ON REPEAT

Similar documents
genesis in kant notes

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Glen Carlson Electronic Media Art + Design, University of Denver

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

A Study of the Bergsonian Notion of <Sensibility>

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Human Finitude and the Dialectics of Experience

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to

Paintings Surface : Thomas Scheibitz meets Deleuze

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

LATOUR, LE CORBUSIER AND SPIRIT OF THE TIME.

Subjective Universality in Kant s Aesthetics Wilson

Hegel and Neurosis: Idealism, Phenomenology and Realism

From Deleuze to Conceptual Art: on the Demystification of the Artistic Object and the Creative Process

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

From Individuality to Universality: The Role of Aesthetic Education in Kant

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

A Kantian Critique of Positive Aesthetics of Nature

Theorem 4: Autonomy Can It Be True of Art and Politics at the Same Time?

Georg Simmel's Sociology of Individuality

1/10. The A-Deduction

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Lecture 7: Incongruent Counterparts

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

James Williams PARRHESIA NUMBER

The Second Copernican Turn of Kant s Philosophy 1

The Kantian and Hegelian Sublime

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

observation and conceptual interpretation

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

Immanuel Kant s Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation between Sensibility and Understanding Wendell Allan Marinay

A RE-INTERPRETATION OF ARTISTIC MODERNISM WITH EMPHASIS ON KANT AND NEWMAN DANNY SHORKEND

Working with Deleuze and Laruelle : The Non-Philosophical Use of Philosophical Concepts. Ashley Woodward

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

SOULISTICS: METAPHOR AS THERAPY OF THE SOUL

The Concept of Nature

c. MP claims that this is one s primary knowledge of the world and as it is not conscious as is evident in the case of the phantom limb patient

New York University Department of Media, Culture, and Communication Special Topics in Cultural and Visual Studies: DELEUZE S AESTHETICS FALL 2012

objectivity. I set out this theory of objective interpretation and explain the concept of 'locatedness' with reference to Kant and Deleuze. In additio

ON GESTURAL MEANING IN ACTS OF EXPRESSION

Revitalising Old Thoughts: Class diagrams in light of the early Wittgenstein

presented by beauty partners Davines and [ comfort zone ] ETHICAL ATLAS creating shared values

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Self-Consciousness and Knowledge

Art and Anxiety, or: Lacan with Joyce. Professor Ruth Ronen

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

THE DIDACTIC PROCESS AT THE ATELIER OF SCULPTURE, PREPARED FOR STUDENTS OF ARCHITECTURE

DELEUZE AND KANT S CRITICAL PHILOSOPHY

ArtsECO Scholars Joelle Worm, ArtsECO Director. NAME OF TEACHER: Ian Jack McGibbon LESSON PLAN #1 TITLE: Structure In Sculpture NUMBER OF SESSIONS: 2

A System of Heterogenesis: Deleuze on Plurality

Key Term: Anti-Kantian Aesthetics. Peter Blouw. Innovative, influential, and always somewhat controversial, Immanuel Kant s

Categories and Schemata

No Proposition can be said to be in the Mind, which it never yet knew, which it was never yet conscious of. (Essay I.II.5)

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

LANGUAGE THROUGH THE LENS OF HERACLITUS'S LOGOS

The Unfolding of Intellectual Conversion

Aesthetic Experience: Is it Viable in Contemporary Education?

Cazeaux, C. (2011). Introduction to Immanuel Kant, in C. Cazeaux (ed.), The Continental Aesthetics Reader, 2nd edition, Abingdon: Routledge, 3 9.

