Introduction. Gloria Zúñiga y Postigo 1 Kenneth Williford

Similar documents
PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

THE POWER OF ABSTRACTION: BRENTANO, HUSSERL AND THE GÖTTINGEN STUDENTS

Investigating subjectivity

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

THE LOGICAL FORM OF BIOLOGICAL OBJECTS

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

"History of Modern Economic Thought"

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

Institute of Philosophy, Leiden University, Online publication date: 10 June 2010 PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

THE REPRESENTATIVENESS OF HOMO OECONOMICUS AND ITS RATIONALITY

CONTENTS II. THE PURE OBJECT AND ITS INDIFFERENCE TO BEING

Art, Mind and Cognitive Science

Normative and Positive Economics

observation and conceptual interpretation

Intersubjectivity and Language

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

1. What is Phenomenology?

Tishreen University Journal for Research and Scientific Studies - Arts and Humanities Series Vol. (31) No. (1) 2009.

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

APSA Methods Studio Workshop: Textual Analysis and Critical Semiotics. August 31, 2016 Matt Guardino Providence College

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

We know of the efforts of such philosophers as Frege and Husserl to undo the

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

PUBLICATIONS Book: The Science of Subjectivity. Palgrave Macmillan Press 2015

Short Course APSA 2016, Philadelphia. The Methods Studio: Workshop Textual Analysis and Critical Semiotics and Crit

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

Intersubjectivity, Subjectivism, Social Sciences, and the Austrian School of Economics

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy

Increadible Sociological Reflections On The Neurosciences Advances In Medical Sociology

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Call for Papers. Tourism Spectrum. (An International Refereed Journal) Vol. 4, No-1/2, ISSN No Special Issue on Adventure Tourism

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

History of Analytic Philosophy

Scientific Philosophy

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Logic and Formal Ontology 1

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

In retrospect: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

GRADUATE SEMINARS

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Hear hear. Århus, 11 January An acoustemological manifesto

Joona Taipale, Phenomenology and Embodiment: Husserl and the Constitution of Subjectivity

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

Phenomenology Glossary

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

Mass Communication Theory

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska

KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

A Soviet View of Structuralism, Althusser, and Foucault

1/9. The B-Deduction

Psychology. Department Location Giles Hall Room 320

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

From J. Hintikka, et al. (eds.), Philosophy and Logic: In Search of the Polish Tradition, Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster: Kluwer, 2003,

In Search of the Totality of Experience

Categories and Schemata

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Curriculum Vitae Chris A. Kramer Department of Philosophy Rock Valley College

Philosophy of Economics

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

In their respective articles in the Spring 2002 issue of International Studies

Phenomenology and Mind. Guidelines

Transcription:

Axiomathes (2017) 27:437 441 DOI 10.1007/s10516-017-9357-z Introduction Gloria Zúñiga y Postigo 1 Kenneth Williford 2 Published online: 20 September 2017 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2017 On November 2012, a group of international specialists in Austrian economics and Austrian philosophy gathered at the University of Texas at Arlington for a conference on Austrian thought. The focus was the legacy of the schools led by Franz Brentano, in philosophy, and Carl Menger, in economics, in Vienna at the turn of the twentieth century. The discussions at the conference ranged from the themes of intentionality, scarcity, social ontology, and logic to broader interdisciplinary topics in value theory, psychology, and cognitive neuroscience. These discussions were the inspiration for this volume. The contributions to this special issue of Axiomathes constitute a tapestry of the various ideas advanced by Austrian economists and philosophers and indicate something of their significance today. Although the Austrian School of economics is not well represented in presentday mainstream economics or in the growing literature on the philosophy of economics, the boundaries of this school are not difficult to describe. By contrast, Austrian philosophy is more difficult to describe or demarcate. It is not by reference to the nationality of its members, for not all were Austrian, including Brentano who was German-born. Some would argue that Austrian philosophy, as a heading, should include movements such as the Vienna Circle. However, it is the way in which Brentano and his followers did philosophy that distinguishes them from the Vienna Circle. 1 In this volume, all references to Austrian philosophy should be 1 See Eaton (1930), Grassl and Smith (1986), Gordon (1993), Smith (1995). & Gloria Zúñiga y Postigo ontogloria@gmail.com Kenneth Williford williford@uta.edu 1 2 Ashford University, San Diego, CA, USA The University of Texas at Arlington, Arlington, TX, USA

