Possible Ramifications for Superiority

Similar documents
! Japanese: a wh-in-situ language. ! Taroo-ga [ DP. ! Taroo-ga [ CP. ! Wh-words don t move. Islands don t matter.

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Islands. Wh-islands. Phases. Complex Noun Phrase islands. Adjunct islands

Diagnosing covert pied-piping *

Research Seminar The syntax and semantics of questions Spring 1999 January 26, 1999 Week 1: Questions and typologies

1 Pair-list readings and single pair readings

The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT. How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement?

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

17. Semantics in L1A

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope

Sentence Processing III. LIGN 170, Lecture 8

When data collide: Traditional judgments vs. formal experiments in sentence acceptability Grant Goodall UC San Diego

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions

Answering negative questions in American Sign Language

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

To: Joint Steering Committee for Development of RDA. From: Damian Iseminger, Chair, JSC Music Working Group

Sense and soundness of thought as a biochemical process Mahmoud A. Mansour

Non-Reducibility with Knowledge wh: Experimental Investigations

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

The Interpretation of the Logophoric Pronoun in Ewe Hazel Pearson. The distribution of the logophoric pronoun yè in Ewe is as follows:

Vagueness & Pragmatics

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Industry view on C-band related WRC-15 agenda items (i.e. AI 1.1 and 9.1-5) ATU/ITU Radiocommunications Forum (24 April, 2015 Niamey Niger)

Automatic Projector Tilt Compensation System

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

LNGT 0250 Morphology and Syntax

1. PSEUDO-IMPERATIVES IN ENGLISH Characterization.

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

The ambiguity of definite descriptions

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

1 The structure of this exercise

Chapter 3 Sluicing. 3.1 Introduction to wh-fragments. Chapter 3 Sluicing in An Automodular View of Ellipsis

CURIE Day 3: Frequency Domain Images

Ling 720 Implicit Arguments, Week 11 Barbara H. Partee, Nov 25, 2009

Vowel sets: a reply to Kaye 1

Recap: Roots, inflection, and head-movement

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Usage of provenance : A Tower of Babel Towards a concept map Position paper for the Life Cycle Seminar, Mountain View, July 10, 2006

Faculty Governance Minutes A Compilation for online version

HDR A Guide to High Dynamic Range Operation for Live Broadcast Applications Klaus Weber, Principal Camera Solutions & Technology, April 2018

Replies to the Critics

Handout 3 Verb Phrases: Types of modifier. Modifier Maximality Principle Non-head constituents are maximal projections, i.e., phrases (XPs).

Rhetorical Structure Theory

Cyclic vs. circular argumentation in the Conceptual Metaphor Theory ANDRÁS KERTÉSZ CSILLA RÁKOSI* In: Cognitive Linguistics 20-4 (2009),

Analysis of MPEG-2 Video Streams

Or what? Or what?: Challenging the speaker. NELS 46, Concordia. Or what questions are strategies for re-asking a big question.

Aristotle on the Human Good

Algorithmic Music Composition

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

11. SUMMARY OF THE BASIC QUANTIFIER TRANSLATION PATTERNS SO FAR EXAMINED

Singular Propositions, Abstract Constituents, and Propositional Attitudes

February 16, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977

I-language Chapter 8: Anaphor Binding

Scientific Philosophy

Material and Formal Fallacies. from Aristotle s On Sophistical Refutations

LOGICO-SEMANTIC ASPECTS OF TRUTHFULNESS

Region Adaptive Unsharp Masking based DCT Interpolation for Efficient Video Intra Frame Up-sampling

Errata Carnie, Andrew (2013) Syntax: A Generative Introduction. 3 rd edition. Wiley Blackwell. Last updated March 29, 2015

Emergence of Cooperation Through Mutual Preference Revision

The Language of First-Order Predicate Logic

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Return Loss (RL), Effective Return Loss (ERL), and COM Variations

7. The English Caused-Motion Construction. Presenter: 林岱瑩

The critique of iconicity: the Bierman-Goodman connection. Made by : Agata Ziemba Patrycja Ziętek Bartłomiej Ziomek Michał Szymanek

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1

Rhetorical Questions and Scales

Speaker s Meaning, Speech Acts, Topic and Focus, Questions

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Re-appraising the role of alternations in construction grammar: the case of the conative construction

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Sidestepping the holes of holism

COMPUTER ENGINEERING PROGRAM

Meaning 1. Semantics is concerned with the literal meaning of sentences of a language.

