Stefán Snævarr, Kunstfilosofi: En kritisk innføring. Bergen: Fagbokforlaget, pages. isbn

Similar documents
PHIL 271 (02): Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art

Literature 300/English 300/Comparative Literature 511: Introduction to the Theory of Literature

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Philosophy Of Art Philosophy 330 Spring 2015 Syllabus

Aesthetics. Phil-267 Department of Philosophy Wesleyan University Spring Thursday 7:00-9:50 pm Location: Wyllys 115

The Confluence of Aesthetics and Hermeneutics in Baumgarten, Meier, and Kant

Stephen Wright University College, Oxford Trinity College, Oxford

Narrating the Self: Parergonality, Closure and. by Holly Franking. hermeneutics focus attention on the transactional aspect of the aesthetic

PHR-107 Introduction to the Philosophy of Art

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

BASIC ISSUES IN AESTHETIC

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

PHILOSOPHY OF ART AND BEAUTY

The Outside of the Political

6AANA034 Aesthetics Syllabus Academic year 2016/17. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines

Aesthetics. Stephen Wright University College, Oxford Trinity College, Oxford Hilary 2018

Philosophy and Literature

UGS 302: Art, Criticism, and Society University of Texas at Austin Fall 2016

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Anti-Essentialism. San Jose State University. From the SelectedWorks of Tom Leddy. Tom Leddy, San Jose State University

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Aesthetics and the Arts Philosophy 327 Spring 2014

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

CLASS PARTICIPATION IS A REQUIREMENT

The Institutional Theory of Art

FORUM: QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH SOZIALFORSCHUNG

Classificatory Theories of Art: Resemblance and the Artworld

Aesthetics. Stephen Wright. Office: XVI.3, Jesus College. Hilary Overview 3. 2 Course Website 3. 3 A Note on the Reading List 3

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Goldmedaille bei der IPO 2015 in Tartu (Estland)

Humanities 4: Critical Evaluation in the Humanities Instructor: Office: Phone: Course Description Learning Outcomes Required Texts

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

Intention and Interpretation

Curriculum Vitae Dr. Kyriaki Goudeli Assistant Professor

POST-KANTIAN AUTONOMIST AESTHETICS AS APPLIED ETHICS ETHICAL SUBSTRATUM OF PURIST LITERARY CRITICISM IN 20 TH CENTURY

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Aesthetics. Stephen Wright. Office: XVI.3, Jesus College. Michaelmas Overview 3. 2 Course Website 3. 3 A Note on the Reading List 3

A Short History of German Philosophy

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

The Ancient Philosophers: What is philosophy?

TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE... INTRODUCTION...

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Discerning Values: Aesthetics Today via Shakespeare and Van Eyck

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Sample Syllabus. Course Number: AMG 505

Objective Interpretation and the Metaphysics of Meaning

The Humanities as Conversation and Edification: On Rorty s Idea of a Gadamerian Culture

Keywords: Postmodernism, European literature, humanism, relativism

LT218 Radical Theory

PHILOSOPHY. haverford.edu/philosophy

Philosophy Faculty Reading List and Course Outline PART II PAPER 11: AESTHETICS

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

PHIL 415 Continental Philosophy: Key Problems Spring 2013

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Name Period Date. Grade 7, Unit 1 Pre-assessment. Read this selection from Fast Sam, Cool Clyde, and Stuff by Walter Dean Myers

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

ATINER's Conference Paper Series PHI

An Outline of Aesthetics

Phenomenology and Structuralism PHIL 607 Fall 2011

Choosing your modules (Joint Honours Philosophy) Information for students coming to UEA in 2015, for a Joint Honours Philosophy Programme.

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

Philosophy of Art and Aesthetic Experience in Rome PHIL 277 Fall 2018

Course Description. Alvarado- Díaz, Alhelí de María 1. The author of One Dimensional Man, Herbert Marcuse lecturing at the Freie Universität, 1968

Benjamin pronounced there is nothing more important then a translation.

