructed over time, with the identities constructed in the course of the debate on African philosophy being part of this trend. There has been however, a growing tendency to regard these different African identities as mythical constructions. Blyden for instance observes, The Negro of the ordinary traveler or missionary and perhaps, of twothirds of the Christian world is a purely fictitious being, constructed out of the traditions of slave-traders and slave-holders, who have circulated all sorts of absurd stories, and also out of prejudice inherited from ancestors, who were taught to regard them as a legitimate object of traffic. 14 Although Blyden was not commenting on any of the identities constructed in the course of African philosophy, the identity he referred to is similar to the identity of the 14 Blyden, E. W., Christianity, Islam and the Negro Race, London: Edinburgh University Press, 1967, p58 7

traditional African constructed in ethno-philosophy and could therefore be said to be an indictment of it. Since all identities are constructions, the challenge has been to find a constructed identity that is sufficiently authentic and therefore acceptable as representative of the African. There is a sense in which talk of an authentic African identity could be said to be premature and therefore inappropriate at this time in history. Chinua Achebe for instance, in his musings concerning the several identities that has been subject observes; It is, of course true that the African identity is still in the making. There isn t a final identity that is African. But, at the same time, there is an identity that is coming into existence 15 His reason for this is that it is not entirely clear what it means to be an African, since different people associate different penalties and responsibilities to this tag. African-ness is therefore something that needs to be explored, discovered and most probably transmuted into something that will be sufficiently representative and of which the African will be comfortable. In defending Achebe s view, Appiah argues that the African identity is a new thing; that it is a product of history ; and that the basis through which so far it has largely been theorized race, a common historical experience, a shared metaphysics presuppose falsehoods too serious for us to ignore. 16 Appiah s position appears to rest on three basic assumptions. First, that identity ought to be something that is consciously held and since the people that we now refer to as Africans have never been conscious of having a common identity prior to colonization, whatever is touted as an African identity should not predate colonization. Second, that the variety of cultures and the variety of colonial experiences have resulted in differences that are not easy to overcome and that it is in the overcoming of these differences that an African identity is being constructed. Third, that the different African identities constructed in the course of interaction with the West are at best useless falsehoods and at worst dangerous falsehoods which should not be countenanced in developing an African identity. 15 Achebe, Chinua A., Interview, quoted in Kwame Anthony Appiah, In my Father s House: Africa in the Philosophy of Culture, Oxford: University Press, 1992, p173. 16 Appiah, Kwame Anthony, In my Father s House: Africa in the Philosophy of Culture, Oxford: University Press, 1992, p174. 8

The above assumptions raise several issues concerning collective identity and its construction. The first is whether or not a collective has to be conscious of itself as a collective or, at least of having common properties before it can be credited with a certain identity or for its identity to be authentic. Also, who determines the identity of a collective? Is it the collective itself or can a collective be credited with an identity of which it is unaware? There is still the question as to what it means for an identity to be authentic and whether such an identity can ever be constructed. The answers to these questions not only respond to the above assumptions by Appiah but also contribute to our understanding of the African identity. In his evaluation of different African identities, Appiah seems to suggest that identities ought to be constructed by the referent group and exported to others, and as such the group should not only be cohesive but also be conscious of itself as a homogeneous unit. This is despite acknowledging Achebe s view that one can possess an identity of which one is not conscious and can suffer the penalties of such an identity over time before becoming conscious of and sometimes embracing the identity. Also, Appiah seems to suggest that sharing an identity entails the absence of differences within the identity group or at least, the consciousness of a collective determination by members of the group to overcome such differences. Again, Appiahs position seems to suggest that an authentic identity need to be completely devoid of falsehood and that such an identity needs to be consciously constructed. This is despite acknowledging that identities are the products of histories, some of which are useless falsehoods ; an acknowledgement that is not only true of constructed African identities but of all constructed identities. In contrast to Appiah, Masolo argues that identities of persons are determined biologically and socially, by some assumed homogeneous characteristics which they share with other members of the group to which they belong. 17 This suggests that even such useless falsehoods as race and national histories could legitimately feature in the 17 Masolo, D. A., From Village to Global contexts: Ideas, Types and the Making of Communities in Philip Anderson (ed.) Diversity and Community, Oxford: Blackwells, 2002, p88 9

