Shadi Bartsch and David Wray (eds.), Seneca and the Self (Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009), ISBN:

Similar documents
Antonio Donato 2009 ISSN: Foucault Studies, No 7, pp , September 2009 REVIEW

Seneca and the self: new directions

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

Julie K. Ward. Ancient Philosophy 31 (2011) Mathesis Publications

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Paul Allen Miller, Postmodern Spiritual Practices: The Construction of the Subject and the Reception of Plato in Lacan, Derrida, and Foucault

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Hegel's Absolute: An Introduction to Reading the Phenomenology of Spirit

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

Culture, Space and Time A Comparative Theory of Culture. Take-Aways

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Trying Not to Try: The Art and Science of Spontaneity by Edward Slingerland (review)

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Fairfield Public Schools English Curriculum

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Kent Academic Repository

Writing an Honors Preface

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Aristotle on the Human Good

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

CANZONIERE VENTOUX PETRARCH S AND MOUNT. by Anjali Lai

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Book review: Men s cinema: masculinity and mise-en-scène in Hollywood, by Stella Bruzzi

Surface Integration: Psychology. Christopher D. Keiper. Fuller Theological Seminary

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Hegel and the French Revolution

(1) Writing Essays: An Overview. Essay Writing: Purposes. Essay Writing: Product. Essay Writing: Process. Writing to Learn Writing to Communicate

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Objective vs. Subjective

Curriculum Map: Academic English 11 Meadville Area Senior High School English Department

DEGREE IN ENGLISH STUDIES. SUBJECT CONTENTS.

Content. Philosophy from sources to postmodernity. Kurmangaliyeva G. Tradition of Aristotelism: Meeting of Cultural Worlds and Worldviews...

AN INTRODUCTION OF THE STUDY OF LITERATURE

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Categories and Schemata

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

The Theory and Practice of Virtue Education Edited by Tom Harrison and David I. Walker *

Goldie on the Virtues of Art

Program General Structure

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

BDD-A Universitatea din București Provided by Diacronia.ro for IP ( :46:58 UTC)

Choosing your modules (Joint Honours Philosophy) Information for students coming to UEA in 2015, for a Joint Honours Philosophy Programme.

Hebrew Bible Monographs 18. Colin Toffelmire McMaster Divinity College Hamilton, Ontario, Canada

Introduced Reinforced Practiced Proficient and Assessed. IGS 200: The Ancient World

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

GREGYNOG CONFERENCE 2017 Monday 24th July Wednesday 26th July (Monday 6 p.m. to Wednesday a.m.)

Advanced Placement English Language and Composition

PH th Century Philosophy Ryerson University Department of Philosophy Mondays, 3-6pm Fall 2010

ENGL S092 Improving Writing Skills ENGL S110 Introduction to College Writing ENGL S111 Methods of Written Communication

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Hear hear. Århus, 11 January An acoustemological manifesto

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

VIRTUE ETHICS-ARISTOTLE

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Deep Ecology A New Paradigm 19 September 2012 Page 1 of 6

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Intentional approach in film production

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Valuable Particulars

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

Misc Fiction Irony Point of view Plot time place social environment

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

1. Two very different yet related scholars

THE ROLE OF THE PATHE IN ARISTOTLE S CONCEPTION OF VIRTUE

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

IMPORTANCE OF ART EDUCATION

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

observation and conceptual interpretation

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Review. Discourse and identity. Bethan Benwell and Elisabeth Stokoe (2006) Reviewed by Cristina Ros i Solé. Sociolinguistic Studies

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

6AANB th Century Continental Philosophy. Basic information. Module description. Assessment methods and deadlines. Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Correlated to: Massachusetts English Language Arts Curriculum Framework with May 2004 Supplement (Grades 5-8)

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

APHRA BEHN STAGE THE SOCIAL SCENE

A Condensed View esthetic Attributes in rts for Change Aesthetics Perspectives Companions

126 BEN JONSON JOURNAL

COMPREHENSIVE EXAMINATION SAMPLE QUESTIONS

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Transcription:

