Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Similar documents
KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

1/10. The A-Deduction

1/9. The B-Deduction

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Categories and Schemata

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Human Finitude and the Dialectics of Experience

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

The Case for Absolute Spontaneity in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason. La defensa de la espontaneidad absoluta en la Crítica de la razón pura de Kant

Summary of the Transcendental Ideas

The Concept of Nature

The Role of the Form/Content Distinction in Hegel's Science of Logic

HEGEL S IDEALISM. Robert Stern

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Universities of Leeds, Sheffield and York

Georg W. F. Hegel ( ) Responding to Kant

Please cite the published version in Human Studies, available at Springer via

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

The Unfolding of Intellectual Conversion

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

Kant s Critique of Judgment

KANT S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

NATURAL IMPURITIES IN SPIRIT? HEGELIANISM BETWEEN KANT AND HOBBES Heikki Ikäheimo

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Taylor On Phenomenological Method: An Hegelian Refutation

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Ridgeview Publishing Company

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

Hegel's Absolute: An Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

KANT'S TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION: AN ANALYTICAL-HISTORICAL COMMENTARY BY HENRY E. ALLISON

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

The Role of Imagination in Kant's Theory of Reflective Judgment. Johannes Haag

observation and conceptual interpretation

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

Philosophical Foundations of Mathematical Universe Hypothesis Using Immanuel Kant

Pure and Applied Geometry in Kant

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

Kant and the Problem of Experience

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Is Hegel s Logic Logical?

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Subjective Universality in Kant s Aesthetics Wilson

The aim of this paper is to explore Kant s notion of death with special attention paid to

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Kant on Unity in Experience

Hegel and Neurosis: Idealism, Phenomenology and Realism

dialectica The Place of Subjects in the Metaphysics of Material Objects

Chapter Two. Absolute Identity: Hegel s Critique of Reflection

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

Review of S. J. McGrath and Joseph Carew (eds.). Rethinking German Idealism, London: Palgrave Macmillan, pp.

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

Hegel on Consciousness The Opening Chapters of A Spirit of Trust : A Semantic Reading of Hegel s Phenomenology Bob Brandom

KANT, SELF-AWARENESS AND SELF-REFERENCE

Critical Political Economy of Communication and the Problem of Method

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Philosophy of History

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

The Place of Logic within Kant s Philosophy

Hegelian Analytic Philosophy According to P. Redding*

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Foucault's Technologies of the Self: A Kantian Project?

Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. 10, No. 1. (Sep., 1949), pp

The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and Reason by Mark Johnson, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987

Practical Action First Critique Foundations *

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

The concept of capital and the determination of the general and uniform rates of profit: a reappraisal

Kant: Critique of Pure Reason

Aristotle s Modal Syllogistic. Marko Malink. Cambridge Harvard University Press, Pp X $ 45,95 (hardback). ISBN:

Hegel, Subjectivity, and Metaphysics: A Heideggerean Interpretation

From Individuality to Universality: The Role of Aesthetic Education in Kant

Transcription:

How Kantian Was Hegel? Author(s): Terry Pinkard Source: The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 43, No. 4 (Jun., 1990), pp. 831-838 Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20128947 Accessed: 13-11-2016 14:07 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://about.jstor.org/terms Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Metaphysics

