Book Reviews. Perspectival Thought: A Plea for (Moderate) Relativism, by François Récanati. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007, x pp.

Similar documents
PERSPECTIVAL THOUGHT: A PLEA FOR (MODERATE) RELATIVISM

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

Introduction. Fiora Salis University of Lisbon

The dynamics of situations

Types of perceptual content

Indexical Concepts and Compositionality

On Recanati s Mental Files

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Relativism 1: Representational Content

Some Observations on François Recanati s Mental Files

Relativism and Knowledge Attributions

MORAL CONTEXTUALISM AND MORAL RELATIVISM

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

RELATIVISM ABOUT TRUTH AND PERSPECTIVE-NEUTRAL PROPOSITIONS

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

Review of Epistemic Modality

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes* Tyler Burge

CHAPTER 15. Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes. Tyler Burge

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

Two-Dimensional Semantics the Basics

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

!"#$%&'()**#%*#+,*,-./#!"##)*0#1.*02#%3#3.-2'45,-2%*4%-.,*',0#/%*',*'"#

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

Predicates of Personal Taste and Perspective Dependence

Ling 720 Implicit Arguments, Week 11 Barbara H. Partee, Nov 25, 2009

Manuel García-Carpintero & Genoveva Martí (eds.): Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2014, 368 pages

Perceptual Demonstrative Thought: A Property-Dependent Theory

How Narrow is Narrow Content?

The limits of selflessness: semantic relativism and the epistemology of de se thoughts

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

Moral Relativism. Entry for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. By Max Kölbel

Recommending Beauty: Semantics and Pragmatics of Aesthetic Predicates

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Content and Target in Pictorial Representation

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

Sources of Immunity to Error through Misidentification

Symposium on Disjunctivism Philosophical Explorations

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Partial and Paraconsistent Approaches to Future Contingents in Tense Logic

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Phenomenology Glossary

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Moral Relativism in Context

M. Chirimuuta s Adverbialism About Color. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. I. Color Adverbialism

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Thinking of Particulars 1

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Kent Academic Repository

Beyond A- and B-Time Reconsidered

dialectica The Place of Subjects in the Metaphysics of Material Objects

PART ONE: PHILOSOPHY AND THE OTHER MINDS

Katalin Farkas Central European University, Budapest

CHAPTER 7. cjvy. Referring De Re TYLER BURGE

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Frege s Philosophy. Course Outline and Selected Reading

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Peirce s Final Account of Signs and The Philosophy of Language ALBERT ATKIN

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

Reply to Romero and Soria

Mental Files and Identity

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

We know of the efforts of such philosophers as Frege and Husserl to undo the

The ambiguity of definite descriptions

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Berkeley s idealism. Jeff Speaks phil October 30, 2018

CONDITIONALIZATION AND KNOWLEDGE DE PRAESENTI

A New Analysis of Verbal Irony

Volume 59 Number 236 July 2009

Image and Imagination

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

40 THE JOURNAL OF PHILOSOPHY. LIVING WAGES OF SINN* Frege's concept sense (Sinn) is better understood now than it

A Relevance-Theoretic Study of Poetic Metaphor. YANG Ting, LIU Feng-guang. Dalian University of Foreign Languages, Dalian, China

THE PROPOSITIONAL CHALLENGE TO AESTHETICS

Relativity and Degrees of Relationality Jack Spencer Forthcoming in Philosophy and Phenomenological Research

In The Mind and the World Order, C.I. Lewis made a famous distinction between the

Semantic Externalism and Psychological Externalism. Åsa Wikforss Department of Philosophy Stockholm University

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Vagueness & Pragmatics

Topics in Linguistic Theory: Propositional Attitudes

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Transcription:

