H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 1

Similar documents
I Hearkening to Silence

Chiasmi International



that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Leonard LAWLOR (The University of Memphis)

6. The Cogito. Procedural Work and Assessment The Cartesian Background Merleau-Ponty: the tacit cogito

Phenomenology and Structuralism PHIL 607 Fall 2011

1. What is Phenomenology?

ON GESTURAL MEANING IN ACTS OF EXPRESSION

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

Intentionality, Constitution and Merleau-Ponty s Concept of The Flesh

Dada and Existentialism

Mariana Larison, L être en forme. Dialectique et phénomenologie dans la dernière philosophie de Merleau-Ponty. Éditions Mimésis, 2016.

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

The Spell of the Sensuous Chapter Summaries 1-4 Breakthrough Intensive 2016/2017

Phenomenology Glossary

The Experience of Knowing:

EASTERN INTUITION AND WESTERN COGNITION: WHERE AND HOW DO THEY MEET?

RESPONSE AND REJOINDER

03 Theoretical discourse

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

On the motivations for Merleau-Ponty s ontological research

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

PH 8122: Topics in Philosophy: Phenomenology and the Problem of Passivity Fall 2013 Thursdays, 6-9 p.m, 440 JORG

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Introduction SABINE FLACH, DANIEL MARGULIES, AND JAN SÖFFNER

Surrender and Subjectivity: Merleau-Ponty and Patočka on Intersubjectivity

SENIOR SEMINAR: Aesthetics and the Philosophy of Art: Between Phenomenology and Semiotic. Fall 2012 & Winter 2013

1/9. The B-Deduction

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

what we see, what we ought to see.

Part I I On the Methodology oj the Social Sciences

Merleau-Ponty s Transcendental Project

Merleau-Ponty Final Take Home Questions

Zeynep Bulut Ph.D. Candidate Department of Music (Emphasis: Critical Studies/Experimental Practices) University of California, San Diego

Phenomenology of Perception

'A Direction of Thought': Speech, Reversibility and the World in Merleau- Ponty's Late Philosophy of Language. Martin Goldstein.

Conception of nature as foundation of a non-fundamental ontology Merleau-Ponty between the Nature lectures and The Visible and the Invisible

Truth's veil: language and meaning in Merleau- Ponty and Derrida

Embodied music cognition and mediation technology

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

THE APPLICATION OF PHENOMENOLOGICAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE REALM OF ARCHITECTURAL DESIGN ARC6989 REFLECTIONS ON ARCHITECTURAL DESIGN

observation and conceptual interpretation

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

What is Science? What is the purpose of science? What is the relationship between science and social theory?

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Visual Composition of Bodily Presence. A Phenomenological Approach to Paul Thomas Anderson s The Master

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

CHAPTER IV RETROSPECT

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

Devon Coutts Ontological Vibrations in Merleau-Ponty: Metaphor, Voice, and Linguistic Figuration

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

CARTESIAN MEDITATIONS

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Arakawa and Gins: The Organism-Person-Environment Process

The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and Reason by Mark Johnson, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987

This version was downloaded from Northumbria Research Link:

Philosophy and the Idea of Communism

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

art of everyday making. I love this turn of phrase. Everyday relates to all daily

Mass Communication Theory

The Existential Concept of Freedom for Maxine Greene: The Influence of Sartre and Merleau-Ponty on Greene s Educational Pedagogy

PHI 8119: Phenomenology and Existentialism Winter 2016 Wednesdays, 4:30-7:30 p.m, 440 JORG

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

MERLEAU-PONTY'S EXISTENTIAL CONCEPTION OF SCIENCE Joseph Rouse, Wesleyan University

GEORG W. F. HEGEL, JEAN-PAUL SARTRE AND MAURICE MERLEAU-PONTY: WHERE AND HOW DO THEY MEET?

foucault studies Richard A. Lynch, 2004 ISSN: pending Foucault Studies, No 1, pp , November 2004

SOULISTICS: METAPHOR AS THERAPY OF THE SOUL

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

Article: Hoel, A.S. and Carusi, A. (2018) Merleau-Ponty and the Measuring Body. Theory, Culture and Society, 35 (1). pp