CRITICAL EXCHANGE HOW KANTIAN WAS HEGEL? TERRY PINKARD JLt is a truism that hegel took much of his program from Kant, but it has always been a matter of great dispute as to just what he took, how much he took, and how much he altered and added to the Kantian program. Since Kant is currently at a high point in ac ceptance in Anglo-American philosophical circles, a fresh look at Hegel's adoption and criticisms of that program will perhaps not only shed new light on Hegel but also point the way to a new inte gration of Hegelian themes in contemporary thought. In Hegel's Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Consciousness, Robert Pippin goes a long way to doing just that. Pippin provides a balanced philo sophical account of Hegel and his program by arguing, among other things, that Hegel's work should be understood as a transformation of the Kantian idea of deriving all the conditions of knowledge from the transcendental unity of apperception, a special kind of self-con scious awareness of objects.1 The results are impressive. In elaborating Hegel's system, Pippin ascribes two Kantian theses to Hegel, which I shall call the "Apperception Thesis" and the "Transcendental Thesis." On Pippin's view, Hegel's program should be broadly construed in something like the following way: Hegel carries forward the Kantian program of constructing the cat egories without which we could have no conceptual scheme at all 1 Robert Pippin, HegeVs Idealism: The Satisfactions of Self-Conscious ness (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1988). Unless otherwise noted, page references in the text are to this book. One caveat to the reader: Pippin's book is an extraordinarily rich reading of Hegel, both in his use of historical material and textual reconstruction as well as in his general philosophical argument. As in all short exchanges, I am focusing on some very general features of the book at the expense of the richness of its detail. Review of Metaphysics 43 (June 1990): 831-838. Copyright? 1990 by the Review of Metaphysics

832 TERRY PINKARD (the Transcendental Thesis), and, like Kant, he locates the principle of that reconstruction in the conditions of self-conscious awareness of objects (the Apperception Thesis).2 Hegel departs from Kant in rejecting the dependence of thought on intuition, and in adding a social, intersubjective dimension to the categories. (Pippin defends this in a particularly good section on Hegel's Phenomenology of Spirit.) Hegelian absolute idealism thus finally ends up being more like contemporary antirealism than like the subjective idealism of Kant's philosophy. This forms Pippin's ambitious attempt to make sense of one of the most problematic aspects of Hegel scholarship: the relation of the Phenomenology of Spirit to the rest of the system. This is more than of merely parochial interest to Hegel scholars; it is important for anyone who wants to make a reasoned judgment on the value of the Hegelian program. The problem is that Hegel said many dif ferent things about the Phenomenology in his various works, and it remains unclear where it fits in his thought. On one reading, it is the presupposition of the rest of his system, and the whole system stands or falls with the success of the Phenomenology. On another reading, it is just a youthful work that he later mostly abandoned, reworking nonetheless a small part of it into the mature system. Pippin might seem to be on his strongest ground in his inter pretation of the Phenomenology in terms of the Apperception Thesis. There he offers an intriguing account of how Hegel transformed the Kantian idea of rationality into a more social account and how he substituted a developing historical subject for the abstract Kantian transcendental unity of the I. However, the attempt to impose the Apperception Thesis on the Logic?indeed, on the mature system as 2 Pippin takes this apperceptive principle to be that "consciousness can be said to be in relation to an object only in the sense that it takes itself to be" in such a relation (p. 114). This means: "For anything to count as a representation of mine, I must be self-consciously representing such an object, implicitly taking myself to be representing thusly" (p. 132). In Hegel's transformation, however, Pippin argues that the Kantian claims about the apperceptive conditions of self-consciousness become transmuted into the claim that "participating in a practice can count as such only if the practice is undertaken... within... the 'horizon' of assumptions taken by the participants to be those assumptions" (p. 152). Thus, the self-relation, or apperception, necessary for a determinate cognitive relation to objects is possible only under certain types of intersubjectivity (p. 158). Kantian rationality thus becomes socially construed.

