Dutch modals with a null VP proform complement

Similar documents
Restructuring restructuring: explaining long passive phenomena in Dutch. Jan-Wouter Zwart University of Groningen

The FOFC asymmetry: a layered derivation perspective

(The) most in Dutch: Definiteness and Specificity. Koen Roelandt CRISSP, KU Leuven HUBrussel

John Benjamins Publishing Company

! Japanese: a wh-in-situ language. ! Taroo-ga [ DP. ! Taroo-ga [ CP. ! Wh-words don t move. Islands don t matter.

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Islands. Wh-islands. Phases. Complex Noun Phrase islands. Adjunct islands

The Syntax and Semantics of Traces Danny Fox, MIT. How are traces interpreted given the copy theory of movement?

LOCALITY DOMAINS IN THE SPANISH DETERMINER PHRASE

EXCLAMATIVES! Hans Bennis

6 tenses. 6 tijden mix. Present Simple Past Simple Present Continuous Past Continuous Present Perfect Past Perfect

The Future Tenses. There are a number of ways to express that something happens in the future. These are the most frequently used options.

1 The structure of this exercise

I-language Chapter 8: Anaphor Binding

vragen en ontkenningen

An HPSG Account of Depictive Secondary Predicates and Free Adjuncts: A Problem for the Adjuncts-as-Complements Approach

0515 DUTCH (FOREIGN LANGUAGE)

Developing Detailed Tree Diagrams

0515 DUTCH (FOREIGN LANGUAGE)

Handout 3 Verb Phrases: Types of modifier. Modifier Maximality Principle Non-head constituents are maximal projections, i.e., phrases (XPs).

LNGT 0250 Morphology and Syntax

Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International General Certificate of Secondary Education

0515 DUTCH (FOREIGN LANGUAGE)

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope

The structure of this ppt. Sentence types An overview Yes/no questions WH-questions

Particles, adpositions and cases: a unified analysis

The structure of this ppt. Structural and categorial (and some functional) issues: English Hungarian

The structure of this ppt

Stars FILE 7 STARS KGT 2

Language and Mind Prof. Rajesh Kumar Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Sentence Processing III. LIGN 170, Lecture 8

University of Groningen. A place for life or a place to live Gieling, Johannes

Samenvatting door Sietske 3062 woorden 4 augustus keer beoordeeld. 3A The world of work

Diagnosing covert pied-piping *

Errata Carnie, Andrew (2013) Syntax: A Generative Introduction. 3 rd edition. Wiley Blackwell. Last updated March 29, 2015

VP Ellipsis. (corrected after class) Ivan A. Sag. April 23, b. Kim understands Korean and Lee should understand Korean, too.

Recap: Roots, inflection, and head-movement

Perfect doubling does not exist

VERB PATTERNS. Verb + Ving (avoid speaking) Verb + to inf (learn to speak) Verb + inf (I would rather speak)

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

The structure of this ppt

When data collide: Traditional judgments vs. formal experiments in sentence acceptability Grant Goodall UC San Diego

As mentioned before, English does not have any inflectional future tense, but there are several possibilities for expressing future time.

What s New in the 17th Edition

5,1. Spreekbeurt door een scholier 1600 woorden 27 december keer beoordeeld. Introduction

Research Seminar The syntax and semantics of questions Spring 1999 January 26, 1999 Week 1: Questions and typologies

Misschien maar even over preferentie

The Silence of the Words

Tensions in the Classroom

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

Chapter 3 Sluicing. 3.1 Introduction to wh-fragments. Chapter 3 Sluicing in An Automodular View of Ellipsis

BBLAN24500 Angol mondattan szem. / English Syntax seminar BBK What are the Hungarian equivalents of the following linguistic terms?

TEST ONE. Singing Star Showing this week. !The Wild Wheel Ride! Indoor tennis centre. RACING CAR TRACK To drive, children must be 1 metre or more

Osho-Veeresh interview, deel 2.

Deriving the Interpretation of Rhetorical Questions

On Recanati s Mental Files

2. MODALS. must, may, might, shall, should, will, would, and ought to. Modals function

Repeated measures ANOVA

Language Documentation and Linguistic Theory STYLE SHEET Department of Linguistics, SOAS

A note on lo que Ángel J. Gallego (UAB)

Reported (Indirect) Speech: Discovering the rules from Practical English Usage

January 11, 2015 LSA 2015

1. Introduction. Paper s Questions

The indefinite articles 1. We use the article a / an when we are talking about something for the first time or not specific things.