Philosophy in the educational process: Understanding what cannot be taught

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

[My method is] a science that studies the life of signs within society I shall call it semiology from the Greek semeion signs (Saussure)

SENIOR SEMINAR: Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: Between Phenomenology and Semiotic. Fall 2012 & Winter 2013

at all and similar claims were (and still are) made about Nietzsche and Kierkegaard.

GRADUATE SEMINARS

Narrative Case Study Research

E. D. Hirsch Jr. Hans-Georg Gadamer. 12JZD019 E. D. com

RESPONDING TO ART: History and Culture

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Critical Theory for Research on Librarianship (RoL)

THE DEVELOPMENT OF AESTHETICS THROUGH WESTERN EYES

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

The Outcome of Classical German Philosophy (Draft) Mon. 4:15-6:15 Room: 3207

Introduction and Overview

Round Table. Department of French and Spanish. Memorial University of Newfoundland

A Kantian Critique of Positive Aesthetics of Nature

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Narrative Analysis by David M. Boje. Narrative analysis is the sequencing of events and character identities derived by retrospective

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Syllabus. Following a general introduction, we shall read and re-read the essay in three phases:

Confines of Democracy

The History of Philosophy. and Course Themes

index 417 Fricke, Christel, 365, 372, 375,

Intersemiotic translation: The Peircean basis

Sociological theories: the tradition and current notions pt II

Master of Arts Program in the Humanities

Transcription:

REVIEW Stefán Snævarr, Kunstfilosofi: En kritisk innføring. Bergen: Fagbokforlaget, 2008. 303 pages. isbn 978-82-450-0707-7 There is something nearly paradoxical in writing a review in English on the Icelander Stefán Snævarr s introduction to the philosophy of art. (Snævarr is a professor at Høgskolen in Lillehammer, the University College of Lillehammer, Norway). Not only is his book in Norwegian, but Snævarr has also taken pride in not only drawing on the common and well-known international literature in the field, but also in including Norwegian and other Nordic aestheticians in his discussion. If he had not done that, he remarks, he might just as well have written the book in English or German. The basis for Snævarr s book is partly his notes for lectures on the philosophy of art in Bergen in the 1990s (later held also in Lillehammer and Kristiansand), partly his other, more scholarly work in aesthetics, e.g. his PhD-thesis (in English!) Minerva and the Muses: The Place of Reason in Aesthetic Judgment (1999); actually, Snævarr himself is the author with most entries in the bibliography. This double basis has contributed to giving the text and the whole construction of the book a rather rambling touch. The basic tone is a surprisingly consistent and forceful orality surprising because the basis for the text is the written notes, not e.g. recordings of the actual lectures. Not only does one find phrases like as I said in the introduction (p. 19, my italics), but also remarks like If I understand Goodman correctly (p. 169), This reminds me of a story by an Indian author whose name I do not remember (p. 200) and What would Bourdieu have said? Well, he would probably have said yes (p. 210) and I shall refrain from trying to render any of Snævarr s often not too wonderful verbal puns. But even though the oral style is kept through the whole book, long passages become quite heavy because of their detailed renderings of the theories of specific philosophers or faceted discussions of nuanced differences between theoreticians. A beginner in this field will here get a thorough impression of what philosophical reflection of the analytical kind looks like; I doubt, however, that these readers will be able to stay on around the curves and through the particulars. But even though it says En kritisk innføring ( A Critical Introduction ) on the title page, Snævarr makes it clear in his preface that this is not solely an introduction, partly because it The Nordic Journal of Aesthetics No. 36 37 (2008/2009, pp. 157 163