Antonio Donato 2011 ISSN: 1832-5203 Foucault Studies, No. 11, pp. 200-205, February 2011 REVIEW Shadi Bartsch and David Wray (eds.), Seneca and the Self (Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press, 2009), ISBN: 978-0521888387 This book contains twelve papers which were originally presented at a conference hosted by the University of Chicago in 2003. This collection is a very good example of how research on an ancient author should be done. The remarkable quality of this volume is the result of the choice of bringing together an impressive group of scholars some of the contributors are amongst the most distinguished scholars of Roman philosophy and literature. The purpose of this book is to reflect on Foucault s famous thesis that Seneca is a philosopher who is particularly concerned with the care of the self, i.e., the investigation of the technologies (i.e., practices) that are most suitable to lead a person to moral and spiritual improvement. Some of the contributors (i.e., Inwood, Ker, and Long) of Seneca and the Self explicitly concentrate on Foucault s interpretation of Seneca; others keep Foucault s reading of Seneca in the background and analyze, more or less directly, Seneca s elusive notion of the self. In this review, I will devote more attention to the articles which explicitly discuss Foucault s theory since this section of the book is probably of greater interest for the readers of this journal. Seneca and the Self is divided into four parts, an introduction and three sections which approach Seneca s notion of the self from a philosophical, cultural, and literary perspective respectively. The text s interdisciplinary approach is one of its greatest merits since it does justice of the complexity of Seneca s corpus of works which consists not only of philosophical texts but also of tragedies and satires. The diversity of Seneca s literary production has always constituted a challenge for any scholar who has attempted to consider his thought in a holistic way Seneca and the Self offers an important contribution to the understanding of the relations between Seneca s very diverse works. In the introduction the editors effectively outline both the merits (i.e., the interdisciplinary approach and the discussion between different evaluations of Seneca s notion of the self) and the content of the book. The editors also present the key difficulty involved in the study of Seneca s notion of the self: in Seneca s works the notion of the self is not clearly outlined, in spite of the many texts in which he seems, as Foucault shows, to reflect on how to care for one s self. On the whole, Seneca and the Self shows that Foucault s interpretation of Seneca presents a very serious exegetical difficulty. In the History of Sexuality (vol. 3) Foucault argues that the care for the self was a constant preoccupation among the philosophers who lived during the Imperial Age, regardless of their philosophical affiliations. Foucault s inclusion of authors such as Seneca in the list of those who developed strategies to care for the self is pro- 200

Donato: review of Seneca and the Self blematic since his affiliation to Stoicism makes it difficult to understand what the self is for him. Different from Platonism in which the self is clearly identified with man s soul which is his real essence, Stoic psychology does not seem to make room for the self. The Stoic notion of man s commanding faculty (i.e., hēgemonikon) does not, indeed, carry the sense of individuality which seems to be required to develop a notion of the self. In the introduction to Seneca and the Self the editors suggest an attractive solution to such an exegetical difficulty: Seneca s notion of the self is not ontological but rather ethical, and even there more rhetorical than doctrinal. (4) According to this interpretation, Seneca seems to be interested (i) not in assessing what the self is from an ontological or psychological perspective, but (ii) in examining a basic feature of human existence, i.e. the concern for one s moral and spiritual condition. The exegetical difficulty of assessing what Seneca s notion of the self is and the solution suggested by the editors are explored in great detail throughout Seneca and the Self. The basic difficulty posed by Seneca s notion of self is directly tackled by A. A. Long s article Seneca and the Self: Why Now? Initially, Long shows that Foucault s study of Seneca s notion of the self has two main merits: 1) it contributes to deepening our understanding of the Roman author; 2) it brings to our attention a way of thinking about the self which constitutes a valuable alternative to the Cartesian idea of the self that is still fairly prominent in our culture. In the second part of his article, Long acknowledges the difficulty of placing a reflection on the self within Stoic psychology and proposes an insightful model of the structure of the self. Long s model is not explicitly presented by either Seneca or other Stoic philosophers, but it (i) may have been tacitly employed by Seneca and other Stoic thinkers or, at the very least, (ii) is in harmony with the basic tenets of Stoic psychology. Long indicates that it is possible to distinguish within a human being between (i) an occurrent subjective self which consists of a person s present thoughts and emotions and (ii) a normative self which is what a person should aspire to become. On this reading, Seneca s re-current analyses on how to care for the self can be regarded as a sort of roadmap which indicates how an individual should proceed in order to abandon his occurrent self and acquire the normative self. Long s analysis of Seneca s notion of the self is an effective way to (i) follow up Foucault s intuition that Seneca does have a notion of the self and (ii) offer the theoretical framework to understand how to place Seneca s frequent analyses of the self within the Stoic philosophical framework. B. Inwood s essay, Seneca and Self-assertion, is the most critical of Foucault s reading of Seneca amongst the contributions contained in Seneca and the Self. Inwood s primary target is the view (which he attributes to Foucault) that Seneca innovates on previous treatments of the self by Stoic and Platonic philosophers. Inwood shows very persuasively that that there is no distinctive novelty in Seneca s ontology of the human mind. This reading, however, raises some important exegetical issues. The first is whether Foucault really thinks that Seneca s notion of the self introduces a novelty in Stoic psychology. In his first extensive treatment of the self in the History of Sexuality Foucault mentions Seneca together with many other Epicurean, Stoic, and Platonic philosophers without stressing Seneca s originality but simply presenting 201