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

CAS LX 523 Syntax II Spring 2001 April 17, 2001

HDR A Guide to High Dynamic Range Operation for Live Broadcast Applications Klaus Weber, Principal Camera Solutions & Technology, December 2018

Learning fun with.

Fragments within Islands

PERSONAL SERVANT LEADERSHIP POLARITY SCALE

6.034 Notes: Section 4.1

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

ACT-R ACT-R. Core Components of the Architecture. Core Commitments of the Theory. Chunks. Modules

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Revitalising Old Thoughts: Class diagrams in light of the early Wittgenstein

IF MONTY HALL FALLS OR CRAWLS

Respective Answers to Coordinated Questions

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

Transcription:

1 Possible Ramifications for Superiority 1. Superiority up to semantic equivalence (Golan 1993) (1) Who knows what who bought? (Lasnik and Saito 1992) Good but only when em Attract Closest bedded who receives matrix scope Golan s Interpretation: what can move over who in the embedded clause because that is the only way for who to receive matrix scope. Semantic Sensitive version of Attract Closest (SSSM): C uwh must attract the closest whphrase it can to derive a designated semantic interpretation. Can SSSM account for (the D-linking) exception to Superiority? The answer would be yes if it turned out that superiority violations end up having different semantic interpretations (and if that difference depended on D-linking). 2. A possible source for different semantic interpretations 2.1. Dayal on uniqueness and its obviation in multiple wh questions (2) Which boy came to the party? Presupposes: exactly one boy came to the party. #I know which boy came to the party; John and Bill came to the party. (3) Which boy read which book? Two readings: Single Pair: I know which boy read which book; John read war and Peace. Pair List I know which boy read which book; John read war and Peace; Bill read BK 2.2. An argument for a genuine ambiguity (restriction on Pair list): When lists are given they must be exhausted: in other words, there are two options a single pair or an exhaustive list. No intermediate options are allowed. (4) a. Guess which one of these 3 kids will sit on which of these 4 chairs b. Guess which one of these 4 kids will sit on which of these 3 chairs (4)b is good only if there is a single pair as an answer (or if two kids will end up sitting on the same chair). Conclusion: There is a genuine ambiguity. The pair list reading presupposes Exhaustivity (that every member of the set quantified over by the overtly moved wh-phrase is paired with a member of the set quantified over by the in-situ wh-phrase), a presupposition

2 which does not hold when a single pair serves as the answer. Reading 1: presupposes that there is only a single pair as an answer to the question. Reading 2: presupposes that there are exactly as many pairs and there are elements in the domain of quantification for the first whp. (a consequence of exahustivity and point-wise uniqueness). 2.3. A possible source for different semantic interpretations The nature of the exahaustivity and uniqueness presuppositions depends on which whphrase moves overtly. Hence, violation of superiority is predicted to yield different presupposition. (5) a. Guess which one of these 4 kids will sit on which one of these 3 chairs. Good only if there is a single pair as an answer. b. Guess which one of these 3 chairs which one of these 4 kids will sit on. Good on a pair list answer. (6) a. *Except For War and Peace I know which boy read which book. b. Except for War and Peace I know which book which boy read. (7) a. Except For John I know which boy read which book. b. *Except for John I know which book which boy read. (8) a. I would like to know which resolution(s) Scott Brown voted for. (?)In fact, in every case I would like to know which senator voted for which resolution(s). b. I would like to know which senator(s) voted for resolution 380. (*)In fact, in every case I would like to know which senator(s) voted for which resolution. c. I would like to know which senator(s) voted for resolution 380. (?)In fact, in every case I would like to know which resolution which senator(s) voted for. Prediction: violation of superiority should be impossible on a single pair reading. 1 I think this might very well be right. 1 This prediction seem to hold for German (Wiltschko 1997). Irene Heim pointed out an odd property of the current proposal, namely that it makes English and German out to be identical, contrary to what is usually assumed. If the proposal made here is correct, the only difference between English and German would be in the ease of getting a pair-list reading for multiple wh-questions (a reading that obviates superiority).