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Paper 2-Peer Review. Terry Eagleton s essay entitled What is Literature? examines how and if literature can be

Deleuze, Thompson and Jonas: Toward a New Transcendental Aesthetic and a New Question of Panpsychism


Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Metaphor in English Advertisement Analysis Based on the Conceptual Integration Theory

CUST 100 Week 17: 26 January Stuart Hall: Encoding/Decoding Reading: Stuart Hall, Encoding/Decoding (Coursepack)

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

I Three Intersections Between Aesthetics and Ethics

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Linda M. G. Zerilli. "We feel our freedom": Imagination and Judgment in the Thought of Hannah Arendt [06_2004]

Literary Theory and Literary Criticism Prof. Aysha Iqbal Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

AP English Literature 1999 Scoring Guidelines

The Role of Imagination in Kant's Theory of Reflective Judgment. Johannes Haag

Ingenium and the navigation metaphor: an examination of the power of metaphor as a manifestation of ingenium

Kant s Formalism? Distinguishing between Aesthetic Judgment and an Overall Response to Art in the Critique of Judgment

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Transcription:

ON REPEAT 21.09-26.10. 2018 1

GENIUS AND GENESIS Magdalena Wisniowska Independent researcher, project space leader and artist, Munich, DE Meister The problem of originality was first brought to my attention about a year ago. I went to see an exhibition by Tim Bennett at Jo van de Loo, entitled Me-is-----ter. 1 A play on the title of his previous work Time is a waste, it is also the German word for master, both in the sense of a master craftsman, and of the genius, creator of the master-piece. The work too seemed to recall modernism at its height, consisting as it did, of a series of paintings made by pouring plaster through gypsum board, Jackson Pollock style, and waiting for it to settle around the studio debris. The paintings were accompanied by sculpture, which had a similar modernist quality. Here plinth-like marble blocks were chiselled away by the artist, the broken pieces gathered and quickly reassembled on top. In both cases the narrative was the same: the work was to be the modernist masterpiece, created by the artist s sudden spark of originality. It was precisely this modernist narrative that I found troubling. Bennett s exhibition made me realise how effective the kind of poststructuralist critique of originality, embodied by Rosalind s Krauss s essay, The Originality of the Avant-garde (1985) actually was. No one in the art world talks about originality however appealing to the art-market the concept may be. Looking around, it is safe to assume we are all non-original now. 1 http://galerie-jovandeloo.com/exhibition/me-is-----ter 2

Figure 1. Tim Bennett, Me-is ter, 2016, Jan van de Loo Figure 2 (left). Me-is ter," showing Time is a Waste (rose), 2016 with Conspiracy Cloud (grey) 2016 (125 x 90, plaster, studio debris, acrylic and plasterboard) in the background. Figure 3 (right). Me-is-----ter," showing Time is a Waste (rose), 2016 with Time is a Waste and Time is a Waste (bouquet) Two Conspiracy Clouds are in the background. In philosophy however and especially that of Giles Deleuze the concept of originality still maintains a certain currency. I am thinking of his early works, the short book 3

on Kant, Kant s Critical Philosophy and the essay, The Idea of Genesis in Kant s Aesthetics in particular. As other commentators have also shown, the genetic principle he finds in Kant s third critique, specifically in the free and indeterminate accord of the faculties, serves as a basis for the transcendental empiricism he later develops in works such as Difference and Repetition and The Logic of Sense. 2 But despite referring in these works to the concept of genius, Deleuze only does so within the set-up of transcendental empiricism. He explicitly does not mention art. For at stake is not so much the work the genius is said to create, but the conditions of experience that the genius is tasked with communicating, and whether or not these are adequate to the intense world of differences that according to Deleuze lay behind the being of the sensible. The question is: Does Deleuze s work on originality have any relevance for our discussion about contemporary art? What would it mean to bring the above philosophical debate back to painting and sculpture? And doing so in a critical context where the concept of originality holds little or no value? It seems to me, that if we are to take the problem of originality seriously and not to dismiss it as either irrelevant or outmoded, a kind of double cross-examination must take place, of Deleuze by Krauss, and Krauss by Deleuze. To engage with Deleuze s genetic perspective, while bearing in mind the poststructuralist critique of originality this is the task of this short text. Krauss And Originality Before we begin, it is worthwhile to briefly summarise the relevant sections of Krauss s critique. Rosalind Krauss published The Originality of the Avant-garde as a response to the then recent exhibition of Augustus Rodin at the National Gallery in Washington, and the gallery s decision to cast some work for the first time. The section that concerns us most is part two, where Krauss examines the modernist concept of originality, relative to its opposite, repetition. In this section, Krauss first connects the concept of originality to the historic avantgarde of the early 20 th century. Finding it synonymous with the avant-garde s efforts to break away with tradition and to establish the new, Krauss argues that it stands for origin, ground 2 Daniel W. Smith is one of the first Deleuze readers to put forward this argument in his essay Deleuze s Theory of Sensation: Overcoming the Kantian Duality (30-56). Levi R. Bryant elaborates what such a transcendental materialism may consist of in Deleuze s Transcendental Empiricism: Notes toward a Transcendental Materialism (28-48). Joe Hughes in his introduction to Difference and Repetition makes a similar point, Deleuze s Difference and Repetition: A Readers Guide. 4