Foucault Studies, No. 11, pp. 200-205. him as one of the protagonists of the discovery of the self. 1 As for Foucault s analysis of the notion of the self, he seems to be interested in describing the ways in which authors of the Imperial Age reflected on how to proceed in order to improve one s intellectual, spiritual, and emotional condition. The possible problem which Foucault s interpretation presents is not that it attributes to Seneca a view that he never held as it is suggested by Inwood but that he may have failed to consider what the theoretical ground for the care of the self is. In the second part of his article, Inwood offers a very penetrative analysis of Seneca s texts which aims to show that, contrary to what Foucault claims, Seneca s recurrent use of reflective pronouns is not evidence that he developed a sense of the self. Inwood argues very persuasively that Seneca s self-reflecting language is a literary device which aims to create a literal persona, a moral exemplum of the moral principles Seneca advocates. Inwood s interpretation has the merit of showing the necessity to recognize the difference between Seneca-the-author and the image of Seneca that we get from his works. This reading, however, raises the further problem of assessing what motivated Seneca-the-author to portray himself in a particular way rather than in another. It can be made the argument which Foucault may have endorsed that Seneca-the-author s goal in portraying a fictional Seneca is therapeutic: his fictional selfportrait may allow him to reflect, individuate, and objectify some of his fears and aspirations. In Seneca and Selfhood: Integration and Disintegration C. Gill explores the difficultties involved in defining what, according to Seneca, the self is. Gill concentrates on the difficulties concerning Seneca s notion of the self and its unity that are raised by the descriptions of the struggles that Medea and Phaedra as they are portrayed by Seneca in his tragedies experience when choosing what course of action they should take. Gill addresses this difficulty by developing a very useful model of the structure of the self that is not too dissimilar to the one offered by Long in the first article of Seneca and the Self. Gill suggests that it is possible to distinguish between a natural self and an actual self. The former captures how human beings should be if they were to follow their nature (i.e., reason) completely; the latter indicates the state that human beings are in when they conduct their existence in a way that is not wholly rational. In the light of this distinction, Gill argues that Seneca s descriptions of Medea and Phaedra can be interpreted as dramatic illustrations of the struggle between their natural and the actual selves. In Seneca s philosophical works, Gills claims, we have the description (i) not of the struggle between the natural and the actual self portrayed in the tragedies, but (ii) of the process which allows human beings to integrate these two selves. Gill calls this process oikeiôsis (i.e., affiliation) and describes it as a natural but challenging process. Gill s article should be taken very seriously by any scholar of Foucault since it does a wonderful job in filling some of the exegetical gaps of Foucault s interpretation of Seneca. Gill s distinction between natural and actual self and his analysis of oikeiôsis offer the theoretical justification for Seneca s interest in how we should proceed to care for the self. Gill s article has the further merit of explaining with great efficacy the difference between Seneca s notion of selfhood and the one that is common in Cartesian and post-cartesian philosophy. In Cartesian and post-cartesian philosophy the self is indentified with a person s self-consciousness, 1 Michel Foucault, The Care of the Self, in The History of Sexuality, vol. 3, translated by Robert Hurley (New York: Vintage books, 1990), 37-69. 202

