Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973

Similar documents
SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

Page 1

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Humanities 116: Philosophical Perspectives on the Humanities

The Origin of Aristotle's Metaphysical Aporiae

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

RHETORICAL DEVICES. Rhetoric: the art of effective, persuasive speaking or writing

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

Module 11. Reasoning with uncertainty-fuzzy Reasoning. Version 2 CSE IIT, Kharagpur

Terminology. - Semantics: Relation between signs and the things to which they refer; their denotata, or meaning

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Aristotle (summary of main points from Guthrie)

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Z.13: Substances and Universals

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

An introduction to biological essentialism. John Wilkins Biohumanities Project University of Queensland

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

web address: address: Description

observation and conceptual interpretation

Ideas of Language from Antiquity to Modern Times

WRITING A PRÈCIS. What is a précis? The definition

Theories of linguistics

An Introduction To James Doull's Interpretation Of Aristotle

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

An essay on Alasdair MacIntyre s Relativism. Power and Philosophy

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

ARISTOTLE. PHILO 381(W) Sec. 051[4810] Fall 2009 Professor Adluri Monday/Wednesday, 7:00-8:15pm

Georg W. F. Hegel ( ) Responding to Kant

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

PHIL 260. ANCIENT GREEK PHILOSOPHY. Fall 2017 Tuesday & Thursday: (Oddfellows 106)

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

The Object Oriented Paradigm

Plato s Forms. Feb. 3, 2016

Goldie on the Virtues of Art

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

0:24 Arthur Holmes (AH): Aristotle s ethics 2:18 AH: 2:43 AH: 4:14 AH: 5:34 AH: capacity 7:05 AH:

EXPANDED COURSE DESCRIPTIONS UC DAVIS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT SPRING, Michael Glanzberg MWF 10:00-10:50a.m., 176 Everson CRNs:

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

The Parmenides. chapter 1

Aristotle on the Human Good

Scientific and Research Ethics. Seminar 6: Interpretation

Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008

Critical Thinking 4.2 First steps in analysis Overcoming the natural attitude Acknowledging the limitations of perception

Classics and Philosophy

Aristotle s Categories and Physics

Introduction HIROYUKI ETO

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Plato s Enlightenment, History of Philosophy Quarterly, Vol 14, No 2, April 1997, pp

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Goldmedaille bei der IPO 2015 in Tartu (Estland)

Aristotle's Stoichiology: its rejection and revivals

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

Language & Literature Comparative Commentary

Peirce and Semiotic an Introduction

Literary Stylistics: An Overview of its Evolution

Plato and Aristotle: Mimesis, Catharsis, and the Functions of Art

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY. James Bartell

In order to enrich our experience of great works of philosophy and literature we will include, whenever feasible, speakers, films and music.

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

An Outline of Aesthetics

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Architecture is epistemologically

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

APPLYING DIALECTIC TO ACQUISITION STRATEGY

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile


Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Special Issue on Ideas of Plato in the Philosophy of the 21st Century : An Introduction

The Concept of Nature

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Transcription:

Sonderdrucke aus der Albert-Ludwigs-Universität Freiburg RAINER MARTEN Martin, Gottfried: Plato s doctrine of ideas [Platons Ideenlehre]. Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973 [Rezension] Originalbeitrag erschienen in: Philosophy and history 11 (1978), S. 31-34