438 Axiomathes (2017) 27:437 441 understood to be the philosophy of the Brentano School, which extends to some members of the Göttingen Circle, such as Reinach. Some commentators have linked the Brentanian and Mengerian branches in Austrian thought on the basis of shared fundamental characteristics of their contributions. One common ground for the philosophers and economists in this period of Austrian thought that we present in this collection is the concern with the description (as opposed to explanation) of social experience: thinking, judging, valuing, exchanging. A prominent feature of the intellectual setting at turn of the twentieth century Vienna is the tradition of the Verstehen method for examining phenomena. This method can be understood as having three characteristics. First, its starting point is the subjective perspective of agents when examining social phenomena. Second, it employs methodological individualism in such examinations. And, third, it seeks law-like patterns of explanation in the actions of individuals. We can indeed find the concern with the phenomenon of shared experiences in the work of Menger and Brentano. Menger s aim was to discover laws of economically relevant action by seeking patterns in the day to day activities of the markets that he observed. The influence of this tradition in economics was recognized by Friedrich A. Hayek, a third-generation member of the Menger school. 2 Franz Brentano s starting point in psychology was motivated by the goal of finding pattern distinctions in different sorts of mental acts. The centrality of experience is, of course, most evident in the method of phenomenology and the examination of the lifeworld that Husserl (a student of Brentano s) advanced. Another common ground is the direction of the examinations carried out by philosophers and economists of this period, whose aim was to discover and describe the law-governed structure in each kind of social phenomenon. In the economics camp, the belief that all economic phenomena have a law-governed structure gave rise to the label Austrian economics by their rival school, the German Historical School of Economics led by Gustav von Schmoller. This label was not meant as a geographical marker of their national origin but, rather, as a badge of shame for their dissenting views with the German Historical School, the leading economists in the Continent at the time. For good or bad, the term stuck and it continues to be applied to contemporary economists across the world who are followers of this school. But it is important to recognize that, as is the case for the philosophers, the term Austrian does not refer strictly to the nationality of its members, not even for those economists in the first four generations in Austria. Consider, for example, that some economists who were members of the Austrian School were German by birth. Others were Swiss. And some, as denizens of the multinational Austro-Hungarian Empire at the turn of the twentieth century, were also Czech, Polish, Ukranian, and Croatian. Individually, each school had an impact on its respective discipline. The Austrian School of economics challenged some fundamental tenets in classical economics, especially the labor theory of value. Moreover, the contributions of Austrian economists laid out fundamental principles and concepts such as the theory of subjective economic value, marginal analysis, opportunity costs, and others that 2 See Economics and Knowledge, 52; and The Sensory Order, 8.91. See also Smith (1995, 31).

Axiomathes (2017) 27:437 441 439 ushered in a new era in economic science. Similarly, the contributions by Brentano, his students, and subsequent branches of the Brentano school, represent both an important stream of influence within and a break from what is known as Continental philosophy. Commentators in the literature of Austrian philosophy, or the Brentano School, have likened its approach to the Anglo-American philosophical direction, which it importantly influenced. 3 With the common ground that they shared, it was not surprising that the members of the Brentano and the Menger schools in Vienna engaged in a cross-pollination of ideas that enriched their investigations. At the heart of their common ground of ideas is the subject matter of value. Brentano s students, especially Christian von Ehrenfels and Alexius Meinong, not only pursued the study of value, they both attended Menger s courses and were influenced by his marginal theory. Ehrenfels was also acquainted with economist Friedrich von Wieser, who was also Menger s pupil. Another of Menger s students, economist Eugen Böhm-Bawerk, draws from the work of Brentano and of his disciple Oskar Kraus for his psychological account of time in interest-rate formation, and also cites Ehrenfels in his monumental Capital and Interest. Value was thus the springboard for examinations of the mind, aesthetics, ethics, and the development of the affective sciences. The papers in this collection are divided into two parts. Part I is titled Cognition, Logic, and Psychology. Part II is titled Praxeology, Value, and Property. Part I contains papers by Peter Simons (Trinity College, Dublin), Gregory Landini (University of Iowa), Tina Röck (University of Dundee), Maria Gyemant (Husserl Archives, Paris), and Kenneth Williford (University of Texas, Arlington). In Objects and Objectives, Dignitatives and Desideratives: Meinong s Objects of Cognition and Affect, Peter Simons argues that Alexius Meinong is one of the foremost, most independent-minded, most distinctive, most misunderstood and most unjustly maligned of all (and not just Austrian) philosophers. And he surveys Meinong s mature theory of intentionality and its objects, with particular attention to the otherwise neglected dignitatives and desideratives, which are core concepts in Meinong s theory of value. In Lessons on De Re Quantification from Russell and Meinong Gregory Landini, drawing on the famous Russell Meinong debate about non-existent objects of thought, argues that de re quantification into propositional attitudes has been wrongly conceived and that one must never bind an individual variable in the context of a propositional attitude. He goes on to show that insisting upon this restriction can help us solve contingent Liar paradoxes of propositional attitudes. In Brentano s Methodology as a Path through the Divide: On Combining Phenomenological Descriptions and Logical Analysis, Tina Röck shows how Brentano was able to integrate descriptive philosophy and logical analysis, and how this integration relates to Brentano s concept of philosophy as a rigorous science, a locution Husserl made famous. She shows how Brentano s metaphilosophy was inspired by his philosophy of science, with a special emphasis on sciences in which inductive and descriptive methods predominate (e.g., biology, geology). She contrasts Brentano s metaphilosophy with Frege s and argues that the current 3 See Smith (1995).