zero, birth (156). She shows how it is identified with the figure of the artist, capable of such continual acts of regeneration. However, when Krauss examines actual avant-garde art practices, instead of originality she finds recurrence and repetition. For Krauss, this is exemplified by the modernist artist s use of the grid. As Krauss argues, certain inherent structural properties of grid make it susceptible to vanguard appropriation, resulting in artist after artist claiming the grid as their own unique discovery. For those artists who believe that art should begin in an original purity, it is the disinterest and purposelessness of the grid that facilitates the sense of being born afresh. For others more materially inclined, the grid brings about the unity of the pictorial surface and material ground, which they believe lies at the origin of art. Rosalind Krauss argues that this sense of originality, whether this is the originality associated with the artist or the originality of the surface, is a myth. Avant-garde artists may claim the grid as their own, but history shows that the grid has no one inventor. Similarly, fictional is the original unity of material ground and pictorial surface that the grid is said to manifest. While the grid traces the same surface it represents, it is nonetheless a representation of that surface. In picturing its various qualities, the grid obscures rather than reveals this surface. Furthermore, the grid as a means of organising the pictorial field logically comes prior to any given surface. In Krauss s semiotic language, every instance of the grid invokes a preexisting system of grids, a visual text summarising other visual texts. Far from being unified, the grid s ground is divided and multiple. Krauss ends by comparing the modernist viewpoint with her own semiotic perspective. For modernism to claim that the grid presents an original unity of pictorial surface and material ground, it must operate in a space of auto-referentiality. Only within such a space can the grid signify nothing other than itself and become reified. In contrast, Krauss shows that the grid represents the pictorial surface, its signifier being located in another prior system of grids, which in turn signifies an even earlier one. With its endless chain of references, she characterises this signifier as transparent. Concluding in a manner that seems to foreshadow Deleuze s transcendental empiricism, Krauss argues that it is repetition rather than originality that is the real condition of the grid s use in avant-garde practice. Modernism by valorising originality is only responsible for the repression of this fact. 5

What makes Krauss s critique so convincing is not that she dismisses originality as an outmoded concept, but that she shows the concept itself to be structurally, logically and axiomatically unsound. Although an artist like Tim Bennett does not incorporate the grid in his work, by engaging with the narrative of genius, he participates in the discourse of originality shown to be flawed. Deleuze And Genesis On the other hand, Deleuze s work on originality takes a very different approach. For one, he does not discuss art, modernist or otherwise. Instead, the essay The Idea of Genesis in Kant s Aesthetics offers a brief but succinct introduction to Kantian aesthetics, its central thesis, that Kant s Critique of Judgement does not complete the other two Critiques but instead provides them with a genetic ground. 3 How it does so, is precisely what is of interest to us. Central to its thesis is Kant s definition of the aesthetic judgement of taste as the feeling of pleasure resulting from a relationship of the faculties of understanding and of imagination, in which the first is indeterminate and the second is free. Precisely because this agreement of the faculties is indeterminate and free, it comes prior to the legislation of a determinative faculty, whether this is understanding or reason, which occurs when this relationship has a speculative or a practical purpose. According to Deleuze, the faculties would not enter into a relationship determined by one of themselves, were it not, to begin with, that they were capable of a free and indeterminate relation. 4 The relationship in question is not something given, as was the case with the categories or ideas of Kant s previous two critiques, but engendered. It is internally generative of what it conditions, rather than transcendent and external. Accordingly, the third critique s structure is determined by the three ways in which free and indeterminate accord of 3 I am not the first to make to this argument Deleuze s post-kantian critique is well-known. See Joe Hughes book on Kant, Deleuze and the Genesis of Representation (16-18) for a quick summary. A more extensive (and non-phenomelogical) approach can be found in Conditions of Thought Deleuze and Transcendental Ideas by Daniela Voss. 4 As an aside, it is also interesting to think of the link between Kant s definition and the subject of the current conference, the zone of indeterminacy Deleuze describes in What is Philosophy (173). Specified as that which is only sensation (Ibid.), it is possible to trace back this zone of living, whirling beings to the indeterminate and free accord of the faculties, their state of free play which likewise, can only be felt (Kant 62). 6