142 Book Reviews erations, I take it, severely shake the relevance of C&H s example. But even if these considerations prove to be on the wrong track, the following point still can be made: given the important dialectical role the example plays, the conclusion they want to draw is simply jeopardized without more being said in order to rule out the considerations mentioned. I think Relativism and Monadic Truth is an important book, for I believe it lies down with outstanding clarity the kind of challenges the relativist has to respond to in order to solidify her view. Although I have not addressed other important objections C&H raise (such as the clash with the factivity of knowledge and the treatment of bound uses objections that actually do have answers in the literature), I think the book overstates the troubles for the relativist and presents contextualism as the winning view a bit too hastily. At the end of the book, C&H confess that they do not expect the more entrenched relativists to hop out from the trappings of a relativist picture and that the real target of the book are those fence-sitters and swing voters whom once can hope to prevent from becoming ensnared by it (138). I certainly agree with the first of these claims. As for the second, once the whole picture is brought to light and a thorough examination of both views and their problems is given, I am not completely sure that the fence-sitters and swing voters to whom the book is addressed will be convinced so easily by the kinds of arguments offered in this otherwise rich and interesting book. Dan Zeman LOGOS Universitat de Barcelona C/ Montalegre, 4-6, 4090, 08001, Barcelona dan_zeman@yahoo.com Perspectival Thought: A Plea for (Moderate) Relativism, by François Récanati. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007, x + 308 pp. As the subtitle indicates, François Récanati s Perspectival Thought is a plea for moderate relativism, a view that acknowledges a neglected form of context-dependency in language and thought: situationrelativity. The view is not entirely new: it has its roots in situation semantics and Récanati s earlier work, notably Oratio Obliqua, Oratio Recta (MIT Press, 2000) in which it was applied to attitude reports

Book Reviews 143 and metarepresentation. It is also partly familiar from the current discussion over semantic relativism. However, Récanati s book stands out of the recent literature on two counts. First, it provides a comprehensive relativist framework in which earlier foundational debates between Arthur Prior, Gareth Evans, David Lewis, David Kaplan, John Perry, Jon Barwise and others are resituated and illuminated. Second, it goes beyond philosophy of language to rest its case mostly on considerations drawn from the philosophy of mind, namely the application of the relativist framework to perception, memory, imagination and perspectival thought in general. The resulting work is deeply original (including with respect to Récanati s earlier work) and deals in detail with a wealth of issues. Récanati s moderate relativism consists in three main ideas: (1) situation-relativity, (2) aligning the content/situation distinction on the content/force one, (3) free shiftability. Each of the book s three parts roughly centres on one of these. The first part introduces Récanati s relativist framework within philosophy of language. The two others apply it to philosophy of mind. Situation-relativity is introduced in part I. Its cornerstone is Duality, an idea encapsulated in Austin s slogan that it takes two to make a truth (34). Truth requires a content to be evaluated and a circumstance or situation with respect to which the content is evaluated. On the Duality view, this implies that the primary bearers of truth-value are content-situation pairs. Following Barwise, Récanati calls such pairs Austinian propositions (45). If the content is a classical proposition the situation component of the corresponding Austinian proposition seems superfluous. A classical proposition can be evaluated with respect to reality itself. (That is what being a classical proposition is. For instance, if reality consists in just one world, a function from possible worlds to truthvalues will be a classical proposition.) Since there is just one reality, the situation component appears trivial: we may just as well treat the classical proposition itself as the bearer of truth-value. That this is not so, however, is shown by example from Barwise and John Etchemendy (50). Watching over a game of poker, the speaker utters Claire has a good hand now, while Claire is not in fact among the players in that game; though as it happens, she plays in some other part of the town and does have a good hand. Evaluated with respect to the entire actual world, the speaker s utterance is true. Yet the utterance concerned a particular situation, the one the speaker was

144 Book Reviews looking at. And if evaluated with respect to that situation, the utterance is not true. This explains our ambivalence about the truth of that utterance. So even if we grant that the utterance expresses a classical proposition, it is not trivial to specify a situation to evaluate it. Duality consequently imposes a distinction between two levels of content, explicit vs. full content (42-46). Explicit contents are the first element of content-situation pairs. Full contents are the contentsituation pairs themselves, that is, Austinian propositions. In Barwise and Etchemendy s example, the explicit content is the proposition that Claire has a good hand now. However, its full content is that that proposition is true of the situation perceived. Once we accept Duality, it becomes natural to consider explicit contents as properties of situations. And the more specified the situation, the thinner the explicit content can be. For instance, the explicit content of it is raining can be a constant but time-relative proposition that is true at some times but false at others (44). Stoics attributed such contents to tensed sentences, and called them lekta (39); Récanati borrows the term for the explicit-content component of Austinian propositions (46). Lekta can in principle be further relativized so as to be true at some locations but not others ( It is raining evaluated at Murdock or at Palo Alto (222)), at some domains but not at others ( All students are French evaluated at some group or at other (50)), at some persons but not others ( I am Hume evaluated at Hume or at Heimson (110)) or at some perspective but not others ( the salt is left of the pepper evaluated at one side of the table or the other (84)). Duality provides a framework in which Récanati locates a range of views and debates, including his own moderate relativism. First, relativism is in principle neutral on the literalismcontextualism debate (3,7). In Literal Meaning (Cambridge UP, 2004), Récanati framed the latter around the question whether the mechanisms generating the intuitive content of utterances are strictly semantic ( saturation ) or pragmatic ( free enrichment ) in nature. But in his relativist framework, intuitive contents are just explicit contents, lekta. So the framework introduces an entirely distinct layer of context-dependency, namely the situation. The views still intersect in practice, because saturation, modulation and situation-relativity are alternative accounts available for any particular case of contextsensitivity (8-9). But at the theoretical level, Récanati s relativism and his contextualism have only in common their rejection of the idea that all context-sensitivity reduces to saturation.