Søren Kjørup contains these critical discussions, and partly because it also introduces some of the author s own theories. To me this is completely in order in itself, but I believe that critical discussion and one s own points of view can easily (or with a little effort) be integrated in an introductory work that insists on being introductory, i.e. sticks to a target group of readers to whom the topic of the book is new. Snævarr s Philosophy of Art is divided into three parts. The first is a series of inquiries into the history of aesthetics from Plato to Nietzsche; the second a presentation of main themes and figures of 20th century aesthetics; and the third one a more detailed look at four more or less current aesthetic questions. In principle this is a reasonable structure of an introductory work, in practice a rather uneven and inconsequential presentation, e.g. with a rather unclear distribution of the subject matter between the second and the third part but then again: Everywhere you will find fine and interesting reading matter. The historical part is the least satisfying. Snævarr seems not to have taken a clear stance on which kind of history he wants to tell. He starts out by reminding us that the modern concept of art does not evolve before the beginning of the 18th century, and of course this makes the reader expect a narrative about the rise of this concept. But later he suggests that it is the development of the concept of beauty that we will follow from Plato to Nietzsche, i.e. to the point in time where Beauty loses its status as the highest value of art (p. 20). Such a storyline is however not kept up through the presentation of Plato, Aristotle, Hume, Kant, Hegel and Nietzsche that follows, joined by nearly insipid asides (mostly based on secondary sources) on e.g. Boileau, Baumgarten, Shaftesbury, Hutcheson, Schiller, Schelling, Croce and Collingwood. In my view, the mixture of presentations of the various main characters and discussions of alternative presentations (most clearly with Noël Carroll on Hume) does not work and especially not in an introductory text. And one must ask oneself whether Snævarr is writing history at all, or whether this should be taken as one of those histories of philosophy that treat the philosophers of the past as our contemporaries with whom we enter into an equal dialogue. At any rate, Snævarr does not tell us much about the historical context of the main characters and their theories, e.g. about what their background was for theorizing about art or aesthetic experience. What had Kant to take him as an example seen and heard and read as his basis for the few remarks he has about art in his Critique of Judgment? Did Königsberg have a theatre in the latter half of the 18th century? 158

Review To exemplify what a Kantian uninterested judgment about the pleasant can be, Snævarr chooses an example (p. 65), not from Kant himself, but from J. O. Urmson s often reprinted essay What Makes a Situation Aesthetic from 1957; an example that in Urmson s original English text begins in this way: Let us... suppose that we observe a man in the audience at a play who is obviously beaming with delight and satisfaction. 1 But is it that kind of experience Kant speculated about? Sitting in a theatre, looking at a play? I shall not claim that I know the answer, but I take it to be a must for a real historical discussion to consider such questions. In the second part of the book it gets clear that Snævarr does not only have his background in analytical aesthetics, but that he also lets himself be inspired by the continental tradition. But the case is pretty much what I indicate here: Snævarr finds inspiring material and points of view in continental philosophy, but he writes like an analytical philosopher. He starts out with Adorno, and the Adorno chapter is extended with some material on the Frankfurt School, figures Herbert Marcuse and Walter Benjamin and a short side glance to Georg Lukács before the chapter concludes with a discussion of Feminism in aesthetics. The next chapter has Martin Heidegger as protagonist, even though it is impossible to find much aesthetics or philosophy of art in his writings; Snævarr finds it first of all in the essay The Origin of the Work of Art (first version from the middle of the 1930s) where Heidegger s main example is van Gogh s painting of a couple of his own boots (which Heidegger mistook for belonging to a peasant women). It is characteristic of Snævarr s use of these instances of continental writing that his presentation gets its volume from all the ideas of other philosophers, mainly from the analytical tradition, of which Heidegger s text reminds him (here e.g. Kuhn, Polanyi and Wittgenstein). From here we reach the chapter on Beardsley s Grand Edifice, concentrating on Beardsley s concept of the work of art and his discussion of aesthetic judgments, and with a few concluding remarks on his criticism of The Intentional Fallacy. Then follows a chapter on the Wittgenstein tradition in aesthetics, where also the Bergen School is deservedly mentioned (Gunnar Danbolt, Kjell S. Johannessen and Tore Nordenstam), and one on Nelson Goodman, the presentation of whom is not followed by remarks on disciples or successors, but only with the views of several critics. Even though I consider myself a follower of Goodman to a certain extent, Snævarr is probably right here: during the now 40 years since the publication of his Languages of Art in 1968, Goodman s often rather ex- 159