440 Axiomathes (2017) 27:437 441 separation of philosophy into the seemingly antithetical strands of (continental) phenomenology and analytic philosophy may be seen as a consequence of how the term rigorous science in philosophy as a rigorous science is interpreted And she concludes that Brentano s integration of descriptive and analytical methods can still provide a suitable starting point for an equally successful integration of these methods in contemporary philosophy. In Contrasting Two Ways of Making Psychology: Brentano and Freud, Maria Gyemant explores the extent to which Brentano s conceptions of psychology and consciousness influenced Sigmund Freud. She argues that [d]espite the explicit critique of the unconscious that we find in Brentano s Psychology from an Empirical Standpoint, Freud never truly opposed Brentano. He rather took Brentano s descriptive psychology a step further: he introduced a dynamic component to the analysis of the psyche that is complementary to Brentano s descriptive psychology and could be considered a type of genetic psychology. In A Brief on Husserl and Bayesian Perceptual Updating, Kenneth Williford argues that Husserl s description of perceptual updating actually fits very nicely into the Bayesian Brain paradigm, articulated by Karl Friston and others, and that this paradigm, in turn, can be taken as an excellent example of Neurophenomenology. He further argues that [t]he apparently un-phenomenological Helmholtzian component of the Bayesian Brain paradigm according to which what one consciously seems to see is a product of unconscious causal reasoning to the best explanation of one s sensory stimulations can be finessed in a way that makes it compatible with a phenomenological orientation. Part II of this collection contains papers by Michael Oliva Córdoba (Universität Hamburg), Wolfgang Grassl (St. Norbert College), Gloria Zúñiga y Postigo (Ashford University), and Olivier Massin (Université de Genève). In Uneasiness and Scarcity: An Interpretation of Mises Praxeology, Michael Oliva Córdoba presents a bridge connecting Menger and Mises. Although members of the same Austrian School of economics, their views have been understood by some as incompatible. One of these, according to Oliva Córdoba, is Barry Smith, who charges that in praxeology other core notions, in addition to the concept of action, have been smuggled in and the theory is therefore not purely analytic. In response, Oliva Córdoba, offers Mises s uneasiness theorem and the scarcity theorem as counterexamples and concludes that these also serve to support Mises s controversial claim that economics is a priori founded in action theory. One of the major developments in Austrian thought at turn-of-the twentieth century Vienna is the formation of the first and second schools of value. Menger and the economists constituted the former, and Brentano and his students the latter. Wolfgang Grassl observes in Toward a Unified Theory of Value: From Austrian Economics to Austrian Philosophy that the contributions in value theory from both schools of value would serve cutting-edge marketing, as well as business, more generally. Under one understanding of marketing, Grassl explains, this discipline focuses on the creation of customer value. Although nobody doubts today that value is subjective and it emerges from consumer judgment, the causality is less clear. Grassl argues that both schools of value share enough common

Axiomathes (2017) 27:437 441 441 ground that, by drawing on some essential assumptions in each camp, a general theory of value can be developed. The next paper, by Gloria Zúñiga y Postigo, addresses Menger s theory of subjective economic value. Zúñiga y Postigo argues in her paper On the Transformation of Economic Value that although both Austrian economists at the turn of the 20th Century and contemporary economists alike accept the view that economic value is subjective, both presuppose a different causality and even a different bearer of such value. But these differences have gone unnoticed, largely because today subjective value is accepted without the examination of the theory behind it. Lacking a common ground in theory, then, Zúñiga y Postigo observes that the neoclassical understanding of value has taken an orthogonal direction from its Austrian foundations. The last paper in the collection The Metaphysics of Ownership: A Reinachian Approach presents an example of Brentano s far-reaching sphere of influence, beyond Vienna. Adolf Reinach started attending Husserl s lectures at Göttingen in 1905 and soon became one of the founding members of the Göttingen Philosophische Gesellschaft, also referred to as the Göttingen Circle. In his paper, Olivier Massin links Reinach s theory of ownership to the Brentanian lineage of Austrian Aristotelianism. Ownership, for Reinach, is a primitive and indivisible relation between a person and a thing. This suggests an application of the notion of intentional action. According to Massin, this relation not only grounds property rights, it is also a pre-legal structure that is presupposed by positive law. Massin argues that Reinach s theory of ownership offers a far superior alternative to any rival theory of ownership. The variety of topics examined by the authors for this collection thus show the wealth of the contributions from economists and philosophers of the period in Austrian thought at the turn of the twentieth century and, indeed, the import that these contributions have for contemporary work. There is still much more to be explored, and we hope that this collection helps spur the attention that Austrian thought merits. Gloria Zúñiga y Postigo and Kenneth Williford Guest Editors References Eaton HO (1930) The Austrian philosophy of values. University of Oklahoma Press, Norman Gordon D (1993) The Philosophical Origins of Austrian Economics Ludwig von Mises Institute, Auburn, AL, Retrieved from https://mises.org/library/philosophical-origins-austrian-economics-1 Grassl W, Smith B (1986) Austrian economics and Austrian philosophy. In: Grassl W, Smith B (eds) Austrian economics and Austrian philosophy. Croom Helm, London Smith B (1995) Austrian philosophy: the legacy of Franz Brentano. Open Court, Chicago