Two Styles of Construction Grammar Do Ditransitives

CHAPTER II A BRIEF DESCRIPTION OF ELLIPTIC CONSTRUCTION. In this chapter, the writer would like to discuss about elliptic contruction or elliptical

Hiding Content: Notes on Translating Stevens Colors and Frost s A Time to Talk

Gerunds & Infinitives. Week 14, Mon 11/23/15 Todd Windisch, Fall 2015

A corpus-based approach to infinitival complements in early Latin

Search for three-nucleon force effects in proton-deuteron elastic scattering Ermisch, Karsten

Answering negative questions in American Sign Language

Mental Spaces, Conceptual Distance, and Simulation: Looks/Seems/Sounds Like Constructions in English

Module Four (based on New Headway & PET reading and writing tests)

17. Semantics in L1A

Language at work Present simple

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

Grammar Flash Cards 3rd Edition Update Cards UPDATE FILE CONTENTS PRINTING TIPS

Luigi Rizzi TG 1. Locality

Sonority as a Primitive: Evidence from Phonological Inventories Ivy Hauser University of North Carolina

Grammar. Name: 1 Underline the correct words.

Adjectives - Semantic Characteristics

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Sentence Processing. BCS 152 October

Assessing answers: Towards a third-turn proof procedure?

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Direct and Indirect Speech

Bachelor Thesis. linked to the course: Vertaling en vertaalreflectie 2

U3: B: P20/21: E1 /3 U3: C: P22/23: E1/ 4 U3: P19: E2: V U1: P5: E1: V U3: A: 18/19: E1 /3 U3: C: P22/23: E1/ 4 U13: P97: E4/5: V U3: P19: E2: V

Complement Structures: Outline. Complement Structures and Non-Finite Constructions in HPSG. Problems for Small Clauses. Category Selection

Six. Unit. What does he do? Target Language. What does he do?

Deze tekst is afkomstig van de online bibliotheek op

Speaking in Minor and Major Keys

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

Unit Topic and Functions Language Skills Text types 1 Found Describing photos and

STEPS TO SUCCESSFUL WRITING

Possible Ramifications for Superiority

THE PASSIVE VOICE A) FORMATION

1 Pair-list readings and single pair readings

Positive vs. negative inversion exclamatives

Review: Discourse Analysis; Sociolinguistics: Bednarek & Caple (2012)

Markers of Literary Language A Computational-Linguistic Odyssey

Transcription:

Colloque de Syntaxe et Sémantique à Paris October 4-6, 2007 CSSP 2007 Ecole Normale Supérieure, Paris Lobke Aelbrecht Catholic University of Brussels / CRISSP lobke.aelbrecht@crissp.be B: Hij wil/ mag/ kan/ hoeft/ moet niet. he wants may can need must not He doesn t want to/is not allowed to/can t/doesn t need to/doesn t have to. There are (at least) three possible analyses for this phenomenon: Deletion of a fully specified syntactic structure, parallel to English VP ellipsis. 1 The basic data 2 Against a deletion account 3 Against an intransitivity account 4 Null VP proform 5 Implications and further research 6 Conclusion OUTLINE OF THE TALK There is no complement; the verb is simply intransitive. The verb selects a null proform. main claim: null infinitival complements (NIC) involve a vp containing a null VP proform 2 AGAINST A DELETION ACCOUNT Ross (1969), Merchant (2001) & Johnson (1996, 2001): 1 THE BASIC DATA Modals can have at least 2 interpretations: epistemic and deontic English VP ellipsis (VPE) = deletion of a full syntactic structure (3) Mina didn t eat the banana, but Peter did [ VP eat the banana]. (1) a. Het is acht uur. Klaas moet nu wel thuis zijn. = epistemic it is eight hour Klaas must now PRT home be It s eight o clock. It must be the case that Klaas is at home now. b. Klaas moet morgen afwassen. = deontic Klaas must tomorrow wash.the.dishes Klaas has to wash the dishes tomorrow. The deontic modals allow their complement to be absent: (2) A: Komt Thomas ook naar je lezing? comes Thomas also to your talk Is Thomas coming to your talk too? (4) IP DP I ellipsis Peter I VP did V V DP eat the banana 1/10