Vinod Lakshmipathy Phil 591- Hermeneutics Prof. Theodore Kisiel

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

Film-Philosophy

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

ESSAYS IN PHENOMENOLOGY

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

Citation for the original published paper (version of record):

DARKNESS IN THE THEATRE: THE PERCEPTION OF THE EMBODIED SELF IN ACTION

Sam Gill, Dancing Culture Religion

AESTHETICS. PPROCEEDINGS OF THE 8th INTERNATIONAL WITTGENSTEIN SYMPOSIUM PART l. 15th TO 21st AUGUST 1983 KIRCHBERG AM WECHSEL (AUSTRIA) EDITOR

Musical Phenomenology: Artistic Traditions and Everyday Experience

THE ECOLOGICAL MEANING OF EMBODIMENT

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Existentialist Metaphysics PHIL 235 FALL 2011 MWF 2:20-3:20

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Imitating the Human Form: Four Kinds of Anthropomorphic Form Carl DiSalvo 1 Francine Gemperle 2 Jodi Forlizzi 1, 3

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

This essay will attempt to add to and expand upon a recent publication

Recommended: Dermot Moran, Introduction to Phenomenology (New York and London: Routledge, 2000).

The Pennsylvania State University. The Graduate School. College of the Liberal Arts IMPERATIVE SENSE AND LIBIDINAL EVENT. A Thesis in.

Charles Taylor s Langue/Parole and Alasdair MacIntyre s Networks of Giving and Receiving as a Foundation for a Positive Anti-Atomist Political Theory

PHIL 475 Topics in Contemporary European Philosophy Mon & Wed 2:35-3:55 SH

Merleau-Ponty s Intertwined Notions of Subjectivity and Intersubjectivity Douglas Low

Husserl s theory of perceptive donation according to profiles¹

Rethinking the Aesthetic Experience: Kant s Subjective Universality

Transcription:

H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 1 H-France Review Vol. 15 (October 2015), No. 136 Stephen A. Noble, Silence et langage: Genèse de la phénomenologie de Merleau-Ponty au seuil de l ontologie. Leiden and Boston: Brill, 2014. 285 pp. Editor s foreword, notes, bibliography, index, acknowledgments. $163.00 U.S. (cl.) ISBN 978-90-04-26651-3. Review by Glen A. Mazis, Penn State Harrisburg. Merleau-Ponty (1908-1961) is well-known as the French philosopher who redirected the traditional European philosophical and cultural tradition of identifying the self with a disembodied mind or inner spirit, instead locating the center of identity and knowing the world in human embodiment. Further, of great current intellectual interest is his later articulation of the ontology of the flesh of the world, in which all beings are interconnected and interdependent in a way that resembles a field paradigm in physics. Stephen Noble s book uncovers a key path of Merleau-Ponty s thought in tracing the continuity of his earliest analyses of the structure of perception within behavior to his arriving at his late indirect ontology. The central role that silence plays in Merleau-Ponty s being able to move from his analysis of perception, to the bringing forth of its deeper meaning in expression, to transforming philosophy from a grasp of a determinate world in concepts to an expression of the interwoven dimensions of meaning in the depths of the sensible, and its correlative ontology, has not be adequately appreciated by Merleau- Ponty s readers. Noble correctly argues that until the role of silence in expression is traced back to its origins in perception and seen in its ramifications for altering the course of philosophy, Merleau-Ponty s ontology will not be fully understood. Noble starts the book by pointing to Merleau-Ponty s ongoing effort to make us aware that the ordinary use of language masks its authentic function, to express our inherence in things (p. 3), or in other words, to express the way our sense of ourselves emerges from our intertwining with the world. Yet, to be able to express the primordial contact in perception with the world that was the focus of Merleau- Ponty s ontology, silence must be brought into language. This approaches contrasts with philosophy s traditional attempt to render how the world appears by employing second order concepts gained through reflection about this experience. Expressive language recognizes a silence of consciousness that envelops the speaking world and where the words first receive their configuration and sense ( un silence de la conscience qui enveloppe le monde parlant et où les mots d abord reçoivent configuration et sens ) (p. 4). Here, once again, Merleau-Ponty is at odds with much of the philosophical tradition in the way he understands silence. The decisive point, says Noble quite correctly is to see that the question of silence is not about an auditory nothing, but on the contrary concerns a modality of the world s being and that of sonorous being (p. 4). Silence, for Merleau-Ponty, is not the opposite of sound or of language, but is a quality of sense inaugurated by the nature of prereflective perceptual contact and runs throughout language in its expressive fabric. Noble rightly asserts that the role of silence grows after the 1945 publication of the Phenomenology of Perception and becomes even more central in Merleau-Ponty s last writings when he is formulating his indirect ontology. Tracing out the role of this silence is essential for phenomenology in order to fulfill its avowed task, as first articulated by Edmund Husserl, of returning to the things themselves, since silence leads us back to the originary experience of the things of the world through perception. The use of the word originary is deliberate, since phenomenology does not seek to grasp an impossible origin--