HOW KANTIAN WAS HEGEL? 833 a whole?is more strained than it is when applied purely to the Phenomenology. Why? The apperceptive principle is most clearly at home where Kant had it, namely, in discussing our conscious awareness of objects.3 Where Pippin's interpretation strains is on the point of whether the principles appropriate for the philosophy of consciousness (with its inherent opposition of subject and object) are appropriate for the consideration of dialectical thought, in which such an opposition is supposed to be overcome. This is a crucial difference. Consciousness may be reflexively aware of itself, but thought subsumes and refers to itself; the former concerns the struc ture of our psychology, whereas the latter is more "logical" in nature. Pippin's use of the Apperception Thesis ultimately must fail to explain Hegel's systematic goals. Perhaps it explains why the Phe nomenology would precede the Logic, but it is difficult to see why Hegel's system would require a Logic at all (much less the Encyclo paedia system that follows the Logic). Most importantly, its failure to capture the Hegelian distinction of consciousness and thought also fails to capture the sense in which Hegel saw his system as being that in which "substance" becomes "subject." I would take this to be something like the following. The Logic begins with the categories in which we articulate the conceptions of individuals as differentiated from each other with respect to their quantitative and qualitative features (the "Doctrine of Being"). It gives way to a logic of substructural explanation of superstructural appearance (the "Doctrine of Essence"). This ends in an account of a world of substances interacting causally with each other, the whole system of which is the world-substance. Now, while this causal system could perhaps be said to be self-explanatory (causa sui, as Spinoza described it), it could never be self-subsuming. Self-subsumption 3 The Phenomenology concerns appearing (erscheinende) knowledge, that is, the knowledge involved in the opposition between our consciousness and the objects of which it is aware. The purpose of the Phenomenology is to delineate and order the possible forms that such an opposition of consciousness can take. After it has run through all the possible forms, the Phenomenology depicts a consciousness that reaches the stage at which it has no relation to an object at all. A consciousness without a relation to an object, however, is no longer consciousness at all but thought thinking about itself. Since this thought is self-mediating (it has no object to me diate it), it is therefore "absolute" and is thus ready to begin the Logic. Pippin takes the view that the Logic nonetheless presupposes the Phenom enology. I take issue with this later in this paper.

834 TERRY PINKARD is a logical relation among concepts. Thus, we must go beyond "Substance" to the categories of conceptual, inferential thought, that is, "Subject." Logic thus culminates in the conception of self subsuming, self-explanatory thought, namely, the Idea. It was this move that Hegel thought Kant had implicitly made but had mistakenly restricted to forms of consciousness.4 The sys tematic conclusions he drew are the following. Although the Logic concludes with an account of thought's self-reflexivity, it does not tell us how this "thought" is connected to human minds. For that, a Philosophy of the Real (Realphilosophie) is required, which cul minates in a conception of Absolute Spirit, that is, the human mind collectively reflecting on itself through the historical practices of art, religion, and philosophy. Spirit is the self-reflection of human minds, just as Idea is the self-reflection of thought. Where does the Phenomenology fit into this picture? It turns out to be the study of how we, determinate historical individuals and communities, have reached the cultural stage at which we understand ourselves as Spirit (communal subjectivity) and how we (determinate historical indi viduals) are now culturally ready for pure thought (the Logic). The Phenomenology is thus a study of how we have arrived historically at the stage at which we are ready to begin the systematic reflection that culminates first in Idea, then later in Absolute Spirit. Thus, not only is apperception not the key to Hegel's system, but seeing it as such will blind us to the systematic features that for Hegel were so important. I have even deeper misgivings about Pippin's Transcendental Thesis. By seeing Hegel's program in terms of the Transcendental Thesis, Pippin forces Hegel's idealist dialectic into two claims that 4 In Hegelian eyes, Kant's theory of the mind should be divided into two parts. First, there is the theory of "the" mind, in which it gets divided into a faculty of intuition and concept. Second, there is the theory as to how "the" mind is realized in human minds, namely, as our forms of sen sibility and our forms of understanding. If you drop the condition of intuition as a requirement of "the" mind (retaining it perhaps as a condition for human minds), then one gets something like the Hegelian Logic. In Hegel's view of a proper appreciation of Kant's achievement, we should understand that although our minds may be sensibility and understanding, "the" mind is only concept. The relevant Kantian text in this regard is Kant's celebrated footnote to?16 (B134n.) of the "Transcendental Deduc tion": "The synthetic unity of apperception is therefore that highest point, to which we must ascribe all employment of the understanding, even the whole of logic, and conformably therewith, transcendental philosophy."

