Journal of Music Theory

Similar documents
Structure and voice-leading

Schenker s Elucidations on Unfolding Compound Voices from Der Tonwille 6 (1923) to Der freie Satz (1935)

BASIC CONCEPTS AND PRINCIPLES IN MODERN MUSICAL ANALYSIS. A SCHENKERIAN APPROACH

Readings Assignments on Counterpoint in Composition by Felix Salzer and Carl Schachter

Music 281: Music Theory III

William Pastille. Volume 1, Number 6, November 1995 Copyright 1995 Society for Music Theory. KEYWORDS: Schenker, valuation

Set Theory Based Analysis of Atonal Music

composition including, but not limited to, rhythm, prolongation, and form little

Calculating Dissonance in Chopin s Étude Op. 10 No. 1

Student Performance Q&A:

Example 1 (W.A. Mozart, Piano Trio, K. 542/iii, mm ):

Informal Introduction to Schenkerian Analysis techniques. a student primer. Glen C. Halls 2010

Course Objectives The objectives for this course have been adapted and expanded from the 2010 AP Music Theory Course Description from:

Übergreifen in Schenker s writings

Descending- and ascending- 5 6 sequences (sequences based on thirds and seconds):

MTO 15.2 Examples: Samarotto, Plays of Opposing Motion

MTO 21.4 Examples: Yust, Voice-Leading Transformation and Generative Theories of Tonal Structure

Student Performance Q&A: 2001 AP Music Theory Free-Response Questions

have several times experienced a sinking feeling upon reading the following passage from

Student Performance Q&A:

Lesson RRR: Dominant Preparation. Introduction:

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Volume 10, Number 4, December 2004 Copyright 2004 Society for Music Theory

Student Performance Q&A:

Counterpoint of Lines or Voices

COMPUTER ENGINEERING SERIES

MTO 18.4 Examples: Goldenberg, The Interruption-Fill and Corollary Procedures

PROLONGATION IN POST-TONAL MUSIC: A SURVEY OF ANALYTICAL TECHNIQUES AND THEORETICAL CONCEPTS WITH AN ANALYSIS


A NEW ANALYTICAL APPROACH TO THE MUSICAL LANGUAGE OF RAVEL

Ligeti. Continuum for Harpsichord (1968) F.P. Sharma and Glen Halls All Rights Reserved

Student Performance Q&A:

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

USING HARMONIC AND MELODIC ANALYSES TO AUTOMATE THE INITIAL STAGES OF SCHENKERIAN ANALYSIS

Complexity. Listening pleasure. Xiao Yun Chang MIT 21M.011 Essay 3 December

The purpose of this essay is to impart a basic vocabulary that you and your fellow

Victor Hammer collection, MP

Document généré le 12 déc :26. Canadian University Music Review

MELODIC AND RHYTHMIC EMBELLISHMENT IN TWO VOICE COMPOSITION. Chapter 10

Ashton Allan MU 228 Tonality within Aaron Copland s Piano Variations

Murrieta Valley Unified School District High School Course Outline February 2006

Prolonged Anticipations: Towards a Theory of Counterline (A Mock Proposal) used to describe the setting of note against note punctus contrapunctum.

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

uch has been done over the past thirty years to contextualize Schenker s

Deviant Cadential Six-Four Chords

Influence of timbre, presence/absence of tonal hierarchy and musical training on the perception of musical tension and relaxation schemas

Prelude and Fantasy for Baroque Lute by Denis Gaultier

Composing and Interpreting Music

Schenkerian Theory, Neo-Riemannian Theory and Late Schubert: A Lesson from Tovey RENÉ RUSCH

Virginia Commonwealth University MHIS 146 Outline Notes. Open and Closed Positions of Triads Never more than an octave between the upper three voices

Etna Builder - Interactively Building Advanced Graphical Tree Representations of Music

Music Annual Assessment Report AY17-18

AP Music Theory Curriculum

An Integrated Music Chromaticism Model

Interpreting Museums as Cultural Metaphors

Martin Link. Immediate constituent analysis as a future model of electroacoustic music theory

Ambiguity of Tonal Meaning in Chopin s Prelude op. 28, no. 22

AP MUSIC THEORY 2015 SCORING GUIDELINES

Michael Lüthy Retracing Modernist Praxis: Richard Shiff

NUMBER OF TIMES COURSE MAY BE TAKEN FOR CREDIT: One

Florida State University Libraries

PKUES Grade 10 Music Pre-IB Curriculum Outline. (adapted from IB Music SL)

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Music Education. Test at a Glance. About this test

MUSIC (MUS) Music (MUS) 1

A GTTM Analysis of Manolis Kalomiris Chant du Soir

NUMBER OF TIMES COURSE MAY BE TAKEN FOR CREDIT: One

UNIVERSITY COLLEGE DUBLIN NATIONAL UNIVERSITY OF IRELAND, DUBLIN MUSIC

Curriculum Catalog

MUSIC THEORY CURRICULUM STANDARDS GRADES Students will sing, alone and with others, a varied repertoire of music.