H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 2 impossible, since existence is relentless becoming--but rather sees each moment of expression as an endlessly ongoing origin of new sense, at least in language s expressive use. It is the progression of this theme of the role of silence in Merleau-Ponty s work that is the focus of Noble s book, tracing out the shifts in locution, emphasis, terminology, influence from other philosophers and Merleau-Ponty s historical context. In the first chapter, Noble examines Merleau-Ponty s first book, The Structure of Behavior, which was originally his minor doctoral thesis, and claims that his whole oeuvre is rooted there (p. 7). Noble traces how in this work Merleau-Ponty redefines interiority as gained through interchange with exteriority (pp. 11, 32); manages to find a middle course between determinism and finalism (p. 14); makes a dynamic sense of the gestalt central to his descriptions of perception; and reconfigures form as not an inherent given quality (pp. 16-24), but as an emergent phenomenon of expression of organisms (p. 29). If interiority is a co-emergence in and through the world, it is marked by contingency in a way ignored by traditional philosophy (p. 35). In this chapter, Noble asserts that Merleau-Ponty s ideas were influenced by Kant s treatment of purposiveness in the third Critique (pp. 12-14) and his description of productive imagination (p. 24); Kurt Goldstein s work, not solely by his idea of the gestalt, but also by his sketch of the relationship of organism to environment (pp. 17, 27); and, Edmund Husserl s sense of the opacity of the perceptual (p. 44). For Noble, The Structure of Behavior culminates in a sense that language is not conceptual, but rather perceptually driven in its development and expression. The paradoxes of language are discussed in the second chapter, and there especially Noble details what he sees as Merleau-Ponty s debt to the late writings of Husserl and to the work of Eugen Fink, who carried on Husserl s explorations. Merleau-Ponty s trip in 1939 to the Husserl archives at Louvain certainly had an impact upon the young philosopher (p. 59). Noble speculates that Fink s search for a language that could adequately articulate phenomenological insights (p. 62) inspired Merleau-Ponty, as well as Fink s call for a different logic (p. 65) and an interplay of natural language with transcendental language (p. 74). Noble sums up the achievement of the Phenomenology of Perception as the articulation of the connection between language and the sense of truth gained through perception, whereas in his later writing he will explore the connection of language with the truth of the flesh (p. 80). The third chapter explores Merleau-Ponty s developing ideas about the expressiveness of language after his the 1945 publication of the Phenomenology of Perception. Although first written in 1938, but not published until 1942, the essay Metaphysics and the Novel is, Noble feels, of exceptional importance (pp. 92-93). This importance stems both from its being the first statement by Merleau-Ponty that ties together the task of a revised metaphysics of everyday life or philosophy in general with the practice of literature, and from the content of its analysis of Simone de Beauvoir s novel, She Came to Stay. Like Emmanuel de Saint Aubert, Noble asserts that the friendship and the writings of de Beauvoir shifted Merleau-Ponty towards seeing philosophy as a shared articulation with literature, and ultimately requiring the use of literary language (p. 105).[1] It is helpful that Noble cites the 1959 interviews with Charbonnier, during which Merleau-Ponty discusses this shift (p. 113). Noble discusses other influences, such as Husserl s Cartesian Meditations (p. 95), Bréhier s questioning Merleau-Ponty for further explication of how to put the primacy of perception into language (p. 116), and the 1946 phenomenological conference in which this question of expression comes to the fore. As a result of this period of research, Noble feels that Merleau-Ponty had become focused on the deeper question, What is the being of language? This question leads to ontology and to fathoming the role of silence in both perception and expression (p. 124). Noble begins the third chapter by emphasizing a theme that runs throughout the book: that there is a strict continuity in Merleau-Ponty s philosophy from its earliest works to its last (p. 130). This has not often been asserted, as some are puzzled by the connection between the early works and the last writings, but I think that Noble is correct.[2] His citing of many of the unpublished writings helps to prove this case, as Merleau-Ponty often wrote about insights using terms that would only come to light