3 (9) My two kids are fighting: Who hit who first? *Who did who hit first? (10) a. I know which boy read which book. John read War and Peace b. I know which boy read which book. John read War and Peace, Bill read BK c. *I know which book which boy read. War and Peace was read by John/John read W&P. d. I know which book which boy read. War and Peace was read by John, BK was read by Bill (11) a. I know which one of my students wrote which one of these papers before any other student wrote any other paper. b. *I know which one of these papers which one of my students wrote before any other student wrote any other paper. (12) a. Guess which one of these 4 kids will sit on which one of these 3 chairs. Good only if there is a single pair as an answer. b. (#)Guess which one of these 4 chairs which one of these 3 kids will sit on. (13) a. A certain boy read a certain book. I wish I knew which boy read which book. b. A certain boy read a certain book. #I wish I knew which book which boy read. (14) a. There is a boy in that room reading a book. I wish I knew which boy is reading which book. b. There is a book in that room that the teacher is reading to a boy. I wish I knew which book the teacher is reading to which boy. c. There is a book in that room that a boy is reading. (#)I wish I knew which book which boy is reading. 3. A Golan type account of Superiority violations Assume that wh 1 c-commands wh 2 prior to wh-movement Moving wh 2 overtly over wh 1 is possible on the pair list reading because it yields different presuppositions than what we would get if we moved wh1 overtly (hence licensed by SSSM). For concreteness, let s assume question have Hamblin denotations (i.e. they denote sets of propositions or families of such sets, etc.). We would now say that two question LFs Q and Q are equivalent if w w' Ans([[Q]])(w')(w) = Ans([[Q']])(w')(w)

4 Superiority would state that moving wh 2 overtly over wh 1 is ruled out whenever the result is equivalent to what we would get by moving wh 1 overtly. Possible approach to D-linking: Contextual assumptions must allow for two presuppositions to be met (exhaustivity and point-wise uniqueness). The universal exhaustivity presupposition can (realistically) be satisfied only if the domain that the overtly moved wh phrase quantifies over is somehow familiar (familiar enough to have presuppositions about). We thus derive something close to D-linking for the overtly moved wh-p. Should the domain of the in-situ wh-p be familiar? Yes. Well at least enough for pointwise uniqueness to be grounded. [For related discussion, see Comorovski 1989, Kiss 1993, Miyagawa 2001, 2005, and Yoshida 2012.] 4. Problem: the constraint on crossing dependencies? (15)a.??[Which book] 1 did you ask who 2 Mary told t 2 [PRO to present t 1 ]? b. *[Which person] 1 did you ask what 2 Mary told t 1 [PRO to present t 2 ]? (16)a. This is the violin wh 1 that I wonder which sonatas 2 to play t 2 on t 1. b. *These are the sonatas wh 1 that I wonder which violin to play t 2 on. It seems that SSSM should not block moving wh2 over wh1 in the embedded clause because that would yield a different interpretation globally. 5. Possible modifications Strategy: keep to the standard (semantically insensitive) formulation of attract closest and introduce a semantically sensitive condition which will affect the consequences of attract closest in cases that involve two wh phrases in spec of the same CP. 5.1. Version One with tucking-in Internal merge (can sometimes not extend the tree feature cyclicity) Four Additional Assumptions 1. Attract Closest receives the traditional formal definition, which is semantically insensitive. (17)Attract Closest: C int must attract the/a closest wh-phrase that has not already checked off a wh-feature on C. 2. Shortest move -- the tucking-in requirement -- is semantically sensitive: (18)Semantically Sensitive Shortest move: A moved wh-phrase must tuck-in below