arguments: VPE allows extraction out of the elided complement and agreement with elements inside the complement (see examples below).! The properties of NIC differ from those of VPE in this respect. Claim: the null complement of a modal does not contain a fully specified VP. 2.1 Extraction Extraction is not allowed out of a NIC VPE does allow it. Wh-phrases may extract out of an elided VP (cf. Schuyler 2002, Merchant to appear), but not out of a NIC. (5) A: To who should Peter introduce Mina? VPE B: I don t know. To who should Tom? (6) A: Aan wie moet Katrien een cadeautje geven? NIC to who must Katrien a present give B: Dat weet ik niet. * Aan wie moet Bert? that know I not to who must Bert VPE: VP must contain internal structure to be able to host the trace of the whphrase (cf.(7)). (7) To who should Tom [ VP introduce Mina t to who ]. NIC: the wh-phrase cannot be moved out of the complement explanation: no internal VP structure. VPE allows arguments or adjuncts to survive the ellipsis (= pseudogapping), NIC does not: (9) * Katrien kan brood kopen en Bert kan melk. NIC Katrien can bread buy and Bert can milk INTENDED READING: and Bert can buy milk. VPE: VP must contain internal structure to be able to host the trace of the object (which has moved out of the VP prior to the deletion of VP; see Jayaseelan 1990; Johnson 1996; Lasnik 1999a, 1999b, 2001 & Takahashi 1994). (10) Mina can roll up a newspaper and Peter can a magazine [ VP roll up t a magazine ]. NIC: the object cannot be moved out of the complement explanation: no internal VP structure. VPE allows antecedent-contained deletion (ACD), NIC do not. (11) Mina reads each book that Peter should. VPE (12) * Joris leest elk boek dat Monika moet. NIC Joris reads each book that Monika must INTENDED READING: Joris reads every book that Monika must read. VPE: The relative clause involves wh-movement of an empty operator (Chomsky 1977, 1981). This empty operator Op i needs to bind a trace, so the elided VP has to contain syntactic structure that can host the trace. (13) Mina reads each book Op i that Peter should [ VP read t i ]. NIC: there is no VP structure for the operator to move out from. (8) Mina can roll up a newspaper and Peter can a magazine. VPE 2/10

Object scrambling out of the null complement is disallowed: (14) a. Ik wil [ je helpen], maar ik kan je niet [ t je helpen]. I want you help but I can you not help b. Ik wil je helpen, maar ik kan (* je) niet. I want you help but I can you not I want to help you, but I cannot. 2.2 There-expletives An elided VP can have a there-expletive as its subject (Ross 1969), NIC cannot. (15) Mina thinks there should be balloons in the hall, but there shouldn t. VPE (16) A: Moeten er veel mensen naar de vergadering komen? NIC must there a.lot.of people to the meeting come B:*Nee, er moeten niet. no there must not VPE: the elided VP must contain an indefinite DP that licenses there and agrees with the finite verb (17), but there shouldn t [ VP be balloons in the hall] NIC: er there is not licensed explanation: the NIC does not contain a fully specified VP structure containing an indefinite DP. (18) a. Hij heeft dat niet gehoord. 2-verb cluster: past participle he has that not heard He didn t hear that. b. Hij heeft dat niet horen vallen. 3-verb cluster: IPP he has that not hear.inf fall.inf He didn t hear that fall. modals in 3-verb clusters: also IPP (19) Kwam Peter niet gisteren? Nee, hij heeft niet * gewild/ willen came Peter not yesterday no he has not wanted want.inf komen. come.inf Did Peter come yesterday? No, he didn t want to come. NIC: no IPP effect (20) Kwam Peter niet gisteren? Nee, hij heeft niet?gewild/*willen. came Peter not yesterday no he has not wanted want.inf Did Peter come yesterday? No, he didn t want to. explanation: there is no VP structure containing the main infinitive that causes IPP. Conclusion: Dutch NIC do not involve deletion of a fully specified syntactic VP. 2.3 The IPP effect NIC do not display the IPP (Infinitivus Pro Participio) effect. IPP: in 3-verb clusters the non-finite auxiliary verb is an infinitive instead of the expected past participle in Dutch. 3/10