Søren Kjørup treme (but precise) nominalist and constructivist views have more often worked as points of departure for criticism and theoretical refinement than as examples for imitation. This second part of the book ends with a chapter on pragmatist aesthetics, John Dewey and first of all Richard Shusterman, and here Snævarr is really on home ground with critical approval. (After Snævarr himself, Shusterman is the philosopher who has most entries in the bibliography.) Then follows the third part of the book, with chapters on single issues, beginning with the question whether one can define art, and if so, how. A grumpy reviewer would here claim that the architecture of the book breaks down because we have already read long discussions on this theme in the Beardsley chapter, and it has also been treated e.g. in connection with Goodman s When is art? -stance. And the construction gets really wobbly when we see that the chapter starts with the Wittgenstein follower Morris Weitz and the notion of family resemblance as his answer to what connects the many different works and genres of art under one common concept. But somehow the structure is no problem in this case! Not surprisingly the chapter tells the story from Weitz (1956) over Arthur Danto and his Artworld (1964) and George Dickie s institution of art (1969), rounded off with Jerrold Levinson s and Noël Carroll s historical turn in the 1990s except that Snævarr treats Dickie before Danto (and misdates Dickie s presentation of his theory to 1974). A coherent narrative that it makes good sense to tell and to discuss. The following chapter, about interpretation, is on the other hand far from coherent and pertinent. Snævarr begins with a slightly skewed introduction to hermeneutics that quickly reaches Hans-Georg Gadamer. From there the text takes a completely superfluous and useless turn around a little bit of Saussure, continues with the French film semiologist Christian Metz, the Russian folklorist Vladimir Propp, the Lithuanian-French semiologist Algirdas Julien Greimas (Snævarr writes French-Lithuanian ), the French anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss (just turned 100, by the way!) and the French semiologist Roland Barthes to reach the French philosopher Jacques Derrida and his deconstruction. Here Snævarr seems to be on foreign ground: neither Propp nor Greimas is in his bibliography, the linguistically educated Greimas is called a literary scholar and gets his first name wrongly spelt, and Lévi-Strauss with French Jewish parents from Alsace, and grown up in Paris is called Belgian-French, probably because his father, a painter, had taken his family to Bruxelles where he had a job during the weeks around the birth of his son. 160

Review The chapter ends with a discussion of the theories within analytical philosophy about rationality and relativity in the interpretation of literary works (with a side glance to interpretation of movies). Issues concerning interpretation of other visual arts or of music are not mentioned. In the chapter on the evaluation of works of art Snævarr really feels at home: This is the theme of his dissertation. Here the different positions get names and are discussed in a fairly exact way: Objectivism (Noël Carroll), Scepticism, divided into Relativism (e.g. Bernard C. Heyl) and Subjectivism (e.g. Alfred Ayer and Pierrre Bourdieu), and then we reach Rationalism, Snævarr s own stance: judgments about works of art are not completely subjective, but contain an element of reason and a certain empirical basis. I would probably have divided the positions differently, e.g. making use of the distinction between cognitive and non-cognitive theories (Snævarr considers subjective theories non-cognitive, but they may of course also be cognitively relativist, e.g. if you claim that A good work of art is a work that pleases me ). And I would have used the term sceptical in a more specific fashion than Snævarr does. I am tempted to say that he could have been much more precise in defining the various positions. The last chapter is about the question of whether art is autonomous, liberated from any kind of social, political or moral connection. Snævarr starts out with a discussion about the existence of a special aesthetic experience, based on Edward Bullough s well-known essay on Psychical Distance from 1912 (and with Dickie s criticism of the concept). It is an important discussion, but I do not really see the relevance in connection with the autonomy of art. In general I must confess that I have trouble taking the whole question of autonomy (and l art pour l art etc.) seriously because of its essentialistic foundation. Of course art is nothing in itself, and every single person is free to decide whether she wants to focus on aesthetic or moral aspects of a work of art. I imagine that Snævarr here thinks the way I do, but strangely enough he does not make his position clear in this chapter. He restricts himself to giving a series of adequate presentations of the positions of various contributors to the theme and of their mutual discussions, and only at the end he surprisingly suggests an essentialistic stance. It may e.g. be the case that instrumental music is close to autonomous (p. 275), he writes; he does not seem to know the story of how in Italy in the middle of the 19th century just to whistle a theme by Verdi could mean making a political statement because of Verdi s well-known political position, and because his name could be understood as an acronym of Vittorio Emmanuele, Re d Italia (Victor Emmanuel, King of Italy). But right after this unlucky remark about 161