H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 3 in his published work later. The chapter focuses on Merleau-Ponty s 1949-50 course on The Child and the Acquisition of Language, his 1951-52 writing on the manuscript, The Prose of the World, which remained unfinished and was published posthumously, and his revision of part of the book, published in 1952 in Les temps modernes--his co-edited journal with Jean-Paul Sartre--as an essay, Indirect language and the Voices of Silence. Merleau-Ponty describes the child s unique way of being-in-the world (p. 132), the child s primal contact with being (p. 133), the way the child moves from silence to language as representative of the problem of all language use (p. 136), and how literature is tied to the coming into expression (p. 143). The writings in The Prose of the World manuscript pursue the articulation of the way silence enters language through poetry and the creative use of language. Noble contrasts these passages with those in the Phenomenology of Perception concerning the tacit cogito and silence. He feels the influence of Saussure has opened Merleau-Ponty to a more intersubjective sense of the how language emerges from perceptual experience, as a shared expression (p. 180). Noble notes how Merleau-Ponty navigates between Malraux s emphasis on the subjectivizing of literary and artistic expression and Saussure s overly impersonal emphasis on language s development and function (p. 183). Malraux has pointed to a silence that the individual faces in the impenetrability of perception (p. 187) and Saussure to the way there is a silencing of the personal creativity in language s totalizing of sense (p. 183-4), yet Merleau- Ponty will come to show that on an ontological level the meaning expressed by language can only emerge from a silence of the way the world envelops itself in perception (p. 190). In other words, Merleau-Ponty renders silence ontological. The final chapter explores the last works of Merleau-Ponty that culminate in his articulation of the ontology of the flesh, including the essay Eye and Mind, and the notes and writings of the unfinished projects such as Being and World (Être et Monde) or the incomplete manuscript and working notes that were published posthumously as The Visible and the Invisible. Noble contrasts Sartre s privileging of prose writing, as considered to be signifying, unlike poetry, which like painting, music or sculpture is not (p. 210). For Sartre, the writer of prose uses language to change the world and to engage in meaningful acts (p. 217). Silence, for him, is the non-being of the subject and the world which predates speech and is transcended by language (p. 212). For Merleau-Ponty, poetry and the poetic language are at the heart of language s expressive capacity and its ability to open intersubjectivity (p. 219), whereas for Sartre, poetic passages within prose introduce zones of obscurity (p. 221). Throughout the book, Noble has remarked that he finds an ambiguity in Merleau-Ponty s use of the terms world and nature, and he feels it persists even in these late writings, although he notes that term Umwelt is a term that moves between the two (pp. 232, 238). The chapter ends by explaining that for Merleau- Ponty the literary and creative use of language must dovetail with the philosophic use of language such that the sensible is made to manifest the invisible sense that is at its depths. Language can be used creatively to configure the visible in such a way that the invisible becomes manifest as dimensions of sense. This book is beautifully researched and is a treasure trove of biographical information, references to the unpublished writings archived in the Bibliothèque Nationale, and speculations concerning possible influences on Merleau-Ponty s thinking. It traces out carefully the evolution of the line of thinking, from the silence of perception to the way language expresses perception to the way that expression emerges from the thick interconnectedness of beings within the flesh such that only the indirect, allusive language of poetic language can express ontology. Along the way, Noble s assertion of the influences on Merleau-Ponty s thought like that of the late Husserl or Goldstein seems undeniable, while others such as that about Kant or Fink seem less certain. What is lacking from the book, however, is an exploration and description of the nature of silence, the expressive aspects of poetic and literary language, or even the nature of the ontology of the flesh in Merleau-Ponty s philosophy. The major concepts--silence, perception, expressive language, art, and the