understanding and imagination is internally brought about. I will briefly summarise all three, because of how this affects our understanding of originality. Deleuze argues that the basic principles of how the free and indeterminate accord is engendered can be found in the experience of the sublime, this experience offering a basic template that the two other ways of engendering accord will follow. All three are predicated on what is discovered in the sublime, that this genetic principle involves the activity of reason, whereby reason attempts to present its non-sensible ideas in the sensible realm. In the case of the sublime this happens when imagination is confronted with something beyond its powers of comprehension. As a consequence, reason steps in as the faculty of super-sensible thought, capable of comprehending what imagination cannot. In doing so, reason also raises imagination to its transcendental function, as the faculty capable of representing ideas of reason negatively. The resulting feeling is what is described as the sublime, a supra-sensible unity, in which both of the faculties involved are enriched. The experience of certain type of nature brings about a comparable relation. In this second case, nature provides us with objects, which allow us to reflect in a free and indeterminate manner. Nature has what Deleuze calls a rational purpose ( The Idea of Genesis in Kant s Esthetics 63-66). Interestingly the example Kant lists and Deleuze refers to, free formation or crystalisation, (Kant 222, The Idea of Genesis in Kant s Esthetics 65) is not dissimilar looks-wise to the random plaster shapes of Tim Bennett s Conspiracy Clouds. The idea that in these objects reason finds a means of presenting its ideas sensibly is also recognised by Bennett, the conspiracy of the title referring to the possibility of seeing different things within. This reflective activity of reason, once again unifies and enriches the other two faculties, because it extends the concepts of understanding and frees the imagination from conceptual determination. Finally, the last of the three ways engendering accord is genius. Operating according to a meta-aesthetic principle analogous to that defined by rational purpose, genius is responsible for the creation of objects, which allow for the reflective activity of our faculties the same way as certain natural objects do. In the objects created by genius reason can once again present its ideas sensibly. If in the instance of the sublime, ideas of reason were presented directly but negatively in imagination s struggle for comprehension, and in the mode defined by rational purpose, indirectly but positively through the experience of certain natural objects, in the case of genius, ideas are presented positively through the creation of an other nature (( The Idea of Genesis in Kant s Esthetics 66). And as was the case where 7

