Scientific Knowledge: Situatedness and Intersubjectivity without Standpoints

Similar documents
Feminism, Underdetermination, and Values in Science

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Lecture : 8. Science,Technology and Society. Feminist Challenges

Feminist Philosophy of Science: Values and Objectivity

Gender in the Substance of Chemistry, Part 2: An Agenda for Theory

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

What is woman s voice?: Focusing on singularity and conceptual rigor

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

Significant Differences An Interview with Elizabeth Grosz

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Literary Theory and Criticism

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

LANGAUGE AND LITERATURE EUROPEAN LANDMARKS OF IDENTITY (ELI) GENERAL PRESENTATION OF ELI EDITORIAL POLICY

What is Science? What is the purpose of science? What is the relationship between science and social theory?

M. Chirimuuta s Adverbialism About Color. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. I. Color Adverbialism

References DOI: /

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Historical/Biographical

FEMINIST EPISTEMOLOGY AND THE SEARCH FOR LIBERATING KNOWLEDGE

Biology, Self and Culture. From Different Perspectives

Journal for contemporary philosophy

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

Philip Joseph Kain. Santa Clara University Scotts Valley, CA Santa Clara, CA fax

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Introduced Reinforced Practiced Proficient and Assessed. IGS 200: The Ancient World

Literary Theory and Criticism

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Feminist Research and Paradigm Shift in Anthropology

24.502: Topics in Metaphysics and Ethics Spring 2012: Social Structure: What? How? Why?

Normative and Positive Economics

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

"Strong Objectivity" and Socially Situated Knowledge

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

The following seminars will be offered during Fall semester 2017:

Guidelines for Manuscript Preparation for Advanced Biomedical Engineering

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Japan Library Association

Investigating subjectivity

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

t< k '" a.-j w~lp4t..

PHIL/HPS Philosophy of Science Fall 2014

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Learning Approaches. What We Will Cover in This Section. Overview

Yinyang and Dao. Yi Jing (I Ching) Taiji (Taichi) Yinyang

Giuliana Garzone and Peter Mead

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Expertise and the formation of university museum collections

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Publishing India Group

Approaching Aesthetics on User Interface and Interaction Design

GENERAL WRITING FORMAT

But, if I understood well, Michael Ruse doesn t agree with you. Why?

Comparative Literature: Theory, Method, Application Steven Totosy de Zepetnek (Rodopi:

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

If Leadership Were a Purely Rational Act We Would be Teaching Computers. Chester J. Bowling, Ph.D. Ohio State University Extension

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

Defending a Risk Account of Scientific Objectivity

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Acceptance of a paper for publication is based on the recommendations of two anonymous reviewers.

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Blindness as a challenging voice to stigma. Elia Charidi, Panteion University, Athens

Best Practice. for. Peer Review of Scholarly Books

Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Ideological and Political Education Under the Perspective of Receptive Aesthetics Jie Zhang, Weifang Zhong

The Unlevel Knowing Field: An Engagement with Dotson s Third-Order Epistemic Oppression Alison Bailey, Illinois State University

Architecture is epistemologically

Week 25 Deconstruction

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Beauvoir, The Second Sex (1949)

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Exploring the Monty Hall Problem. of mistakes, primarily because they have fewer experiences to draw from and therefore

SOC University of New Orleans. Vern Baxter University of New Orleans. University of New Orleans Syllabi.

Liberatory Knowledge and Just Social Practices. her activism. Her insights have inspired my research for the past twenty years. Recently I have been

Trying Not to Try: The Art and Science of Spontaneity by Edward Slingerland (review)

Transcription:

L&PS Logic and Philosophy of Science Vol. IX, No. 1, 2011, pp. 517-522 Scientific Knowledge: Situatedness and Intersubjectivity without Standpoints Maria Cristina Amoretti University of Genoa, Italy e-mail: cristina.amoretti@unige.it Nicla Vassallo University of Genoa, Italy e-mail: nicla.vassallo@unige.it 1. Introduction 2. On standpoints 3. Without standpoints ABSTRACT. We have already argued not only that essentialism is detrimental for epistemologies and philosophies of sciences, as well as sciences themselves, but also that feminist standpoint epistemologies of sciences inevitably yield essentialism, or at least its undesirable consequences (Amoretti and Vassallo 2010a, 2011, forthcoming). Although abandoning feminist standpoint epistemologies seems to represent the straightforward solution, matters are more complicated. Some of the tenets of these epistemologies, in fact, can hardly be disregarded, such as those underlying the situatedness and intersubjectivity of scientific knowledge. Thus, the specific aim of this paper is showing that it is still possible to retain the above characteristics namely situatedness and intersubjectivity even while rejecting the very notion of standpoint. 1. Introduction Elsewhere, we have extensively argued not only that essentialism is detrimental for epistemologies of sciences, philosophies of sciences, and sciences themselves, but also that feminist standpoint epistemologies of sciences inevitably yield essentialism, or at least its undesirable consequences (Amoretti The Authors 2011. Published by L&PS Logic and Philosophy of Science http://www2.units.it/~episteme ISSN: 1826-1043

AMORETTI MARIA CRISTINA, VASSALLO NICLA and Vassallo 2010a, 2011, forthcoming). Although abandoning feminist standpoint epistemologies of sciences seems to represent the best solution, matters are not so straightforward. Some of the tenets of these epistemologies, in fact, can hardly be disregarded, such as the tenets underlying the situatedness and intersubjectivity of scientific knowledge. Thus, one should first establish whether it is still possible to retain the above characteristics even while rejecting the very notion of standpoint. 2. On Standpoints Feminist standpoint epistemologies of sciences place their emphasis on the situatedness of scientific knowledge: our understanding of the natural and/or social world also depend on our specific perspective on it. More precisely, these epistemologies underlie the significance of our particular social location in modeling, not only our epistemic point of view as subjects of knowledge but also our own objects of knowledge; in other words, they point out that the dichotomy between the subject and object of knowledge is annihilated because they are shaped by the same social forces. 1 Overcoming the dichotomy between the subject and object of knowledge, scientists may represent the natural and/or social world in a way that is neither influenced by individual interests and prejudices nor affected by androcentric metaphors and conceptualizations of nature and/or society. To cite a famous example, Barbara McClintock has proven that by minimizing the distance between subject and object and by dedicating loving attention to the object, it is possible to establish a less dominant relationship and, therefore, to reduce the rigid separation between the two. Furthermore, feminist standpoint epistemologies of sciences hold that there is no single epistemic subject able to produce scientific knowledge independently of other epistemic subjects, and thus, they underline the pivotal role of the notion of intersubjectivity. This notion is particularly evident when we think about scientific discoveries: new hypotheses and/or scientific theories become knowledge only after they are tested, evaluated, and legitimated by a community of scientists, that is, they are legitimated intersubjectively. It is the whole scientific community (or one of its subgroups) that takes up a new hypothesis and eventually attributes to it the status of knowledge. 1 It is worth noting that maintaining the situatedness of knowledge per se does not rule out the possibility of objective knowledge, but it certainly raises new questions about the very notion of objectivity (Anderson 1995b; Tanesini 1999). 518

SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE The standpoint of women can be a valuable resource for natural and/or social sciences for at least three reasons (Potter 2007, pp. 148-151). First, if we assume such a standpoint, we may be able to identify new scientific problems and new research agendas, because these problems and research agendas drastically differ from those that appear in dominant androcentric frameworks. To put it differently, the standpoint of women may enrich the context of discovery, because adopting a different perspective on the natural and/or social world may facilitate the posing of novel questions as well the recognition of puzzles and even facts previously unseen and unconsidered. Second, because women scientists have no interest in perpetrating a sexist and androcentric description of the world, finding new approaches and experiments to test or attempt to falsify already established scientific theories is easier for them. More specifically, the standpoint of women can play a crucial role in the context of justification, contributing to the production of new scientific knowledge, or at least to finding justified hypotheses and theories as well as accounts of nature and society that are less distorted compared with those produced by dominant androcentric groups. Third, the standpoint of women may help ensure the strong objectivity of the sciences (Harding 1991, 1993). To obtain objective results i.e., results not biased by individual interests, prejudices, personal values, etc. the scientific community generally agrees to adopt particular methods and standards. Still, these methods and standards are often considered too weak to grant objectivity. However, embracing the standpoint of women may contribute to revealing widely (although perhaps unconsciously) held sexist and androcentric biases and thus to assuring the strong objectivity of the sciences. What biases? Consider, for example, biological research that scientifically strengthens sexist and androcentric stereotypes and behaviors because of distorted presumptions about women s and men s different sexual natures or cognitive psychological research that scientifically strengthens sexist and androcentric stereotypes and behaviors because of distorted presumptions about women s and men s different cognitive natures (Bleier 1984; Fausto-Sterling 2000; Fine 2010; Spanier 1995; Vassallo 2009). Unmasking these sexist and androcentric biases may be helpful not only for increasing and assessing the quality of the objectivity of scientific research but also for extending and intensifying the opportunities to comprehend the natural and/or social world. Women scientists have indeed the kind of dual vision that yields a better epistemic position both on the natural and/or social world. On the one hand, women scientists are outsiders and thus can understand their own situation in a way inaccessible to the dominant group (i.e., male scientists). On the oth- 519

AMORETTI MARIA CRISTINA, VASSALLO NICLA er hand, they are also outsiders within : because they live within the dominant framework without having any interest in perpetrating it, they can critically analyze that framework and understand it in a way that is inaccessible to the dominant group of male scientists. In other words, by discovering biases that are held by the entire scientific community, women scientists may gain less partial and more empirically adequate knowledge of the natural and/or social world. Hence, the standpoint of women may contribute to disclosing methods, models, and metaphors as well as discursive resources that, when they are sexist, androcentric, and immersed in cultural ideals of masculinity, can constrain our research and compromise a genuine understanding of the natural and/or social world. 3. Without Standpoints Given the above considerations, to evaluate whether the rejection of feminist standpoint epistemologies of sciences may or may not be a promising solution for epistemologists and philosophers of sciences, one should determine whether it is possible to save their great merits even while renouncing the very notion of standpoint. We believe it is possible, and we will now examine why. At the outset, we do not need to theorize about the notion of standpoint to prove that our scientific knowledge of the natural and/or social world is socially situated, and we do not need to belong to a specific standpoint to have a particular perspective on the natural and/or social world or to recognize perspectival biases (Campbell 1998, 2001; Longino 1989, 2001, 2006; Nelson 1990). To recognize the social dimension of scientific knowledge and to evaluate how crucial the role of intersubjectivity is in the sciences, it is sufficient to analyze real scientific practice, that is, how new scientific hypotheses and/or theories are produced, tested, and eventually accepted and justified. Today, almost all serious scientific research is in fact pursued by large panels of scientists with a variety of expertise (Amoretti and Vassallo 2010b; Hardwig 1985; Vassallo 2011). 2 If our aim is to identify new scientific problems and research agendas as well as new methods and experiments to test scientific hypotheses and/or the- 2 This fact became evident in the second half of the past century with projects such as the Manhattan Project and the Human Genome Project. 520