H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 4 flesh--and all the concepts to which they are intimately related, such as the latency of perception, the phenomenology of silence in the gestures of the (perceived) world, the gestural aspect of language, metaphor, the imaginary, the reversibility of the perceiver and the perceived, lateral relations, and the differing idea of truth in regard to Merleau-Ponty s indirect ontology are not explicated at all or instantiated (a practice always followed by Merleau-Ponty). These stated terms and ideas are left as if they are self-evident, although Merleau-Ponty has given them unique senses that call for explicit description. The terms that are left out as well as the emphasis on the earliest works of Merleau-Ponty, especially The Structure of Behavior, point to a missing dimension of this book that needs to be supplemented by a fuller explanation of the topic. This lack is evident in the figures that Noble chooses to discuss as influencing Merleau-Ponty, such as Kant, Husserl, Goldstein, Fink and Malraux, instead of explaining the many references to and influence of Proust, Cézanne, Claudel, Valéry, Klee, Bergson, Bachelard and others who would have added another dimension to the book s understanding of silence and expressiveness. These sources would necessitate an examination of depth, of the expressiveness of silent gestures, of the role of the imagination in bringing out the latencies of perception, the nonrational logic of lateral relations, and in general a less rationalized framework of interpretation. The way that perception is obscure, for Merleau-Ponty, is not about the kind of impenetrable opacity that Noble discusses as allied with one type of silence. Rather, the obscurity of perception is as much about the inexhaustibility of its sense, which led Merleau-Ponty to privilege depth as the dimension of dimensions, since on a prereflective level there is always more sense to be manifest.[3] The way the world gestures to us and we respond to its beckonings as first discussed in the phenomenology of silence in the tacit cogito passages of the Phenomenology of Perception gives another sense to how silence envelops language as a latent depth of perceived sense that can become manifest [4]. Merleau- Ponty gradually articulates another type of imagination at odds with fantasy that instead works with perception to deepen the original sense of the perceived by making manifest latent meanings. Poetic language, if described in detail, and metaphor bring together that which seems to be incompossible, which is Merleau-Ponty s definition of depth. Silence can be allowed to enter language more fully to bring these depths to expression. NOTES [1] Emmanuel de Saint Aubert, Du lien des êtres aux éléments de l être (Paris: J. Vrin, 2004), pp. 61-104. [2] Again, Emmanuel de Saint Aubert is in complete agreement with this assertion, and he was the custodian of Merleau-Ponty s unpublished writings after Claude Lefort and has studied them in great detail. [3] Maurice Merleau-Ponty, L oeil et l esprit (Paris: Gallimard, 1964), p. 79. [4] Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phénoménologie de la perception (Paris: Gallimard, 1945), p. 462. Glen A. Mazis Penn State Harrisburg gam7@psu.edu Copyright 2015 by the Society for French Historical Studies, all rights reserved. The Society for French Historical Studies permits the electronic distribution of individual reviews for nonprofit educational purposes, provided that full and accurate credit is given to the author, the date of publication, and the location of the review on the H-France website. The Society for French Historical Studies reserves the right to withdraw the license for edistribution/republication of individual reviews

H-France Review Volume 15 (2015) Page 5 at any time and for any specific case. Neither bulk redistribution/ republication in electronic form of more than five percent of the contents of H-France Review nor re-publication of any amount in print form will be permitted without permission. For any other proposed uses, contact the Editor-in-Chief of H-France. The views posted on H-France Review are not necessarily the views of the Society for French Historical Studies. ISSN 1553-9172