construction of identities. Again, since dominant identities are formed almost solely by exclusion 18 and the exclusion may be made both by those to whom the identity refers or by others, we cannot escape the possibility of having falsehood incorporated into identities. Also, it appears reasonable to assume that where identities are constructed by those other than them that the identity refers, the referent group need not be conscious of its homogeneity nor is it necessary for the homogeneity to be factual. Again, since the construction of an identity, whether by the referent group or by outsiders, usually serves a purpose outside the constructed identity, it cannot be completely free of falsehood, since the underlying circumstance in the construction of the identity, in other words its history, can only be a perspective of actual events. What this means is that no constructed identity can be completely free of falsehood since the construction of an identity necessarily involves emphasis on certain features of the group and the suppression of others in order to make the identity either flattering or pejorative. This is without prejudice to the fact that a constructed identity, whether flattering or pejorative could be completely false. Of Identities and the Authentic There is still the question as to what it means for an identity to be authentic and whether such an authentic identity could ever be constructed. It is a question that confronts the African, not only in view of the problems that Appiah identifies with the African identity but also in view of the conflicting African identities constructed in the course of African philosophy. An identity could be said to be authentic if it is worthy of acceptance or belief as conforming to or based on fact. 19 An African identity would therefore be authentic if it depict the true African and portray an image of the African that is based on facts about the African and therefore acceptable as a sufficiently representative of the African. But here, the problem confronts us anew. First, it is not clear what facts about the African sufficiently represent the African and is therefore worthy of incorporation into the African identity. Secondly, it is not clear who should authenticate the representative character of such facts. In considering this, we have to be conscious of 18 Sartwell, Crispin, Community at the Margin in Philip Anderson (ed.) Diversity and Community, Oxford: Blackwells, 2002, p49 19 Merriam-Webster Online Dictionary http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/authentic accessed 11/04/09. 10

Heidegger s 20 caution against the inauthenticity that arises from our passive and uncritical acceptance of identities constructed from the unnoticed forces of the cultures in which we live. In other words, we should avoid defining an authentic African identity from the inauthenticity imposed on us by culture. It is perhaps this caution against inauthenticity that Appiah heeded in trying to construct an African identity that is a rational choice of the African rather than the product of race, histories, nationalities, and shared metaphysics. His concept of the African identity appears to emphasize what the African identity ought to be in a world where every identity has its rewards and penalties. But even if we heed Heidegger s caution against inauthenticity, an authentic African identity would still be elusive, since Heidegger acknowledges that some degree of inauthenticity is unavoidable in view of the fact that the critical assessment of values presupposes the uncritical acceptance of the values upon which the critical assessment is based. What this seems to suggest is that an authentic identity is an ideal, towards which the construction of every identity ought to aim. This means not only that an authentic identity cannot be constructed but also that what constitutes the authentic is for ever changing in response to new insights as to what the authentic ought to be. By this view, it is not only true that an authentic African identity is in the making but also that it will always remain in the making as it responds to new inauthenticities and their accompanying rewards and penalties. It follows from the nature of identities that an African identity can neither be authentic nor homogeneous. It is neither the traditional identity of ethno-philosophy and philosophic sagacity nor the modern identity of professional philosophy and nationalistic ideological philosophy but is rather an ideal to which none of these identities has ever, or will ever be constructed to conform. It is not an identity that can be clearly constructed or articulated but rather an ideal that will continue to mutate in response to new inauthenticities that define the world from time to time. 20 Heidegger, M., Being and Time New York:Harper & Row, 1962. 11