Donato: review of Seneca and the Self individuality, and subjectivity; in Seneca the natural self is the state that all human beings experience when they act and feel in complete accordance with reason. Nussbaum s Stoic Laughter: Seneca s Apocolocyntosis concludes the section that investigates Seneca s notion of self from a philosophical perspective. Nussbaum deals with Seneca s notion of the self indirectly by reflecting on the therapeutic role of laughter and satire. Initially, Nussbaum presents a very useful outline of three basic kinds of laughter: 1) the vulgar and mindless laughter which is effectively illustrated by the frat boy ; 2) the Stoic and Cynic laughter which has a therapeutic goal and occurs when a person realizes the discrepancy between philosophical values and the values of ordinary people; 3) the Aristophanic laughter in which we assist at the comic celebration of the human body and its needs. In the second part of her article Nussbaum examines the difficulty of classifying the laughter that we encounter in Seneca s Apocolocyntosis. Through a thoughtful and insightful analysis of Seneca s text Nussbaum shows that Apocolocyntosis presents a particular type of laughter which is centered on the notion of fastidium (i.e., disgust, revulsion at contamination. ) The disgust that Seneca describes in the Apocolocyntosis has, Nussbaum argues convincingly, the therapeutic effect of exposing life-styles and behaviours that a student of philosophy should feel compelled to reject. This article may be taken to support the idea that activities such as reading and writing can crucially contribute to the process of caring for the self an idea that Foucault strongly endorsed. 2 The section on Roman culture begins with a stimulating essay by E. Asmis: Seneca on fortune and the kingdom of god. Amis offers a fascinating analysis of the originality of Seneca s depiction of fortune. Different to most Stoic philosophers who recommend their followers to develop indifference towards fortune and her gifts, Seneca advocates engaging in a heroic fight against fortune. Amis s original interpretation of Seneca shows that we can find in the Roman thinker the seeds of the Renaissance ideal of the homo faber fortunae suae. Scholars of Foucault will find this article useful since it shows how the activity of caring for oneself was considered by authors such as Seneca to be a dramatic and agonistic process. C. Edwards Free yourself! Slavery, freedom, and the self in Seneca s Letters is an exemplary article which offers a very good example of how the knowledge of the historical and social context in which an author operates is crucial for an accurate understanding of his works. Edwards investigates how in his Letters Seneca often employs the images of the master and the slave to illustrate the challenges a person encounters when he tries to free himself from the slavery of passions and become master of his moral and spiritual self. Edwards shows that in order to fully appreciate the way Seneca uses the images of the master and the slave it is necessary to recognize the complex dynamics which were at play between slaves and masters in Seneca s time. The dialectic between the images of the master and the slave is used by Seneca, Edwards explains very persuasively, to illustrate the process that philosophers engage in when they abandon the self which is attached to external things and embrace the real self. The study of the way Seneca uses the images of the master and the slave to describe the process of acquisition of the real self offers further textual support to Fou- 2 Michel Foucault, Self Writing, in Michel Foucault, Ethics: Subjectivity, and Truth. Essential Works of Foucault 1954-1984, vol. 1, edited by Paul Rabinow (New York: Vintage Books, 1997), 207-222. 203