Søren Kjørup instrumental music, Snævarr wraps up the whole book with an insipid observation that it may all be as in the Bible: There is a time for everything, a time for seeing art as autonomous, a time for seeing it as a tool of morals, etc. I hope that my reader has understood that Snævarr s book is full of interesting material, even though it may also contain some annoying aspects. For me he gets a high score for his mixture of oral language and perceptive presentations and discussions. Then one must bear with the places where he just rattles off some standard material he may not even quite master himself, or which he does not manage to communicate to anybody, especially not to newcomers (e.g. the list of actants of Greimas, p. 225). And one must bear with the fact that he is not quite precise everywhere. This is probably not because he wants his text the way it is he is, e.g. quite keen on mentioning sources and giving references (to both original, yet often reprinted, editions and to texts translated into Scandinavian languages). I guess it may be because he remembers wrongly as he goes along (as one often does in free lectures), or maybe it is because he now and then renders his own, somewhat worn, pedagogical version of a point, rather than revisiting the original source to see what it would reveal. But mostly, he masters his material in a convincing way. I, for one, have the special pleasure of seeing that he (contrary to some other Scandinavian commentators) has noticed the radical differences between the institutional theory of art that I introduced in my book Æstetiske problemer (Problems in Aesthetics) in 1971, and Dickie s much better known version from nearly the same year. Here at the end one small reservation (which concerns not only Snævarr s book, but many other contributions to its field): The text demonstrates quite clearly that Snævarr both masters and takes delight in the philosophy of art. But he presents this field nearly without mentioning the scholarly disciplines on the various arts (literary studies, art history, musicology etc.), even though they (at least in my view) overlap with aesthetics and are much closer connected with the purpose of it all, namely making us understand and enjoy actual works of art. And even more intriguing: does Snævarr take any delight in the arts themselves? Google can provide us with the information that he has published several volumes of poems in Icelandic, and his text does suggest that literary fiction (and probably also music) is closer to his heart than the unenthusiastically treated visual arts. (And at least he is very much engaged in Old Icelandic writings and several times picks on the Polish-Norwegian 162

Review cultural studies professor Nina Witoszek for some nonsense that she, in his view, has written about the concept of nature in the Edda and the Sagas). Somehow his book reveals a strange absence of delight in the visual arts and of concrete examples of painting and sculpture, except for some trite standard cases like Mona Lisa and Skrik (The Scream) plus what the discussed theoreticians have referred to. On the cover of the book we see a reproduction of a marvellous painting of a young girl by Ernst Ludwig Kirschner, but nothing of the kind plays any role in the text. søren kjørup Note 1. Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: The Analytic Tradition, ed. Peter Lamarque and Stein Haugom Olsen (Malden, MA: Blackwell, 2004), 19 26, 20. 163