The Cognitive Reality of Prolongational Structures in Tonal Music.

AP Music Theory Syllabus

Music Theory Fundamentals/AP Music Theory Syllabus. School Year:

Introduction to Free Counterpoint. ( or Bach Style Counterpoint ) by Glen Halls All rights reserved.

AP Music Theory. Sample Student Responses and Scoring Commentary. Inside: Free Response Question 7. Scoring Guideline.

Music Theory AP Course Syllabus

ZGMTH. Zeitschrift der Gesellschaft für Musiktheorie

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

Novagen: A Combination of Eyesweb and an Elaboration-Network Representation for the Generation of Melodies under Gestural Control

Reconceptualizing the Lydian Chromatic Concept: George Russell as Historical Theorist. Michael McClimon

Perspective of Music Perception and Cognition

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

George Levine, Darwin the Writer, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, 272 pp.

Course Overview. At the end of the course, students should be able to:

Piano Teacher Program

Theories and Activities of Conceptual Artists: An Aesthetic Inquiry

Add note: A note instructing the classifier to append digits found elsewhere in the DDC to a given base number. See also Base number.

NJCCCS AREA: North Brunswick Township Public Schools. AP Music Theory. Acknowledgements: Written by: James Egan, Band Director

Expected Competencies:

observation and conceptual interpretation

Capstone Design Project Sample

The Environment and Organizational Effort in an Ensemble

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

AP MUSIC THEORY 2006 SCORING GUIDELINES. Question 7

SAMPLE ASSESSMENT TASKS MUSIC GENERAL YEAR 12

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

AP MUSIC THEORY 2016 SCORING GUIDELINES

COMPOSITION AND MUSIC THEORY Degree structure Index Course descriptions

CPU Bach: An Automatic Chorale Harmonization System

AP Music Theory 1999 Scoring Guidelines

Transcription:

REVIEW Robert P. Morgan Becoming Heinrich Schenker: Music Theory and Ideology Cambridge University Press, 2014: xx+275 pp. ($99.00 cloth) Matthew Arndt Robert P. Morgan s Becoming Heinrich Schenker: Music Theory and Ideology offers a conceptual overview of Schenker s theoretical development and ideological position, and it attempts to tell how his work aimed to explain the pitch structure of a limited portion of [tonal] music... totally and with complete rationality or to explain what tonal music is and how it works (xv, xiii, 15). The book adheres to two premises. First, Morgan assumes that Schenker s evolution can be understood as basically consistent and unidirectional, and that it moves toward the final theory, a highly systematic and self-contained theory whose absolute completion is represented by The Masterwork in Music, volume 3, and whose complete presentation is represented by Free Composition (xviii, xvi). Second, he assumes that Schenker s theory contains an ideological paradox consisting of two apparently independent and opposed philosophical strains: a nineteenth-century Idealist one and a twentieth-century Modernist one (xiii). As for previous studies, their tendency has been to emphasize one side of his philosophical position at the expense of the other.... I prefer, on the other hand, to see both idealism and empiricism as consistently present throughout Schenker s entire theoretical career (xivn1; emphasis mine). Moreover, while a number of scholars have examined the conceptual roots of Schenker s musical thought... they have also often identified a single predecessor or intellectual movement as his primary source.... I prefer to see him as someone with a range of intellectual interests, unattached to any single influence (4; emphasis mine). Is the phrase I prefer merely a rhetorical device for Morgan to position himself? I submit, rather, that the book s argument is indeed based on Morgan s preference, his ideology. Part 1 introduces and gives a précis of Schenker s final theory; part 2, the heart of the book, traces the development toward this theory; and part 3 gives a critical assessment of the theory and its ideology. Never before has anyone surveyed Schenker s entire theoretical development as presented in all of the major published works (xix). Morgan weaves together twenty-six Journal of Music Theory 60:1, April 2016 DOI 10.1215/00222909-3448764 2016 by Yale University 89