3 AGAINST THE INTRANSITIVE ANALYSIS A null infinitival complement does not contain a syntactic VP structure this leaves us with 2 options: The modal is an intransitive verb without any complement at all (cf. Napoli 1985 for Italian). The modal has a null VP proform in its complement. This section: argument against an intransitive analysis a detour via Dutch modal verbs Overview: 3.1 Raising versus control 3.2 A subject position below the modal 3.1 Raising versus control Claim: deontic modals are raising verbs, just like epistemic modals. They do not assign an Agent Θ-role to their subject (Wurmbrand 2003). Step 1: Diagnostic tests for the raising/control distinction. Raising verbs can have inanimate subjects when their complement is passive, because they do not assign an Agent Θ-role to it: (21) a. De auto lijkt gewassen te zijn. raising the car seems washed to be The car seems to be washed. b.* De auto probeert gewassen te worden. control the car tries washed to become Raising verbs allow impersonal passive, unlike control verbs: (22) a. Er lijkt gedanst te worden. raising there seems danced to become There seems to be dancing going on. b.* Er probeert gedanst te worden. control there tries danced to become Step 2: Comparing deontic modals to raising and control verbs. inanimate subjects: (23) De auto kan/ moet/ mag/* wil gewassen worden. the car can must may wants washed become The car can/has to/may be washed. impersonal passives (24) Er kan/ moet/ mag/* wil gedanst worden. there can must may wants danced become There can/must/may be dancing going on. However: deontic kunnen can has both an ability and an availability reading. (25) a. Karel kan zwemmen. = ability Karel can swim PREFERRED READING: Karel has the ability to swim. b. Karel kan vanavond de afwas doen. = availability Karel can tonight the dishes do PREFERRED READING: Karel is available tonight for washing the dishes. # Karel has the ability to do the dishes tonight. Only in the availability reading kunnen is a raising verb: (26) De auto kan gewassen worden. the car can washed become = The car is available for washing. The car is able to be washed. 4/10

(27) Er kan gezwommen worden. there can swum become = Swimming facilities are available. There is an ability to swim. kunnen ability = control main verb, assigning an Agent Θ-role to the subject (cf.(28)a). kunnen availibility = raising verb, assigning only a Theme Θ-role to its whole infinitival complement (cf. (28)b). (28) a. SUBJ kunnen [ PRO VP] b. kunnen [ t subj VP] Dutch modals are raising verbs, except for willen (want) and kunnen ability. Willen and kunnen ability are control verbs assigning an Agent role to the subject. b. Kom je naar het feestje vanavond? Nee, ik mag niet. come you to the party tonight no I may not Are you coming to the party tonight? No, I m not allowed. Moreover: only the raising kunnen availability allows NIC. (31) a. Piet kan zwemmen, en Tim kan ook *( zwemmen). Piet can swim and Tim can too swim Pete can swim and Tim can swim too. = ability b. Piet kan vanavond afwassen, en Tim kan ook ( vanavond Piet can tonight wash.the.dishes and Tim can too tonight afwassen). wash.the.dishes Pete can wash the dishes tonight, and so can Tim. = availability The modal is not intransitive: there is at least some structure in the complement of the modal. 3.2 A subject position below the modal Prediction: if the NIC modal is an intransitive verb, there is an incompatibility with raising as in (28)b/(29)b, since there is no position from which raising could have taken place. NIC do not involve an intransitive modal: there is a vp complement present containing a subject position and a null VP proform. (29) a. Hij moet. (intransitive analysis) he must b. Hij i moet [ t i XP ]. (raising analysis) The prediction is not borne out: raising modals can have a null complement. (30) a. Zal Karel vanavond dansen? Hij moet wel! will Karel tonight dance he must PRT Will Karel dance tonight? He has to! 5/10

4 NULL VP PROFORM Overview 4.1 The analysis: a null VP-proform 4.2 Licensing the proform 4.3 Predictions made by the analysis 4.1 The analysis: a null VP proform Dutch NIC: no syntactically specified complement, but a null VP proform (32) Ik wil wel komen vanavond, maar ik mag niet [e]. I want PRT come tonight but I may not I want to come tonight, but I am not allowed. (33) ModP 4.2 Licensing the proform Mod Mod vp mogen SUBJ v v pro VP Not every verb can take a null VP proform complement: the proform has to be licensed. Rizzi (1986): licensing requirements on null objects (34) a. pro is governed by a head X 0 of type y. b. Let X be the licensing head of an occurrence of pro: then pro has the grammatical specification of the features on X coindexed with it. c. pro is Case-marked by X y 0. Current minimalist theories (Chomsky 1995): Identification and licensing of proforms through a local AGREE relation with a syntactic head. Rizzi: licensing of DP proforms NIC: licensing of a pro VP : There must be a local AGREE relation between a licensing head (i.e. the modal) and the VP proform. 4.2.1 Licensing pro VP, step 1: Mod 0 is a derived phase head in NIC. v 0 -head = morpho-phonologically deficient it gets morpho-phonological features from V through movement of V. (35) vp v v VP V v V However: in NIC, V is absent, and pro VP does not have morpho-phonological features. Solution: phase extension t V 6/10