SCIENTIFIC KNOWLEDGE ories, we do not need the notion of standpoint; we only need to democratize the various sciences and improve the interactions within and across communities of scientists, thus allowing people with different social backgrounds, cultural traditions, and personal skills to effectively cooperate in a collective scientific endeavor (Anderson 1995a, 1995b; Longino 1990, 2001). Pluralism would be the best tool to ensure the strong objectivity of the sciences: there is no need to assume that some perspectives are more reliable, privileged or advantaged than others (as feminist standpoint epistemologies of sciences actually assume); rather, it is sufficient to recognize the epistemic authority of every possible point of view (Janack 1997). It is the very presence of various and even conflicting perspectives on the natural and/or social world that improves critical scrutiny, that contributes to the appreciation and unmasking of scientists sexist and androcentric biases, and that may eventually enhance the strong objectivity of the sciences (Amoretti 2010). Consequently, it is worth mentioning that recognizing the epistemic authority of different scientific inquirers i.e., the importance of epistemic inclusion becomes not just a moral but also an epistemic matter. 3 REFERENCES AMORETTI, M.C. (2010): Sulla Dimensione Sociale Della Conoscenza, Cassazione penale, 7-8, pp. 393-403. AMORETTI, M.C. and N. VASSALLO (2010a): Do Feminist Standpoint Epistemologies of the Sciences Answer the Charge of Essentialism?, in De Caro, M., Egidi R. (eds.), Architectures of Theoretical and Practical Knowledge, Roma: Carocci. AMORETTI, M.C. and N. VASSALLO (2010b): Piccolo trattato di epistemologia, Torino: Codice Editore. AMORETTI, M.C. and N. VASSALLO (2011): On Essentialism: Standpoint Epistemologies and Their Unavoidable Problem, in Zhou, Q. (ed.), Applied Social Science, ICASS-2011, Newark: IERI. AMORETTI, M.C. and N. VASSALLO (forthcoming): On the Independence of the Social and Situated Dimension of Scientific Knowledge from the Notion of Standpoint, in Covi, G., Wobbe, T., Knauss, S. (eds.), Genderd Ways of Knowing, Trento: FBK Press. 3 Maria Cristina Amoretti, for her own research, gratefully acknowledges financial support from the Grant POSDRU/89/1.5/S/63663. 521

AMORETTI MARIA CRISTINA, VASSALLO NICLA ANDERSON, E. (1995a): The Democratic University: The Role of Justice in the Production of Knowledge, Social Philosophy and Policy, 12, pp. 186-219. ANDERSON, E. (1995b): Knowledge, Human Interests, and Objectivity in Feminist Epistemology, Philosophical Topics, 23, pp. 27-58. BLEIER, R. (1984): Science and Gender, New York: Pergamon. CAMPBELL, R. (1998): Illusions of Paradox, Boulder: Rowman and Littlefield. CAMPBELL, R. (2001), The Bias Paradox in Feminist Epistemology, in Tuana, N., Morgen, S. (eds.), Engendering Rationalities, Albany: State University of New York Press. FAUSTO-STERLING, A. (2000): Sexing the Body, New York: Basic Books. FINE, C. (2010): Delusions of Gender, New York: Norton. HARDING, S. (1991): Whose Science? Whose Knowledge?, Ithaca: Cornell University Press. HARDING, S. (ed.) (1993): The Racial Economy of Science, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. HARDWIG, J. (1985): Epistemic Dependence, The Journal of Philosophy, 82, pp. 335-349. JANACK, M. (1997): Standpoint Epistemology without the Standpoint? An Examination of Epistemic Privilege and Epistemic Authority, Hypatia, 12, pp. 125-139. LONGINO, H.E. (1989): Can There Be a Feminist Science?, in Garry, A., Pearsall M. (eds.), Women in Knowledge and Reality, Boston: Unwin Hyman. LONGINO, H.E. (1990): Science as Social Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press. LONGINO, H.E. (2001): The Fate of Knowledge, Princeton: Princeton University Press. LONGINO, H.E. (2006): The Social Dimensions of Scientific Knowledge, in Zalta, E.N. (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (1st ed. 2002), http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/scientific-knowledge-social/. NELSON, L.H. (1990): Who Knows?, Philadelphia: Temple University Press. POTTER, E. (2007): Feminism and Philosophy of Science. London: Routledge. SPANIER, B. (1995): Im/Partial Science, Bloomington: Indiana University Press. TANESINI, A. (1999): An Introduction to Feminist Epistemology, Oxford: Blackwell. VASSALLO, N. (2009): Donna m apparve, in Vassallo, N. (ed.), Donna m apparve, Torino: Codice Edizioni. VASSALLO, N. (2011): Per sentito dire. Milano: Feltrinelli. 522