90 JOURNAL of MUSIC THEORY works over almost four decades, with frequent new translations. The result is impressive and enjoyable, and the reader gains a new appreciation for the depth and gradual unfolding Schenker s thinking about music. Morgan puts Schenker in the company of such innovators as Charles Darwin and Isaac Newton, and given the feat of cogitation that he traces in Schenker s work, there is a bit of truth to this characterization. Also like Darwin, Schenker is not just a thinker with a particular ideology but an ideological icon. There is Darwin himself, and then there is Darwin as appropriated in the polarized debate over science and religion. In a similar way, there is Schenker himself, and then there is Schenker as Morgan describes him, a genius that many musicians have turned against in the debate over the music itself and its larger social and political framework (204, 13, xvii). Morgan s conception of Schenker s theory, colored by its role in Morgan s ideology, is not the same as Schenker s conception of it (205). The differences come into focus through an examination of Morgan s premises. Morgan claims that the theory presented in Free Composition is selfcontained, yet Free Composition represents just one of three theories in New Musical Theories and Fantasies. Morgan argues that concepts from the earlier volumes, such as that of the Stufe, are transformed into components of a comprehensive conception, such that Free Composition supersedes the earlier volumes (160). But many elements of Schenker s theory of free composition can be understood only with reference to his theories of harmony and counterpoint. For example, Schenker (1956; 1979, 11) claims that as long as the fifth determines the natural sonority and that will always be so a voiceleading technique based upon the fifth, as nature requires, cannot lead to any diatony other than the diatony which our art has exhibited up to the present day. All that Schenker has established to this point is the initial composing out of the Naturklang by means of descending stepwise motion counterpointed by an arpeggiation through the fifth. But there are five diatonic modes in which such a composing out is possible (diatonic in present-day parlance), not just the major and minor modes that Schenker alludes to. Schenker s (1978; 1954, 55 76) claim is explicable only in light of his argument for rejecting the other modes in Harmonielehre. For another example, Schenker (1956, 46; 1979, 15) says that it will not do to make the Ursatz the first and only source of strict counterpoint and curtail, therefore, instruction in strict counterpoint. Morgan overlooks this intertextuality because he assumes that Schenker s theories are exclusively concerned with music from the commonpractice period of tonality, for which the major and minor modes and the contrapuntal principles that were put together during the tonal period itself are givens (16, xiv). But Schenker describes above how diatony and voice leading will always have to be; his claims are unrelated to a particular period. Morgan also glosses over the distinct, complementary focuses of the three volumes of New Musical Theories and Fantasies by characterizing the final

Review Arndt on Morgan 91 theory as concerned exclusively with pitch structure (11). But Schenker never uses the word structure (Struktur), and I know of only one time that he uses the word pitch (Tonhöhe), in a discussion of temperament in Harmonielehre (1978, 105; 1954, 82). Moreover, Schenker (1979, 5) says that music is never comparable to... architecture, as the term structure would imply. This objection is not a quiddity. The use of the term structure reflects a broader American abandonment of Schenker s organicism in favor of scientific imagery (Snarrenberg 1994, 49). Morgan s assumption that Schenker is concerned with pitch structure leads him to find contradictions where they do not exist. For example, concerning Schenker s well-known analysis of Bach s Prelude in C major from the Well-Tempered Clavier book I, Morgan writes, There is an inconsistency in this graph: on the one hand, the Urlinie tone d 2 is suspended with f 1 over the bass C... ; but on the other, the bass C appears with e 1 and begins an arpeggiated prolongation of e 1 to c 2..., in which case d 2 is only a dissonant upper neighbor to c 2 (33 35). Schenker s graph presents a simple unfolding, where in a chord or series of chords there is a connection from the upper to the inner voice and back again or the reverse (Schenker 1979, 50). In the Bach, the upper voice connects to the inner voice F E and then back to the upper voice D C. The situation is as Schenker illustrates in Free Composition (example 43b4), except originating from sixths instead of thirds. Although Morgan illustrates a similar unfolding in his précis of Schenker s final theory, his explanation of it is inaccurate; he suggests that somehow the two chords combine to create a more background line forming a linear progression (22). Morgan does not recognize this kind of unfolding because it does not involve the elaboration of a fixed pitch structure; it involves a true transformation of the voice leading (Schenker 1979, 25). Morgan assumes that Schenker is concerned with pitch because he does not recognize the full scope of Schenker s conception of the tone. To be sure, he acknowledges the core of Schenker s theories as the spirituality of tone, but he misrepresents this notion (xiii). For example, Morgan draws a distinction between the biological nature of tones, discussed in division 1 of Harmonielehre and associated with music s actual materials (tones, motives, and tonal system), and harmony s spirituality, discussed in division 2 and associated with the Stufe, an ideal harmonic entity that, though represented by a normal triad, is not identical to any actual triad in the music (66 67). But for Schenker (1978, 197; 1954, 152), Die Stufen sind vielmehr identisch mit jenen Quinten, welche wir bereits im 16 als die grundlegenden... Pfeiler und Grundtöne des Systems kennen gelernt haben (The Stufen are rather identical with those fifths which we have already gotten to know in 16 [in division 1] as the foundational pillars and ground tones of the [tonal] system). Morgan further misrepresents Stufen when he writes, There seems little doubt that [Schenker] preferred to view the Ursatz as contrapuntal.... The Ursatz, then, is better conceived as the source of Stufen, but not as having