(36) Syntactic movement of the head H of a phase α up to the head X of a node β dominating α extends the phase up from α to β; α loses its phasehood in the process, and any constituent on the edge of α ends up in the domain of the derived phase β as a result of Phase Extension. (Den Dikken 2006) NIC: v moves to the head of the phrase dominating vp to get morpho-phonological features there, thereby extending the phase and making Mod 0 a derived phase head (see (37)) (37) 4.2.2 Licensing in NIC, step 2: AGREE. Feature specification: Mod 0 [uv], [if] (with F a functional feature) pro VP [iv], [uf] Feature checking: an AGREE relation between Mod and pro VP. (38) ModP Mod Mod ModP Mod extended phase vp v Mod v t v Mod vp pro VP v Mod v [if] [uv] t v pro VP [uf] [iv] The licensing modal head is local enough and the proform gets licensed through AGREE. The proform cannot be licensed by verbs higher up in the tree due to the Phase Impenetrability Condition (PIC; Chomsky 2000). (39) In a phase α with head H, the domain of H is not accessible to operations outside α, only H and its edge are accessible to such operations. 4.3 Predictions made by the analysis Epistemic modals, temporal auxiliaries and raising verbs such as schijnen seem do not license NIC. These verbs are higher up in the structure (Wurmbrand 2003, Butler 2006) not local enough to license the VP proform. epistemic modals: (40) A: Zou Klaas nu op zijn bureau zijn? Would Klaas now on his office be B:*Hij moet wel. Hij werkt altijd op zaterdag. he must PRT he works always on Saturday INTENDED READING: It must be the case that he is in his office. temporal auxiliaries (hebben have, zijn be and zullen will ): (41) A: Heeft Katrien gisteren gebeld? B: * Ze heeft niet. has Katrien yesterday called she has not (42) A: Is Thomas ook naar je lezing gekomen? B: * Hij is niet. is Thomas also to your talk come.part he is not (43) A: Komt Thomas ook naar je lezing? B: * Hij zal niet. comes Thomas also to your talk he will not 7/10

higher raising verbs: (44) A: Heeft iemand de auto gerepareerd? * Ja, Klaas schijnt. has someone the car fixed yes Klaas seems 5 IMPLICATIONS AND FURTHER RESEARCH 5.1 Categorizing the verbs licensing NIC corollary: all verbs that can license a VP proform are low enough in the structure, immediately dominating vp. English modals can only license deletion of a VP structure, not a VP proform. English modals behave differently from Dutch modals (see among others Wurmbrand 2003, IJbema 2002): lack of inflection, cannot co-occur, do not take DP complements. English modals are higher than ModP, in T and cannot license a VP proform. (45) licensing NIC raising deontic modals moeten kunnen (avail.) mogen hoeven willen kunnen (abil.) epistemic modals moeten kunnen mogen hoeven willen other restructuring verbs beginnen durven helpen dwingen weigeren verplichten proberen dreigen Table 1: Categorizing the NIC verbs Examples of non-modal verbs taking infinitival complements: 8/10

beginnen: (46) a. Het begint te regenen. raising it begins to rain b. Lara was aan het zingen en toen ik aankwam, begon Tom ook. Lara was on the sing and when I arrived began Tom too Lara was singing and when I entered Tom began to sing as well. NIC control verbs with NIC: (47) a. Ze moesten enkel de bal wegschoppen, maar ze durfden they must.past only the ball away.kick but they dared niet. not They only had to kick away the ball, but they didn t dare to. b. Hij kan zich aankleden, maar je moet hem wel helpen. he can REFL on.dress but you must him PRT help He can dress himself, but you have to help him with it. c. Ik wou de berg niet afrijden, maar Steven heeft mij I wanted the hill not off.drive but Steven has me gedwongen. forced I didn t want to drive down the hill, but Steven forced me. d. A: Wou iedereen helpen? B: Alleen Klaas weigerde. wanted everyone help only Klaas refused Did everyone agreed to help? Only Klaas refused. e. Tim wou niet komen, maar moeder verplichtte hem. Tim wanted not come but mother compelled him Tim didn t want to come, but mother compelled him to. f. A: Heeft iemand de auto gerepareerd? B: Nee, maar Tom has someone the car fixed no but Tom heeft wel geprobeerd. has PRT tried Did someone fix the car? No, but Tom did try. dreigen: (48) a. Er dreigt gevochten te worden. raising there threatens fought to become There threatens to be fighting going on. b. Het is niet zeker dat de regering zal vallen, maar ze it is not sure that the government will fall but she dreigt wel *( te vallen). no NIC threatens PRT to fall The distinction between the verbs allowing and not allowing a null VP proform crosscuts the familiar distinction between control and raising verbs. 5.2 Further research questions Is there an overt counterpart of this proform in Dutch? Suggestion: Dutch might have a null SO, on a par with the English overt VP proform so. We have two strategies in language to elide a verb phrase: deletion of a syntactic structure (VPE) and null proforms (Dutch NIC). How does language decide between these strategies? What determines the choice? Can we unite these two strategies? Cross-linguistic comparison: there are many other languages with null infinitival complements, e.g. German, Italian, French and Spanish. Can this analysis be transferred to these languages? 9/10

