Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Similar documents
Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

observation and conceptual interpretation

Structural Realism, Scientific Change, and Partial Structures

Scientific Philosophy

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Beatty on Chance and Natural Selection

STRUCTURALISM AND INFORMATION OTA VIO BUENO

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Realism about Structure: The Semantic View and Non-linguistic Representations

Realism about Structure: The Semantic View and Non-linguistic Representations*

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Carlo Gabbani and Marc Lange 1 on Bas van Fraassen s Scientific Representation 2

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS


Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Q1. Name the texts that you studied for media texts and society s values this year.

Ridgeview Publishing Company

Bas van Fraassen's Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective 2

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

On Recanati s Mental Files

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

Formalization: methodology and concrete examples

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Chapter 15. Instrumentalism. Global, Local, and Scientific. P. Kyle Stanford. 1 Prelude: Instrumentalism, the Very Idea

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Phenomenology Glossary

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Epistemology and Philosophy of Science

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Structure, Knowledge, and Ostension

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Author's personal copy

The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and Reason by Mark Johnson, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission.

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Title: What is the Paradox of Phase Transitions? Abstract:

Philosophical foundations for a zigzag theory structure

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Logic, Truth and Inquiry (Book Review)

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

Between Concept and Form: Learning from Case Studies

Matching Bricolage and Hermeneutics: A theoretical patchwork in progress

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

THE STRUCTURE OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTIONS

26:010:685 Social Science Methods in Accounting Research

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Sense and soundness of thought as a biochemical process Mahmoud A. Mansour

The Art of Time Travel: A Bigger Picture

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

Thomas Kuhn s Concept of Incommensurability and the Stegmüller/Sneed Program as a Formal Approach to that Concept

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

KEEPING THINGS IN PERSPECTIVE 1. Catherine Z. Elgin. Keywords: Objectivity, Representation, Van Fraassen, Perspective, Empirical science

Bas van Fraassen on Scientific Representation

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Art, Mind and Cognitive Science

Researching Lived Experience: Human Science /ç for an Action Sensitive Pedagogy by Max van Manen, London, ON: Aithouse Press, 1990

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Université Libre de Bruxelles

ARTICLE IN PRESS. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics

COLOR IS NOT BLACK AND WHITE

CONCEPTUALISATIONS IN DESIGN RESEARCH.

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

VISUAL ARTS. Overview. Choice of topic

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

OTÁVIO BUENO University of Miami. Abstract

CRITICAL STUDIES/BOOK REVIEWS

Transcription:

Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Review Reviewed Work(s): Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective by Bas C. van Fraassen Review by: Jeffrey A. Barrett Source: The Journal of Philosophy, Vol. 106, No. 11 (Nov., 2009), pp. 634-639 Published by: Journal of Philosophy, Inc. Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/20620212 Accessed: 13-08-2018 17:09 UTC JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at https://about.jstor.org/terms Journal of Philosophy, Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Journal of Philosophy

634 the journal of philosophy BOOK REVIEWS Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, bas c. van fraassen. New York: Oxford University Press, 2008. 320 p. Cloth $50.00. Bas van Fraassen 's Scientific Representation evolved from his Locke Lectures at Oxford University in 2001. The central focus of the book is the development of an empiricist version of structuralism. As such, it is continuous with van Fraassen's earlier formulations of construc tive empiricism. Indeed, this substantial book is perhaps best read as providing a sketch for a subtle reformulation of constructive empiri cism, one that results from careful reflection on the nature of scien tific representation. While he intends for his discussion of scientific representation to be neutral between realist and empiricist tenants, the book is throughout in the service of developing an empiricist ver sion of structuralism, and van Fraassen ultimately argues that struc turalism finds its proper articulation only in a constructive empiricist setting. There is, however, much here for structural realists, pragma tists, and empiricists more generally, and most anyone interested in the ways of scientific inquiry will profit from the fresh reconstruction, evaluation, and synthesis of arguments from such as Mach, Boltzman, Planck, Hertz, Duhem, Carnap, Russell, and Goodman. The starting point for the discussion of representation is Boltzman's version of the Bildtheorie account of science. On this view, the goal in formulating a physical theory is to construct an inner picture or repre sentation of the external world by attaching definite concepts to objects in order that our thoughts might model the world they represent. Boltzman, however, conceded that we can know little concerning the relationship between our thoughts and the objects they represent. To this van Fraassen agrees and argues that it is more productive, and less mysterious, to imagine scientific representation by means of concrete (for example, graphs and scale models) and abstract (for example, mathematical models) artifacts. Among the representational artifacts employed by science are measurement outcomes, and insofar as they provide the standard of theoretical adequacy for the empiricist, the problem of representation as it obtains for measurement outcomes is of central importance. On van Fraassen's account, the pointer on a measuring instrument at the end of a successful measurement locates the target of the measure ment in a logical space. The logical space is a theoretical construction, 0022-362X/09/0611/634-39? 2009 The Journal of Philosophy, Inc.