Philosophy 31 MARTIN, GOTTFRIED Plato's Doctrine of Ideas ["PlatonsIdeenlehre"] Berlin: Verlag Walter de Gruyter, 1973; 296 pp. Plato's definition of the idea is particularly topical in German philosophy today, and the work here under review by Gottfried Martin, the professor of philosophy at Bonn who died in October 1972, is not the only book with this title to appear during the seventies. But it differs from the others in being aimed at a wider readership among the non-plato specialists. Martin has no intention to philosophize with Plato and work with him on his problems. He quotes Plato and Plato scholarship to identify for beginners important problems of Plato's doctrine of ideas. For Martin there is, by a process of systematic simplification, such a thing as the doctrine of ideas, although readers of Plato will quickly recognize that the word `idea' (Greek idea, eidos) in Plato covers a variety of concepts. In the first part of his book Martin demonstrates that there is (and in what sense there is) a doctrine of ideas, while in the following section he enters in greater detail into its multifarious problems. Of particular importance is the fundamental decision to search for Plato's philosophy in his dialogues and not, as K. Gaiser and H. J. Kramer (`the Tübingen school') have done, in his unwritten doctrine. Among the dialogues he attaches central importance to the `Symposium', Phaedo', 'Phaedrus' and `Republic'. When Martin wishes to fall back on an authority in his attitudes to Plato he is fond of quoting Hegel. Even today many German philosophers consider him as the most reliable speculative force when it is a question of avoiding the historical relativity of philosophical truths. A somewhat out-of-date feature is the frequent appeal to the doyen of classical philology U. von Wilamowitz-Möllendorf. As to Plato's doctrine of ideas itself, Martin frequently has recourse to P. Natorp and W. D. Ross. He also knows specialized literature from as far afield as the Anglo-Saxon school of Plato studies based on linguistic analysis. His own studies in the history of philosophy, particularly on Odtham, Leibniz and Kant, come to life wherever possible in this study of Plato. They serve among other things as the basis for a comparison of idealism and nominalism, for a discussion of the problems of conceptualization and for a consideration of a formal ethic for Plato. In this way Martin is following a general trend towards consciously renouncing historicism and linking Plato on factual grounds (and not simply out of an opportunist desire to be up-to-date) with present-day philosophical questions. There is a growing awareness that Plato has given unsurpassed formulation to many questions. While no developed logic or ethic is to

32 Philosophy be found in his works, his views on formal logic and moral philosophy are being found again to have great factual competence. He is more.than merely stimulating. Martin teaches us how much efforts goes into a correct understanding of Platonic terminology. Words like phainomenon (phenomenon') and ousia ('being', `essence'), while on the one hand semantically overburdened as the result of a long philosophical tradition, were also, on the other, subject to polysemy in the Greek of Plato's own day. The first requirement is therefore to read Plato himself and to develop intrinsic criteria which will enable a relatively reliable and firm interpretation of individual passages. An essential requirement is some detachment from Aristotle. The Latin word substantia, for instance, may be all very well for Greek ousia in Aristotle, but not in Plato: the Platonic idea as true being is not a substance. Those more familiar with Plato, however, will also learn from Martin how difficult it is to follow intelligently Plato's conception of the idea as true being (ousia ontos ousa). This can best be demonstrated by the example of the `Sophistes' dialogue, where Plato treats of megista gene, literally `largest genera' (whereby Plato does not yet distinguish, as Aristotle does, in a biological sense between genos 'genus' and eidos 'species'). Three of the five `genera' adduced by Plato are being, identity and difference. Martin asks whether these are concepts or ideas, settling after some hesitation for ideas. But all he can claim in justification is that Plato himself speaks of them as ideas. But what is an idea? Although Martin puts this question as a paragraph heading, we look in vain for a satisfactory answer. In accepted Aristotelian manner he holds firm to the belief that ideas are general concepts. These 'largest genera' are therefore for him `very general concepts', `widest concepts', 'concepts of greatest generality'. But since, as is generally accepted, the actual misunderstanding of Plato's doctrine of ideas a misunderstanding that goes back to Aristotle lies in this very interpretation of ideas as concepts, Martin tries to transfer his own hesitation to Plato. Martin takes into account the Greek manner of hypostatizing and personifying in order to rescue Plato's conception of the idea more or less plausibly. This makes the idea of the Beautiful not into a general concept but (sound Greek thinking) into something like the goddess Aphrodite. But here caution must be exercised. The reader of Plato will be aware of how Plato imposed his ideas on current thought precisely in opposition to the prevailing idea of divine individuals. The very fact that the idea of the Beautiful is 'in every respect' and 'alone' beautiful should be enough to discredit the thesis of personification. In order not to give up prematurely the attempt to conceive of `idea' as something different from `concept' one would have to be prepared to accept patiently the fact that from the `Republic' to the Seventh Est e