Book Reviews 145 Second, relativist views are those who acknowledge situationrelative lekta. Among them Récanati distinguishes the radical from the moderate. On moderate relativist views, the full contents of utterances and thoughts are Austinian propositions that have absolute truth. Even when its lekton is incomplete, an utterance is associated to a situation of evaluation and thereby gets a complete content and an absolute truth-value as in the orthodox Fregean picture. By contrast, on radical relativist views an utterance need not be tied to a particular situation of evaluation. Consequently, some utterances are not absolutely true or false but only have truth and falsity relative to points of evaluation (40-41). Récanati s moderate and radical versions of relativism thus correspond to John MacFarlane s nonindexical contextualism and relativism respectively. MacFarlane is the main proponent of the latter; the former covers views like those recently put forward by Peter Lasersohn, Max Kölbel and Stefano Predelli. Arthur Prior, Michael Dummett, David Kaplan, Brian Loar and David Lewis can also be retrospectively characterized as moderate relativists (the first three on temporal propositions, 44-45, 48, the latter two on de se propositions, 109-112, 118). Third, moderate relativism further branches into two versions (41, 113). On the two-level version, lekta are context-independent contents of representation. In the case of utterances, they are the meaning of sentence types like Kaplan s characters (47). In the case of thoughts, they are narrow psychological contents (117). We have just two levels of content, lekton and Austinian proposition. Such a picture is suggested by Dummett and endorsed by Lewis (40, 47, 118). By contrast, on the three-level version, lekta are contextdependent contents like Kaplan s contents (47-48). Roughly, they are the content one gets after filling in the value of indexical items. They may still be relative: for instance, on Kaplan s view, an utterance of it is raining here has a place-specific but temporally neutral content, i.e. a temporal proposition. Context-dependent lekta are thus distinct both from the context-independent content of the representation type and from the full, Austinian content of the representation token. This three-level picture is endorsed by Barwise, Kaplan and Récanati himself (47-48, 113-114). Récanati simply sets aside radical relativism, and devotes most of Part I to a discussion of arguments from the philosophy of language over (1) relativism vs. orthodoxy and (2) the three-level (Barwise- Kaplan) version vs. the two-level (Dummett-Lewis) one. Arguments

146 Book Reviews over relativism are discussed through a detailed review of the debate over temporal propositions: Frege-Evans objection to the very idea of incomplete propositions (37-38, 43-46), the claim by Jeffrey King and others that temporalism makes sense only if tenses are operators (55-65), Mark Richard s idea that temporal propositions cannot be objects of belief (78-81). Récanati finds the objections inconclusive. Additionally, he rejects Max Kölbel s and Peter Lasersohn s pro-relativism argument based on cases of faultless disagreement on matters of taste and puts forward an alternative, non-relativistic, treatment of such cases (90-91). By contrast, Récanati advances two considerations in favour of relativism: it better reflects what Patrick Blackburn calls the internal perspective we have on time (65), and (following Prior and Dummett) it preserves the modal and temporal innocence of nontemporal and non-modal fragments of language (67-71). On the two- vs. three-level issue, Récanati takes up the debate between Robert Stalnaker and Kaplan vs. Lewis over middle-level context-dependent contents (104-119). First, he rejects Stalnaker s idea that they are needed as the intuitive content of speech acts (105): as Lewis argues, such a notion is straightforwardly definable from the context-independent content of the sentence (106). Second, Récanati rejects Barwise s claim that they are needed as the narrow content of attitudes (116): as Perry points out, context-independent content is better suited to that role (115-117). Récanati delays his own case for the three-level picture until Part III (216-217), where he draws on the application of the relativist framework to perception. As I understand it, Récanati s argument for the middle level (roughly, Kaplan s contents) is that it is needed to draw the distinction between those elements of a situation which are represented (e.g. the object of perception) and those which affect the full Austinian content without being represented (e.g. the subject of perception and her location) (216-217). But I fail to see the force of the argument. Just as intuitive speech act content is definable from the context-independent content (as Récanati concedes to Lewis, 106), the above distinction is straightforwardly drawn from that content: namely, the represented elements are just those to which corresponds an indexical item in the representation. There is no need to introduce an additional level in which indexical items are replaced by elements of the situation themselves though I agree that there is no harm in doing so (217). Part II proposes to align the lekton/situation distinction with the content/force distinction (125-129). The idea is that the force of an