BOOK REVIEWS 635 and so is the measurement target as represented by the theory. More specifically, the measurement target is an item that the investigator has classified within the domain of the theory at hand and the logical space is provide by the theory to represent the range of possible states or characteristics of such items (logical spaces include hue, bright ness, and saturation for color perceptions; pressure, volume, and tem perature for the physical states of classical thermodynamics; and Hilbert space for quantum-mechanical states). Measurement outcomes repre sent empirical phenomena, but only relative to the representational use and practice of the inquirer, which, in turn, is contingent on the theory that characterizes the measurement target and logical space and the concrete experimental set-up under which the measurement is performed. Such contingencies represent the essential indexicality of measurement and representation more generally. This essential indexicality is for van Fraassen at root a consequence of the pragmatic model of representation that he endorses. Nothing simply represents something else; rather, theoretical models, data models, measurement outcomes, and other representational artifacts represent only by means of the role they play in the use and practice of inquirers, van Fraassen describes representation as a three-place re lation between the representational artifact, the target, and the user; where the indexical component provided by the user is a subtle busi ness involving the complete conditions of the user's representational use and practice. While this indexical understanding of representation is taken as a necessary step in the successful formulation of structural empiricism, it also leads to problems for the empiricist. In his recitation of his version of the empiricist creed van Fraassen asserts that (i) the pri mary criterion of scientific success is empirical adequacy, (ii) the ac ceptance of a theory has a pragmatic element insofar as it guides future actions and research, and (iii) the acceptance of a theory need involve no more than that the theory is empirically adequate. But what exactly might it mean for a theory to be empirically adequate when one has recognized the deeply contingent indexical nature of even measurement outcomes as representations? As van Fraassen would have it, a measurement outcome is always achieved relative to particular experimental setup designed by the user and characterized by his theory. On the other hand, insofar as a measurement outcome provides evidence for empirical adequacy and empirical adequacy provides the primary criterion of scientific success, one does not want measurement outcomes to be entirely con tingent on the theory in which the measurement is characterized, or, for that matter the contingent interests of the user. Unless there is

636 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY something appropriate and genuinely outside the theory to push back, one has at best only theoretical coherence, in which case there can be no meaningful empirical evaluation of theories. This is a puzzle that generates a useful tension throughout the book, van Fraassen takes phenomena (observable entities like rocks, seas, stars, people, and bicycles) to be the proper target of scien tific representation and theoretical models to be the vehicles for such representation. But since theoretical models are abstract struc tures and abstract structures are mathematical structures and mathe matical structures are not distinguished beyond isomorphism, how is it possible for theoretical models to represent phenomena at all? And if one cannot say how theoretical models represent phenom ena, how could phenomena test the theory? In short, if one has only an abstract theoretical structure, then one has no empirical content to test. Once more, while is sufficient to test the empirical adequacy of a theory that one compare one's theoretical model against a data model (or surface model) that one takes to represent one's experi mental results, how can we explain how a theory represents phe nomena by appeal to a relationship between theoretical models and data models when both of these are abstract entities? The answer must be that the data model somehow represents the phenomena, but then why doesn't this just push the problem back one step? van Fraassen's recurring answer is that while there is nothing in the ab stract structure itself that can determine that it is the relevant data model to be matched to the theory, the "construction of the data model is precisely the selective relevant depiction of the phenomena by the user of the theory required for the possibility of the representation of the phenomena" (253). It is the user's design of the experiment that allows measurement outcomes to represent phenomena, it is the user's construction of the relevant data model from such outcomes that allows the data model to represent phenomena in a way appropriate for testing the theory at hand, and it is the user's identification and comparison of the relevant part of the theoretical model against the data model that allows him to judge that the theory adequately represents the phenomena. It is only by dint of this theory-laden, purposeful chain of representational use and practice that phenomena can push back against the theory at all. The theory is judged to be empirically adequate when there is a (pre sumably, partial and temporary) equilibrium between one's theoretical model, one's relevant data model, and one's theoretical use and prac tice. It is a consequence of this view then that empirical adequacy comes in as many varieties as there may be indexical uses and practices.