Philosophy 33 Plato differentiates between knowledge as definition and knowledge as idea. It would be doing an injustice to Plato to designate knowledge as idea simply as intuition and then to leave it to initiation rites and evidence based on inspiration of a kind no reasonable person could share. One need only read `Republic', VI, 511 b-c, VII, 534 b-d. Martin offers explanations for quite remarkable consequences of Plato's doctrine of ideas. If according to Plato the idea of the Beautiful is itself beautiful, then self-predication or self-participation is taking place (these being terms used by Anglo-Saxon scholars as an argument against Plato). But Plato did not believe that the concept `Beautiful' must itself be beautiful, nor is this an (unintended) consequence of his theory. To appreciate this it is necessary to depart more convincingly and circumspectly than Martin does from substance and concept as a basis for understanding the Platonic idea. Martin also discusses in some detail the relationship of the idea to things determined by it (idea of the Beautiful - beautiful people, beautiful clothes). As a reaction to this relationship the Academy developed an argument against Plato called tritos anthropos, an argument that Plato himself mentions in his 'Parmenides': if the thing determined by an idea resembles the idea, then the idea also resembles the thing. If both resemble each other, then they resemble a third, and so on indefinitely. Here it is essential to take into account the non-substantial character of things determined by ideas. Something beautiful is, strictly speaking, according to Plato not a beautiful thing, but something beautiful to the extent that. The idea of the Beautiful guarantees the beautiful nature of something and nothing else. It follows that one has to interpret the relationship of the idea of the Beautiful and that which is `beautiful to the extent that' as an assymetrical one. Then it becomes more plausible why Plato, regardless of this argument (which he was quite familiar with) should have held firm to the conception of the idea. Martin points to the special significance of the idea of Equality, but does not mention that this idea is surprisingly formulated in the plural (ta isa auta). In the discussion of negative ideas (ugliness) there is no reference to the Not-Beautiful in the `Sophistes'. Nor does Martin adequately draw on dialectics (for example the dihairetic unfolding of pure eide) for an explanation of the doctrine of ideas. Instead he speaks - anachronistically - of a `pure dialectic'. The dialectic discussion in Germany is basically determined straight across the board by Hegel, and neither word nor concept seems to be applicable to Plato's dialectic as a multifarious philosophical method. Aristotle himself did his share to bring this method into scientific discredit. More recent experiments in practical philosophy in German (for example the Erlangen School) have, however, introduced a rehabilitation

34 Philosophy on a broader base of Plato's dialectic as a philosophic-scientific method. Martin saw himself throughout his life as an advocate of ontology. He was open to philosophical innovations, only they ought not to expect him to sacrifice traditional philosophy as a doctrine of being in favour of a purely scientific philosophy in the manner of the early Vienna Circle. But an emphatic avowal of ontology such as is still common in German philosophical provinces easily results in self-deception. Thus Martin has fallen victim to his own creed (not, however, to his own undisputed knowledge of Plato) in believing that the question `What is being?' is Plato's 'highest question'. Being (ousia) is, it is true, defined by Plato in his `Sophistes' as an idea, just as Not-Being is; but that should not prevent us from seeing how Plato for the first time comes up against special theoretical questions of predication and existence which cannot simply be pigeon-holed under the heading of philosophical `questions of being'. It is here that one sees how fraught with peril it is that for Martin idea equals idea even when there are different kinds of ideas. An idea like that of the Beautiful in the `Symposium' and an idea like that of Being in the `Sophistes' are not merely different kinds of ideas, but must be categorized differently as ideas. This is where new questions arise, such as whether for example Plato has with ideas occasionally struck on the problem of meaning and whether he has in mind intellectual forms based on reflexion. Professor Dr. Rainer Marten