6 CONCLUSION Null infinitival complements of modals are vps containing a subject position and a null VP proform. The null complements do not involve deletion of a full syntactic structure, unlike VP ellipsis in English: - They do not allow extraction (e.g. pseudogapping, wh-extraction, ACD, object scrambling). - They do not allow a there-expletive as their subject. - They block the IPP- effect. The modal verb with a null infinitival complement is not used intransitively (contra Napoli 1985). As most of them are raising verbs, there must be a position dominated by the modal from which the subject can be raised. Not all modals allow null VP proforms, only deontic modal verbs do. The boundary between verbs that can take a null infinitival complement and verbs that cannot does not coincide with the distinction between raising and control. REFERENCES BUTLER, J. (2006). The structure of temporality and morality (or, Towards deriving something like a Cinque Hierarchy). In: Linguistic Variation Yearbook 6, pp. 161-201. CHOMSKY, N. (1977). On Wh-Movement. In: P.W. Culicover, T. Wasow & A. Akmajian, (eds), Formal Syntax, New York. CHOMSKY, N. (1981). Lectures on government and binding: the Pisa lectures. Foris Publications. CHOMSKY, N. (1995). The minimalist program. MIT Press. CHOMSKY, N. (2000). Minimalist Inquiries: the framework. In: R. Martin, D. Michaels & J. Uriagereka (eds.), Step by Step: Essays on minimalist syntax in honor of Howard Lasnik. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. DIKKEN, M. Den (2006). Phase extension: Contours of a theory of the role of head movement in phrasal extraction. Ms. University of New York. IJBEMA, A. (2002). Grammaticalization and infinitival complements in Dutch. LOT Dissertation Series. JOHNSON, K. (1996). When verb phrases go missing. In: Glot International 2:5, pp. 3-9. JOHNSON, K. (2001). What VP-ellipsis can do, and what it can t, but not why. In: M. Baltin & C. Collins (eds.), The handbook of contemporary syntactic theory. Blackwell, pp. 439-479. LASNIK, H. (1999a). Pseudogapping Puzzles. In: S. Lappin & E. Benmamoun (eds.), Fragments: studies in ellipsis and gapping. OUP, pp. 141-174. LASNIK, H. (1999b). On feature strength: Three minimalist approaches to overt movement. In: Linguistic Inquiry 30, pp. 197-217. LASNIK, H. (2001). When can you save a structure by destroying it?. In: M. Kim & U. Strauss (eds.), Proceedings of the North East Linguistic Society 31. GLSA, pp. 301-320. MERCHANT, J. (2001). The syntax of silence. Sluicing, islands and the theory of ellipsis. OUP. MERCHANT, J. (to appear). Variable Island Repair under Ellipsis. In: K. Johnson (ed.), Topics in Ellipsis. CUP. NAPOLI, D. (1985). Complementation in Italian: Phonetically null vs totally absent complements. In: Language 61:1, pp. 73-94. RIZZI, L. (1986). Null objects in Italian and the Theory of pro. In: Linguistic Inquiry 17, pp. 501-558. ROSS, J.R. (1969). Guess who?. In: R. Binnick, A. Davidson, G. Green & J. Morgan (eds.), Papers from the fifth regional meeting of the Chicago Linguistic Society. Chicago Linguistic Society, pp. 252-286. SCHUYLER, T. (2002). Wh-movement out of the site of VP Ellipsis. MA Thesis UCSC. TAKAHASHI, D. (1994). Minimality of movement. PhD Dissertation University of Connecticut. WURMBRAND, S. (2003). Infinitives: Restructuring and Clause Structure. Mouton de Gruyter: Berlin/New York. 10/10