HOW KANTIAN WAS HEGEL? 835 cannot, by Pippin's own admission, live up to what Hegel has to say about it. First, Hegel's claims to finality in the Science of Logic depend either on there being some kind of rigorous logical procedure called determinate negation (which is implausible, p. 255), or, just as bad, they depend on a prior and implicit assumption about thought's final self-understanding. Second, too many of Hegel's so called concepts required as a priori constraints on any possible con ceptual scheme are too specific and too contingent to be plausible constraints (p. 258). Pippin cites categories such as "elective affin ity" as examples of categories that are too specific to function as such a priori constraints. These concepts "cannot possibly be con sidered categorial results of thought's pure self-determination..." (p. 258). Since Hegel's dialectic cannot live up to these transcen dental claims, it must be considered a failure. This transcendentalized Hegel is fortunately not the only Hegel available. An alternative is to see Hegel's dialectic as an expla nation of the rational possibility of certain categories. The as sumption is that contradictory sets of categories are impossible (af ter all, the real is the rational), and one explains how a category is possible if one explains how both it and its apparently contradictory "other" are each compatible. Taken in that way, Hegel need not claim therefore that without the notions of "elective affinity" or "force" or the "mathematical infinite," we cannot have thought of the world. Of course we can. What we cannot have is that set of categories, along with consistent, coherent thought of the world. For example, Hegel thought that he could show that if one began, as Parmenides did, with the notion of Being itself, one could show that one could not have consistent thought unless one also supplemented that simple idea with a number of other categories. In that way, the set of categories found in the Logic can claim to be more than just one among many alternative sets. By beginning with the min imal presuppositions of a Parmenidean concept of Being and showing how the problems with it generate further categories, Hegel thought he could thereby also claim a kind of priority for his categories that had eluded other philosophers. This sees the Kantian legacy for Hegel, as does Pippin's reading, in the transcendental deduction of the categories, but it sees its importance not as a philosophy of the conditions of sel?-consciousness but of self-reflexive and self-sub suming thought. Hegel continues Kant's categorial program via similar means.

836 TERRY PINKARD In this light, we should also distinguish something's being a transcendental condition of apperceptive self-consciousness from something's being a condition of the way in which a particular type of self-consciousness is structured. In the mature system (and, in deed, in many sections of the Phenomenology), Hegel's use of "self consciousness" often seems to be more akin to ordinary notions of self-understanding than it is to Kantian notions of apperception. Thus, in Hegelian dialectic, there may be conditions for a certain type of self-consciousness to be attained that are not themselves conditions of self-consciousness in general but categorial conditions of that self-consciousness. This seems in fact to be the way in which the various categories of, for example, art and religion function (what Hegel calls Absolute Spirit): they structure the self-con sciousness of an age, but they are not transcendental conditions of apperceptive self-consciousness in any Kantian sense. As we might put it, in those sections, Hegel is not concerned with the transcen dental conditions of apperceptive self-consciousness per se (with the aspects of any conceptual scheme in general), but with the ways in which various types of self-consciousness (as self-understandings) may be coherent or consistent and with the ways in which the more or less logical problems they engender give rise to new solutions found in new forms of self-consciousness. (It should also be noted that this apperceptive reading will also make Hegel's extensive cat egorial treatment of natural science difficult to understand, as Pippin is aware [p. 263, note 20]. The treatment of the categories of natural science, however, are not a problem for the Hegelian theory inter preted as the explanation of possibility. New a priori categories in the natural sciences are introduced in a similar fashion to the way they are in the whole system.) Now, Pippin might reply that this is all well and good, but with out the Transcendental Thesis, Hegel is left completely open to Kierkegaard's devastating charge that the Logic was just an elab orate game of thought with no application to the real world. Even more strangely, it would make Hegel the theorist of rational pos sibility into the precursor of contemporary possible world theorists. For some, that would no doubt be sufficient grounds to banish Hegel to Twin Earth and be done with him forever. Much more needs to be said about this than can be done here, for it goes to the core of both Hegel's and Kant's projects. Indeed, it touches on many contemporary debates about realism, antirealism,