Book Reviews 147 utterance, or the psychological mode of a thought, is what determines the situation with respect to which the utterance or thought content is to be evaluated (23, 128). For instance, Récanati agrees with Searle that when I make a promise, the promise is satisfied only by a future situation brought about by me (127), and that when I perceive that there is a flower, the perception is veridical only if there is a flower in the situation that causes my perceptual experience (130-131). However, contrary to Searle, Récanati denies that these aspects of the truth-conditions are part of the explicit content of the utterance or thought. Rather, they are contributed by the mode s selection of a situation of evaluation (132-135). The idea draws a boundary between explicit vs. implicit representation: elements of full content that figure in the lekton are explicitly represented; those contributed by the mode s selection of a situation are implicitly represented (23, 145-146). Récanati applies this to perception (135), episodic memory (138-142) and proprioception (146-148). The content of an episodic memory is the same timeneutral content as that of the original perception; the fact that it concerns a past situation is not part of its content, but results from the memory mode. Similarly, proprioception delivers personneutral propositions such as being hot. The self is not explicitly represented in such thoughts; rather, the internal mode ensures that these contents are self-attributed (146-147). Since, as a matter of physical fact, information received on that mode can only be about oneself, such thoughts are immune to error through misidentification (147). (Récanati s implicit de se thoughts thus correspond to Loar s, Chisholm s and Lewis accounts of de se thought (176); but he distinguishes them from explicit de se thoughts in which the subject thinks of himself in a first-person way but through an explicit self-referential concept (as in Evans and Perry s accounts, 176-177).) Part II extensively argues that Récanati s implicit de se provides a better account of immunity phenomena than Searle s and Higginbotham s reflexivist alternatives which account for all selfreferential aspects of thought in terms of explicitly self-referential content (145-194). Situation-relativity is also put to use in an account of first-person imagination (195-210). First-person imaginings are states with person-relative contents, without explicit representation of oneself. This explains how we can visualize something unperceived (216n) and how

148 Book Reviews we can imagine being Napoleon without imagining ourselves being Napoleon ( quasi-de se imagination 204-206). Part III centers on free-shiftability. In part II, relativism was used in an account of egocentric thought: relative contents were always to be evaluated at one s present situation. Quasi-de se imagination introduces the notion of free shiftability: the possibility for thoughts to be evaluated in a heterocentric situation. For instance, if my son in Murdock tells me on the phone it is raining, I may entertain the place-neutral content that it is raining, as long as its situation of evaluation is fixed to be Murdock and not my current location (279). Free shiftability raises several worries. First, Perry argues that the relevant situation has to be explicitly represented if it is not provided by the thinker s current environment (225). Récanati agrees, but replies that it need only be represented in some other thought of the subject (226). Second, Manuel García-Carpintero puts forward a proliferation worry (200): do we need a mode for each place we are able to think about? To this Récanati replies by the suggestion that all free shifts are handled by a single mode, namely the anaphoric mode, which fixes the situation of a thought to be the situation the subject is currently attending to (201, 284). While the reply is cogent, it shows that Récanati s substantially revises the traditional notion of mode: the distinction between anaphoric vs. egocentric thoughts cuts across the distinction between beliefs, desires and other attitudes. Third, Devitt points out that on the free-shift view, thoughts with identical contents may fail to have identical cognitive significance: while my son and I entertain the same place-neutral thought that it is raining, I am not disposed to take an umbrella (227-228). Récanati replies that this difference is accounted by the difference in mode between the two thoughts (287). Récanati s reply to Devitt apparently assumes that the difference in mode entails inferential encapsulation: my place-neutral beliefs concerning Murdock should somehow be kept inferentially isolated from my beliefs about my current location. If that is so, far from being very different from operators (278), Récanati s situationshifting modes are just like operators except that they do not embed that is, a thought can have only one. This is quite consonant, however, with Récanati s suggestion that the anaphoric mode is a proto-operator (288-289).

Book Reviews 149 Récanati s book covers foundational ground in a dense and thought-provoking manner, and will repay close study to anyone interested in linguistic and mental representation. Julien Dutant Department of Philosophy University of Geneva rue de Candolle 2 1211 Genève, Suisse julien.dutant@unige.ch