Foucault Studies, No. 11, pp. 200-205. cault s interpretation of Seneca as a philosopher who is concerned with understanding how to properly care for the self. J. Ker s Seneca on Self-examination: On Anger 3.36 concentrates on a famous Senecan text on which Foucault s interpretation of the Roman thinker heavily relies. Notoriously, Foucault considers On Anger 3.36 as an effective example of a particular technology of the self which Seneca employs to examine his own moral progress towards a conversion to self. Ker thoroughly examines Foucault s reading of On Anger 3.36 and highlights its merits as well as its problems. Then, Ker offers an extremely sophisticated literal analysis of On Anger 3.36 which leads him to show that the philosophical content of Seneca s text is closely connected to the particular literary style he employs. According to Ker, the care in choosing images or terms which effectively capture a philosophical idea that Seneca s text displays constitutes a specific technology which Seneca employs to connect with his true self. The activity of reflecting on how a general philosophical idea can be effectively conveyed requires an author, Ker thinks, to internalize such an idea and to connect it with his own self. On a more general note, Ker s article seems to correctly grasp the spirit of Foucault s reading of the Ancient world. Foucault aimed not to offer a definitive analysis of certain phenomena of the Ancient world, but to bring to our attention aspects of Antiquity which had been previously neglected in order to stimulate further research of the kind pursued in works such as Seneca and the Self. S. Bartsch s Senecan metaphor and Stoic self-instruction can be considered as the ideal continuation of Ker s article. Ker reflected on the importance of analyzing Seneca s language; Bartsch concentrates on a specific aspect of Seneca s language, i.e. his frequent use of metaphors. Traditionally, Seneca s fondness for metaphor has puzzled scholars who regarded with skepticism the use of metaphor in philosophical works. Bartsch considers the interpretations of Seneca s use of metaphor by Inwood and Mireille Armisen-Marchetti as indicative of two possible ways of reflecting on this issue. Inwood is unsympathetic of Seneca s recurrent use of metaphor since he considers that conveying a philosophical idea through a metaphor contains always the risk of distorting it. He argues that a serious exegesis of Seneca s works has to unveil the philosophical meaning that a metaphor conceals or skews. On the contrary, Mireille Armisen-Marchetti explores the pedagogical purposes of expressing philosophical ideas through metaphors; she argues that metaphors can facilitate the expression of abstract ideas by overcoming the limitations of human language. Bartsch acknowledges his debt to this second interpretation and argues that Seneca s use of metaphor has a selftherapeutic goal. Bartsch indicates that, in order to design a metaphor which can effectively express a specific philosophical view, an author has to internalize the doctrine in question and to relate it to his experience. In other words, the effort of choosing the appropriate metaphor requires an author to gain an in-depth knowledge of a theory. On this reading, the process of choosing which metaphor can best convey a particular philosophical idea can be a very effective aid, Bartsch argues, towards moral progress. Although Bartsch does not directly engage with Foucault s interpretation of Seneca his analysis of the therapeutic purpose of Senecan metaphors is very close to Foucault s idea that Ancient authors regarded the activity of writing as a technology of the self. The three articles which compose the last section of Seneca and the Self explore the relation between Seneca s tragedies and his philosophical works. In Seneca and the denial of 204

Donato: review of Seneca and the Self the self A. Schiesaro argues that the tragedies contain an analysis of the self as constituted by reason as well as passion which is ultimately incompatible with the way in which the self is presented in Seneca s philosophical works. In Seneca and Tragedy s Reason D. Wray shows that Seneca s philosophical production cannot be separated from his tragedies since they are both crucial for the articulation of his thought. Seneca s detached, almost clinical analysis of human beings that we get from the philosophical works is balanced by his tragedies graphic descriptions of the brutalities that human beings commit when they are in the grip of extreme passions. The article which concludes Seneca and the Self (i.e., A. Bush, Dissolution of the Self in the Senecan Corpus ) also focuses on the relation between Seneca s philosophical writings and his tragedies. Busch outlines the difference between the analysis of death and the afterlife that we find in Seneca s philosophical works and that which emerges from his tragedies. In his philosophical works Seneca proposes a fairly comforting idea of death which is described as either the end of all sufferings or the transition to a blessed afterlife. On the contrary, in the tragedies Seneca has a dark view of death which is portrayed as the transition to an afterlife characterized by sufferings that are even greater than the ones we can experience in this life. In conclusion, the collection Seneca and the Self offers a stimulating debate on a challenging topic of Seneca s philosophy and is a telling example of the lasting effect that Foucault s studies has had on the scholarship in Ancient philosophy and literature. Antonio Donato, D.phil Assistant Professor of Medieval and Renaissance Philosophy Queens College, CUNY New York USA 205