natural objects were found to be beautiful, the reflective activity of reason mobilises further activity of the other two faculties, imagination and understanding. We can see many different things in the broken pieces of Time is a Waste and that in itself is said to be stimulating of further mental activity. This is art and this would be the genius of Tim Bennett s work, in that he is able to produce objects that inspire reflective activity, but such an interpretation would overlook Krauss s critique. If we are to engage with the narrative of genius in a comprehensive manner, we must take both arguments into account. Originality And Genesis When doing so, it is easy to dismiss Deleuze as yet another example of someone, who upholds the modernist myth of originality and all that this entails. Like Krauss s archetypal avant-garde artist, Deleuze conceives of originality as an absolute origin or beginning, the free and indeterminate agreement of the faculties found in aesthetic judgement being the ground for further activities of these same faculties. He too, by locating genetic ground in the mental faculties of the human subject identifies this originality with the self. The play of faculties, which extends understanding and frees imagination, is comparable to what Krauss calls sources of life (156). As Deleuze writes, Genius vitalizes. It gives life ( The Idea of Genesis in Kant s Esthetics 67). In both cases, the organist metaphor is the same. Similarly, the way Deleuze defines the work of art also has this modernist character. Remembering Krauss s critique, it is partially the disinterestedness and purposelessness of the grid that facilitates the mistaken sense of origin. Likewise, by sharing the same metaesthetic principle as rational purpose found in nature, genius participates in nature s goal-lessness. Just as the rational purpose of nature has no goal (otherwise we could determine in advance what beautiful objects are) the work of genius has no precedent and cannot be learned. Kant famously describes the free and indeterminate play of the faculties constituting the judgment of taste as disinterested (Critique of Judgment 45-6) Deleuze s genetic account is based on this disinterest. However, a distinction needs to be made between the two concepts, originality and genesis, especially as presented by Deleuze. While Deleuze occasionally does use the term, original in the genetic sense to describe the free and indeterminate agreement of the faculties ( The Idea of Genesis in Kant s Esthetics 60), it remains something he tends to associate with the activities of the faculties, when these are neither indeterminate nor free, 8

when these activities serve a purpose (Ibid. 57, 58, 59). For instance, in the Critique of Pure Reason, imagination schematizes and that is perceived as its original function (Ibid. 57, 59). But imagination only schematizes when it is given direction by the faculty of understanding. There is therefore a vast difference between imagination s original schematizing activity and the original free activity of imagination found in the aesthetic judgment of taste. In the first case, originality belongs to the domain of the Critique of Pure Reason, where the faculties are readymade, relations determinate and tasks organized under the direction of the one legislative faculty. In the second case, originality is identified with a process of genesis that comes prior to such organization and coherency. In genesis, whether this is of the sublime, of the rational purpose connected to the beautiful or of genius, the faculties are primeval, the relations between them are indeterminate and free, and all activity is without constraint. The difference between the two senses of the term original comes down to the human subject, or rather the lack of it. There is no human subject in the three geneses of the Critique of Judgment, only the soul (Ibid. 60, 62, 63, 66, 69, 70). Following Kant, Deleuze describes the free and indeterminate agreement of the faculties found in the aesthetic judgement of taste as the ground of the soul (Ibid. 60). As the relation between the faculties in free agreement is different to the relation, when this agreement serves a purpose, it is to be expected that the kind of subject these relations constitute is also different. The soul is not the I, the self, or even the human subject of the first two critiques. The soul is a point of concentration (Ibid. 69) a moment when the faculties discover the principle of their genesis, when faculties engender and animate each other. When pushed to its limits in the confrontation with the sublime, imagination awakens reason (Ibid. 62). Reason in turn pushes imagination to surpass its limits and represent the inaccessibility of the rational Idea. The soul is a state of continual excitement and growth. The way Deleuze understands the difference between originality and genesis, makes the two logics, the logic of originality and the logic of genesis, non-comparable. Krauss s essay is meant to demonstrate that what originality stands for origin, absolute ground and continual renewal has its basis in its opposite, recurrence and repetition. In having no inventor and belonging to a pre-existing system of signification, the grid exemplifies this misconception. It shows that repetition rather than originality is the real condition of its use in avant-garde practice. On the other hand, for Deleuze the genesis involved in the aesthetic judgment of taste, the indeterminate agreement of the faculties that comes prior to any other 9