5 another wh phrase, unless non-tucking in yields a different interpretation (at the end of the day). 3. Whether movement is overt or covert in English depends on the following principle: (19)Chain Pronounciation in English: A head of a chain is pronounced if it is an outerspecifier of an extended projection. Otherwise the tail of the chain is pronounced. (Pesetsky 2001, see also F&P 2010 handout http://web.mit.edu/linguistics/people/faculty/fox/ben-gurion-7-09.pdf). 4. If a chain is pronounced in a trace position, further movement cannot change the verdict (i.e. overt wh-movement of covertly moved wh phrases is impossible). 5.2. Going Through the various cases: Let s start with a C int that has two whps in its scope and must attract at least one (i.e. is interpreted as a question and has an uninterpretable wh feature). C will attract the higher whp (wh 1 ) by attract closest 2 wh 1 C uwh wh 1 wh 2 Then three possibilities need to be considered 1. Do nothing: wh 1 C wh 1 wh 2 (lower position deleted) 2. Tuck-in wh 2 (allowed by SSSM, no matter what) wh 1 wh 2 C wh 1 wh 2 (lower position is deleted at PF for wh 1 ; higher position is deleted for wh 2 ) 3. Extend tree with wh 2 (allowed by SSSM if it yields a different interpretation than what could be derived from 2) wh 2 wh 1 C wh 1 wh 2 (lower position is deleted for wh 2 higher position is deleted for wh 1 ) 3 is what we call a superiority violation and it is allowed if it receives an interpretation that cannot be derived by 2. Two Scenarios to consider #1 The CP we are constructing is interpreted as a multiple wh question. 3 and 2 would have different interpretations only if we have a pair list interpretation for both (which, in turn, requires the two whps to be D-linked). The two pair list interpretations as we have seen are different. #2 The CP we are constructing is interpreted as a single wh question. It is embedded 2 If a highest whp exists. Otherwise more than one whp is a legitimate attractee.

6 under another CP and one of the wh phrases has wider scope. A different interpretation will be made possible by 3 only if wh 2 stays where it is and wh 1 has wider scope. But wh 1 cannot move overtly from Spec CP because there are no phonological features there this position has been deleted (assumption 4). Hence it must move covertly as in L&S s example in (1). 5.2. Version 2 no tucking in (based on conversations with David) Merge (internal and external) must extend the tree Four Additional Assumptions 1. Attract Closest receives a new definition, which cares about only one instance of movement, and in addition is semantically insensitive. (20)Attract Closest: C int must attract one wh-phrase which is closer to it than any other phrase. 2. Apology principle -- the tucking-in requirement -- is semantically sensitive: (21)Semantically Sensitive Apology: When C int attracts multiple wh-phrase its outer specifier (the last instance of movement) must be the closest attractee, unless a different choice yields a different interpretation. 3. Whether movement is overt or covert in English depends on the following principle: (22)Chain Pronounciation in English: A head of a chain is pronounced if it is an outerspecifier of an extended projection. Otherwise the tail of the chain is pronounced. 4. If a chain is pronounced in a trace position, further movement cannot change the verdict (i.e. overt wh-movement of covertly moved wh phrases is impossible). 6. Superiority and Pair list readings (23) a. What did every boy read? (pair list available) b. Who read every book? (pair list unavailable) Could this follow from superiority? Yes, if the condition has no exception for different semantic interpretation: A-bar movement to the extended projection of C must preserve c-command relations from A positions. Possible Prediction (based on the Bulgarian pattern): (24) a. I know which girl you told a story about Plato, and which girl you told a story about Socrates

7 b. #In fact I know which girl you told a story about EVERY philosopher. a. I know which girl Bill told a story about Plato, and which girl Fred told a story about Socrates b. (#) In fact I know which girl EVERY boy told a story about EVERY philosopher. Assuming we want Superiority to derive the constraints on pair list readings, what do we do? 7. Third Version (Pesetsky 2001 Meets Golan based on Conversation with Hadas Kotek) Superiority is not semantically sensitive. Possible implementation (always extending tree) 1. Attract Closest receives a new definition, which cares about only one instance of movement, and in addition is semantically insensitive. (25)Attract Closest: C int must attract one wh-phrase which is closer to it than any other wh-phrase 2. Apology principle -- the tucking-in requirement -- is also semantically insensitive: (26)Semantically insensitive Apology: When C int attracts multiple wh-phrase its outer specifier (the last instance of movement) must be the closest attractee, unless a different choice yields a different interpretation. What is semantically sensitive is the principle that tells us which apparent whphrases are real wh-phrases 3. Every wh phrase can be marked as a non-candidate for movement if this marking yields a different semantic interpretation. 4. Whether movement is overt or covert in English depends on the following principle: (27)Chain Pronounciation in English: A head of a chain is pronounced if it is an outerspecifier of an extended projection. Otherwise the tail of the chain is pronounced. (cf. F&P 2010 handout http://web.mit.edu/linguistics/people/faculty/fox/ben-gurion-7-09.pdf). 5. If a chain is pronounced in a trace position, further movement cannot change the verdict (i.e. overt wh-movement of covertly moved wh phrases is impossible).