92 JOURNAL of MUSIC THEORY Stufen itself (211). But Schenker (1956, 173; 1979, 111) writes, Stufen are present even in the Ursatz itself. These Stufen are the strongest of all, since the Ursatz assures the coherence of the work. For another example, Morgan suggests that for Schenker tones must behave in a certain way and no other and that consequently composers must obey the tonal urges of tones, which are beyond all individual intention (xiii, 17). But for Schenker not every tone has its way, and the artist is not a yes-man to each and every tone. The tones all scramble for a place in the sun, and the artist, the tone wrangler, must shepherd them to their appointed lot, according to his intention (Schenker 1987, 1:14). And there are several other similar misrepresentations of concepts. Morgan claims that the theory presented in Free Composition is complete, yet the section on form is widely regarded as a sketch at best. Morgan argues that this section like Schenker s claims about rhythm, drama, meaning, and affect do[es] not... belong to the final theory proper or lack[s] theoretical weight, regardless of what Schenker himself may have believed (14, 204). More specifically, he points to the problem that all associative relationships, unlike the syntactic ones Schenker primarily addresses, resist strictly Schenkerian explanation, whether thematic, harmonic, or tonal (209). This is circular reasoning: the section on form is not part of the Schenkerian theory proper, because it is not Schenkerian (212). Turning now to Morgan s second premise that Schenker s theory is related to an idealist, modernist/empiricist ideology what exactly are theory and ideology, and how are they related? Morgan tells us that ideology is a conceptual framework through which experience is filtered as part of a more orderly overall picture (4). That sounds rather like a theory. Indeed, Morgan himself has trouble distinguishing ideology from theory in his terms. Morgan characterizes the relation between Schenker s ideology and his theory variously as one of identity (e.g., the theory is a necessary mix of idealistic and modernistic components ), inclusion, support (e.g., Schenker s mature theory, including the modernist-idealist mix that underlay it ), and determination (e.g., specifically musical-theoretical concepts that resulted from the aesthetic topics ) (12, xiii, xix; emphasis mine). Ultimately, Morgan s distinction between Schenker s theory and his ideology boils down to a classification of his theoretical claims as either idealist or modernist/empiricist. Leaving aside whether modernism and empiricism are equivalent, does Schenker really have an empiricist scientific orientation, as Morgan claims (222)? For his part, Schenker (1994 97, 3:8) says, My theory, extracted as it is from the very products of artistic genius, is and must remain itself art, and so can never become science. But Morgan cites Schenker s later stress on musical hierarchy, theoretical notation, and the empirical observation of actual music, or the theory s reliance on logic and empirical verifiability (43, 222). As for hierarchy, Schenker never uses the word. The notion that hierarchy is a hierarchically superior notion for Schenker, so to speak, is another misconception arising from the American abandonment of Schen-