HOW KANTIAN WAS HEGEL? 837 and internal realism (the latter only being the idealism that dare not speak its name). The first part of Hegel's answer, I think, lies in his thesis that "the real is the rational, and the rational is the real." We can put that thesis like this: if something is a requirement of rational thought, then it is a requirement of things in themselves; moreover, there is nothing that is in principle not knowable by ra tional thought (there can be no categories of the real that we are incapable of understanding, no mysteries that lie in principle beyond our cognitive grasp). On my view, Hegelian dialectic may not give us the transcendental conditions of knowledge, but it can tell us what in our thought is consistent and coherent. The program of providing a self-subsuming, self-reflexive explanation of the rational possibility of the categories shows that the realist skeptical alter native (that the categories do not apply to things-in-themselves) is deficient as an explanation of those categories. The second part of Hegel's answer lies in his understanding of the rational criticism of these different forms of self-understanding in history, in that he argues that one can demonstrate that one is superior to another. Hegel's claims for his theory's being "absolute" (as being complete, consistent, self-subsuming, and self-reflexive) can perhaps be reconciled with its historically determinate character in the following way: the theory is complete in that it leaves out none of the relevant historically given categories; it is consistent in that no new contradictions appear in it to propel further moves in the dialectic; its basic principle (dialectical thought) is self-subsum ing and self-explanatory; but it may not be final in that new cate gories can arise in history that recast the present set and present new problems of possibility. Discussing this fully, alas, would take another paper just on its own.5 Both Pippin and I agree that Hegel's thought is best understood in terms of its carrying out the program of the Kantian transcen dental deduction of the categories. We also both agree that Hegel thought that in his system (1) each new category was necessary to avoid a contradiction, and (2) it was the only such category that could be posited. We both agree that a close reading of Hegel's texts leads one to the conclusion that, Hegel to the contrary, neither 51 offer an account of how this ties into Hegel's theses about the teleology of history in chapter 8 of Hegel's Dialectic: The Explanation of Possibility (Philadelphia: Temple University Press, 1988).

838 TERRY PINKARD (1) nor (2) is true. We disagree on where to go from there. I would argue that by reading Hegel in terms of the Transcendental Thesis, Pippin dooms Hegel from the outset, since Hegel quite clearly failed to show the conditions of any conceptual scheme at all. However, on the alternative view, we can endorse the idea of speculative di alectic as a method while nonetheless foregoing Hegel's necessitarian claims for it. We are then left with the task of constructing cate gorial claims simply in terms of how well they do their explanatory job. Likewise, I would argue that by reading all of Hegel's system in terms of the Apperception Thesis, Pippin loses the crucial dis tinction in the mature system between the principles of conscious ness and the principles of thought. However, on the alternative view, we can still see Hegel in terms of a very modified version of the Apperception Thesis?we can always see how the principles of thought are reflected in the consciousness of a period?and thus have our rich and nonmetaphysical Hegel without being subject to Pippin's criticisms of him as a transcendental theorist. We thus end up with a chastened and more Socratic Hegel who is nonetheless still recognizable as Hegel. Hegel the chastened dialectical idealist and theorist of self-consciousness remains intact. Even Hegel's celebrated historicism and his "philosophical history" can remain relatively undamaged. Both Pippin and I locate Hegel in a direct line from Kant. We agree where the line begins (in?16 of the "Transcendental Deduc tion"), but we disagree as to how the line is drawn, and consequently we would disagree, I think, about where the line ends up. Pippin's Apperception Thesis may still, perhaps, be maintained?albeit in a modified form?but why he would want to maintain the Transcen dental Thesis is beyond me. After all, the Transcendental Thesis makes Hegel so clearly wrong, and that is not Pippin's aim in his far-ranging study of Hegel's idealism. Georgetown University