BOOK REVIEWS 637 Given the degree of contingent representational indexicality in volved in judgments of empirical adequacy, there is a threat of a strong relativism that results from exactly that indexicality that is supposed to be required for the possibility of structural representation. Since the only empirical matching is between theoretical models and data mod els, the theory does not confront the observable phenomena but rather only the observable phenomena as described, contingent on the under standing and interests of the user, van Fraassen calls this the loss of reality objection. The strategy he favors for addressing it is one that seeks to dissolves the problem (258). van Fraassen begins by conceding that the claim that a theory is ade quate to the phenomena is not the same as the claim that it is adequate to the phenomena as represented by a user of the theory. While the rep resentation of phenomena in a data model is a contingent construc tion for our contingent purposes, he takes the phenomena themselves to be objective. On the other hand, van Fraassen argues that, in check ing the empirical adequacy of a theory, we have no recourse but to compare the theoretical model against our contingent data model. What is supposed to dissolve the problem is that (i) the theory being empirically adequate to the phenomena as represented by us and (ii) the theory in fact being empirically adequate are the same for us. More specifically, van Fraassen appeals to the pragmatic tautology that there is for a person no difference between the question of whether a theory fits his representation of the phenomena and the question of whether the theory fits the phenomena?if it fits the first, he cannot deny that it fits the second (259-60). But while van Fraassen is certainly right that I cannot do better than to judge my representation of the phenomena against what I take to be the relevant part of the theoretical model; insofar as I hold with van Fraassen that all such representation is contingent, I cannot sim ply pretend that my data model is something more than my contingent construction. Further, and perhaps more important, insofar as I hold that it is possible to err in the scientific representation of phenomena, and I find myself so committed, it would be a methodological error for me to mistake my contingent representation of the phenomena for the phenomena themselves. While I have no choice but to call empirical adequacy as I see it, even as I call it, even I recognize that my call is contingent in a sense that allows for error in the assessment of adequacy of the theory to the phe nomena properly understood. More specifically, I recognize the contin gency of my own judgments of empirical adequacy in my recognition of the error of other inquirers' empirical judgments, my recognition of error in my own past empirical judgments, and my conviction that my

638 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY current epistemic situation is ultimately like both my own past episte mic situation and the current epistemic situation of other inquirers' in kind. Once I recognize the live possibility of representational error, the pragmatic tautology provides little comfort, and I find van Fraassen's dissolution of the loss of reality objection consequently unconvincing. In order to take even my own judgment of the empirical adequacy of a theory seriously here, I must take the judgment to concern the match between the relevant part of the theoretic model and a repre sentation of the phenomena concerning which I am committed to eliminat ing representational error whenever I find it. If this is right, then the force of my judgment of empirical adequacy rests in my pragmatic methodological commitment to eliminate representational error, not in the pragmatic tautology. In order to show how structural empiricism meshes with the actual practice of science, van Fraassen ends the book with an explanation of how structural empiricism makes sense of the Copenhagen interpre tation of quantum mechanics and thereby dissolves the quantum mea surement problem. This example also illustrates the contingency of judgments of empirical adequacy on this view. After explaining why (if one assumes that the linear dynamics de scribes the evolution of the composite system) the result of a measure ment cannot supervene on the quantum-mechanical state of the observer, the measuring device, and/or the object being measured, van Fraassen explains why this is not a problem for the empiricist. The idea here is that there is nothing in quantum mechanics or the practice of using the theory, properly conceived, that requires that what happens in the actual situation must be displayed as entirely identifiable in the theoretical model. The most stringent demand that can be made here is that the relative frequencies of certain events in this sort of situation must have a good fit to probability functions, extrapolated from them in surface models, which are identifiable as parts of corresponding prob ability functions in the theoretical models... When this demand is met? whether strictly or to some approximation?the theory is borne out by the experimental results... (305). Quantum mechanics then might be judged to be empirically adequate even when there is nothing in the theoretical model that one can take to represent the actual determinate physical measurement records that one in fact observes. Rather than require the theory to successfully represent each deter minate measurement record, here one only requires that it save the phenomena in statistical aggregate. The theory might be taken as empirically adequate because the theoretical model corresponds to a surface model that captures the overall statistical properties of measurement outcomes.

BOOK REVIEWS 639 The measurement problem is solved here not by honest toil but by exploiting the freedom one has in stipulating what counts as the appropriate data model to match to the theoretical model. Insofar as one might always construct a data model that would allow one to judge a given theory to be empirically adequate, it is a methodological mistake to take advantage of this freedom to achieve empirical ade quacy. Indeed, an empiricist might properly worry over the prospect of even having this degree of representational freedom. JEFFREY A. BARRETT University of California, Irvine