Review Arndt on Morgan 93 ker s organicism. 1 As for theoretical notation, Schenker s notation is notoriously unsystematic; a symbol frequently means one thing in one case, another in another case. As for empirical observation or verifiability, the content of a masterwork is an idea, and as such it is not empirically observable or verifiable: It is impossible to present in specific and perceptible forms all the events which occur through the miraculous rapport of fundamental structure with foreground (Schenker 1979, 27; 1994 97, 1:1). It can be perceived only by the genius (Schenker 1979, 3). Morgan does not recognize the particularity of Schenker s concept of the genius; he finds that it is consistent with the view of romanticism (71). Schenker, however, distances his view of the genius from that of Romantiker, der, mit sich beginnend u. schließend, in eben diesem circulus vitiosus die Majestät der Sache verletzt (the Romantic, who, beginning and ending with himself, precisely in this vicious circle violates the majesty of the object). 2 It is not surprising that Morgan has trouble distinguishing ideology from theory, given his vague definition. What is a little surprising for a book on the relation of Schenker s theories to his ideology is that he engages hardly at all with the literature on this topic, let alone the literature on the theory of ideology. For example, Morgan dismisses Robert Snarrenberg s attempt to retur[n] us to the humanist roots of Schenker s approach in Schenker s Interpretive Practice as revisionist (195), not recognizing that Snarrenberg (1997, xviii) was writing against a scientistic revision of Schenker s work. In another example, Morgan acknowledges Nicholas Cook s 2007 Schenker Project and says that it had a significant influence on my own, and brought about one important alteration: the brief discussion of ornamentation originally included in the section on synthesis... has been replaced by a much longer one with a section of its own (x xi). The section in question is less than two pages (102 3) and does not cite Cook. Cook makes one substantive appearance in the book: Until Nicholas Cook s recent book on Schenker appeared, the Geist article was consistently misinterpreted as being inconsistent either because of its anti-organicism or (in at least one case) because it supported organicism, and thus idealism. For it harbors elements of both (57). Apparently we are to infer that Cook s view is consistent with Morgan s view, that Schenker s idealism and empiricism both remained prominent throughout his theoretical career, but there is no citation of Cook, and Cook never ascribes empiricism to Schenker (57). Along the same lines, although the book quotes Schenker frequently (relative to other authors), the frequency is not adequate for explaining and interpreting Schenker s concepts, particularly given that the book is not con- 1 Schenker s graphs came to be read as spatial things and not temporal processes, a transformation effected in part by substituting the opposition of higher and lower levels for Schenker s opposition of earlier and later layers (Snarrenberg 1994, 49). 2 Heinrich Schenker, journal entry dated December 6, 1916, Oswald Jonas Memorial Collection, Special Collections and Archives, box 2, folder 5, p. 527, University of California, Riverside.

94 JOURNAL of MUSIC THEORY ceived for experts alone (xvi). For example, Morgan s précis of Schenker s final theory has only one graphic depiction of a piece of music (and there are no score excerpts); all the other examples are abstract illustrations of concepts created by Morgan himself. For another example, Morgan claims that Schenker is unclear on the issue of interruption and that it contradicts a basic assumption of the theory, but he offers not a single quotation from Schenker to substantiate his claims about interruption, even though Morgan himself recognizes it as not only... one of the most crucial aspects of his theory but also one of its most controversial (207). Morgan s book culminates in some commonsense consideration of the practical question: what do we do with Schenker s theories, given their ideology? For Morgan, Schenker s theory tells us something critical about a group of standard common-practice works, but it cannot be accepted at face value, because the ideology rejects all other music, so the theory must be altered to preserve a degree of its depth while allowing for greater coverage (225). He usefully distinguishes three strategies for doing so: The first... simply applies Schenker s theory to his own repertoire... but with the theory reinterpreted in axiomatic terms.... A second type... attempts to accommodate a wider range of triadic music.... The third type... attempts to deal with post-tonal music (216 17). But for Morgan, such an extension of Schenker s theory is more than just the constant process of adaptation that attends all theories; it entails a disintegration of values: it retains the theory s modernist husk but renounces its idealist core, depriving it of the hope of musical truth (211). The disintegration of values is a trope of modernity, which simultaneously idealizes and distances itself from the past. To this extent, Morgan and Schenker are in sync. And just as we can adapt Schenker s groundbreaking theories to our own, so the reader is rewarded by adapting Morgan s unprecedentedly exhaustive but skewed account of Schenker s theories. Works Cited Schenker, Heinrich. 1954. Harmony. Translated by Elisabeth Mann Borgese, edited by Oswald Jones. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.. 1956. Der freie Satz. Vol. 3 of Neue musikalische Theorien und Phantasien, 2nd ed. Edited by Oswald Jonas. Vienna: Universal Edition.. 1978. Harmonielehre. Vol. 1 of Neue musikalische Theorien und Phantasien. Repr. Vienna: Universal Edition.. 1979. Free Composition. Edited and translated by Ernst Oster. Vol. 3 of New Musical Theories and Fantasies. New York: Longman.. 1987. Counterpoint. Translated by John Rothgeb and Jürgen Thym, edited by John Rothgeb. Vol. 2 of New Musical Theories and Fantasies. 2 bks. New York: Schirmer.. 1994 97. The Masterwork in Music: A Yearbook. Translated by Ian Bent, Alfred Clayton, William Drabkin, Richard Kramer, Derrick Puffett, John Rothgeb, and Hedi Siegel, edited by William Drabkin. 3 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Review Arndt on Morgan 95 Snarrenberg, Robert. 1994. Competing Myths: The American Abandonment of Schenker s Organicism. In Theory, Analysis, and Meaning in Music, ed. Anthony Pople, 29 56. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.. 1997. Schenker s Interpretive Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Matthew Arndt is assistant professor of music theory at the University of Iowa.