relation dictated by purpose, sets a ground for further activity. In terms of transcendental empiricism, it is the real, rather than just the possible, condition of experience. It is, what in Krauss s logic would be impossible, the unconditional. The two meanings of originality are non-comparable because they are non-equivalent. The originality rejected by Krauss is not the same as the genetic origin pursued by Deleuze, the first conditioned twofold, the second unconditional. Indeed, originality as Deleuze understands it, is closer in principle to the repetition Krauss associates with the structure and logic of the grid. As Krauss argues, the originality claimed for the grid is illusionary in two ways. On the one hand, the artist cannot pretend to be original, when what he creates is nothing more than a pre-existing historical structure. On the other hand, the grid as a representational text precedes the surface it is meant to reveal, a summary of all other visual texts through which the bound plane was organized as a pictorial field. However we view the grid, whether as the artist s creation or as a way of structuring the pictorial surface, it comes prior to the originality it is said to embody such is its repetitive nature. Would it be such a leap to say that the grid in its repetition engenders these claims of originality? In light of Krauss s conclusion, that repetition is a condition of originality? Krauss by being so keen to dismiss originality for being wrongly valorized, fails to see that repetition has an original, because a genetic component. Genius, providing it is seen as participating in logic of genesis, not originality, would then fall outside of Krauss s critique. Here we come full circle back to Tim Bennett s work. As much as his work could be dismissed for upholding concepts of originality shown to be flawed, it also has a genetic quality. In the gestures he employs, the genetic principle such as identified by Deleuze is at work. This is one that engenders, that makes things happen. For when Tim Bennett pours plaster, or quickly and haphazardly glues broken marble pieces together, he makes no claims of originality. It is not he who is the creative genius. Rather responsibility is shifted to the gestures themselves. And these always belong to someone else, to Pollock or to Giacometti to a long history of modernism. But he recognizes that it is precisely in their repetition, that they can hold creative potential. References Bryant, Levi A. 2009. Deleuze s Transcendental Empiricism: Notes toward a Transcendental Materialism. Thinking between Deleuze and Kant, A Strange Encounter. Ed. Edward Willat and Matt Lee. London: Continuum, 28-48. 10

Deleuze, Gilles. 2012. The Logic of Sense. Ed. Constantin V. Boundas. Trans. Mark Lester. London: Continuum. Deleuze, Gilles. 2009. Difference and Repetition. Trans. Paul Patton. London: Continuum. Deleuze, Gilles. 2008. Kant s Critical Philosophy. Trans. Hugh Tomlinson and Barbara Habberjam. London: Continuum. Deleuze, Giles. 2004. The Idea of Genesis in Kant s Esthetics. Desert Islands and Other Texts, 1953-1974. Ed. David Lapoujade. Trans. Michael Taomina. CA: Semiotext(e), 56-71. Deleuze, Gilles and Guattari, Félix. 1994. What is Philosophy? Trans. Graham Burchell and Hugh Tomlinson. London: Verso. Hughes, Joe. 2009. Deleuze s Difference and Repetition: A Readers Guide. London: Continuum. Hughes, Joe. 2008. Deleuze and the Genesis of Representation. London: Continuum. Kant, Immanuel. 1996. Critique of Pure Reason. Trans. Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett. Kant, Immanuel. Critique of Judgement. Trans. Werner S. Pluhar. Indianapolis: Hackett, 1987. Krauss, Rosalind. The Originality of the Avant-Garde. The Originality of the Avant-Garde and Other Modernist Myths. Cambridge: MIT Press, 1986. 151-70. Smith, Daniel W. Deleuze s Theory of Sensation: Overcoming the Kantian Duality. Deleuze: A Critical Reader. Ed. Paul Patton. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers, 1996. 30-56. Voss, Daniela. Conditions of Thought: Deleuze and Transcendental Ideas. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2013. Keywords Originality; genetic principle/genesis; genius; aesthetic judgement; free and indeterminate accord Bio Magdalena Wisniowska is an independent researcher, project space leader and artist, currently based in Munich. She had studied Fine Art at the Royal Academy in London and completed a PhD in Visual Cultures at Goldsmiths College, London in 2010. A participant in the conference, Aesthetics of the 21 st Century, in 2012, her essays on speculative realism and Deleuzian aesthetics have been published as part of Speculations, in Deleuze Studies and in SubStance. Since 2015 she has been running an art project space, GiG Munich. Email: gigmunich@gmail.com Web: www.gigmunich.com 11

12