Philosophica, 48, Lisboa, 2016, pp

Similar documents
7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

Foucault's Archaeological method

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

1/9. The B-Deduction

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Phenomenology Glossary

BDD-A Universitatea din București Provided by Diacronia.ro for IP ( :46:58 UTC)

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

The Second Copernican Turn of Kant s Philosophy 1

The Historicity of Understanding and the Problem of Relativism in Gadamer's Philosophical Hermeneutics

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Categories and Schemata

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Significant Differences An Interview with Elizabeth Grosz

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

POST-KANTIAN AUTONOMIST AESTHETICS AS APPLIED ETHICS ETHICAL SUBSTRATUM OF PURIST LITERARY CRITICISM IN 20 TH CENTURY

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

The Debate on Research in the Arts

Foucault's Technologies of the Self: A Kantian Project?

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

The Outside of the Political

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, 2d ed. transl. by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall (London : Sheed & Ward, 1989), pp [1960].

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

Summary of the Transcendental Ideas

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

A new grammar of visual design Entrevista com Gunther Kress Helena Pires*

TABLE OF CONTENTS PREFACE... INTRODUCTION...

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

The Teaching Method of Creative Education

GRADUATE SEMINARS

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Lecture 24 Sociology 621 December 12, 2005 MYSTIFICATION

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

1/10. The A-Deduction

The Role of Imagination in Kant's Theory of Reflective Judgment. Johannes Haag

Deconstructing Prinz s moral theory. Desconstruindo a teoria moral de Prinz

CRITIQUE AS UNCERTAINTY

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Culture and Art Criticism

observation and conceptual interpretation

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

On The Search for a Perfect Language

«Only the revival of Kant's transcendentalism can be an [possible] outlet for contemporary philosophy»

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Post Structuralism, Deconstruction and Post Modernism

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

Marx, Gender, and Human Emancipation

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Ontological and historical responsibility. The condition of possibility

Leverhulme Research Project Grant Narrating Complexity: Communication, Culture, Conceptualization and Cognition

Cover Page. The handle holds various files of this Leiden University dissertation.

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

UMAC s 7th International Conference. Universities in Transition-Responsibilities for Heritage

Human Finitude and the Dialectics of Experience

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

INHIBITED SYNTHESIS. A Philosophy Thesis by Robin Fahy

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

2007 Issue No. 15 Walter Benjamin and the Virtual Aura as Productive Loss By Warwick Mules

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Chapter 2: The Early Greek Philosophers MULTIPLE CHOICE

Emília Simão Portuguese Catholic University, Portugal. Armando Malheiro da Silva University of Porto, Portugal

Transcription:

Paulo Frazão Roberto, The Concept of Man in Foucault s Les mots et les choses [O Conceito de Homem em Les mots et les choses de Foucault], M.A. Dissertation in Philosophy, Faculdade de Letras da Universidade de Lisboa, 2014. The main object of our dissertation is the concept of man in Foucault s Les mots et les choses, analysed from a critical and hermeneutical point of view. The leitmotiv of our study is a common misunderstanding of the controversial utterance on the death of man at the end of Les mots et les choses. Our attempt of conceptual elucidation is, at least, partially, a critical problematization of that one formulation, whose persistent misunderstanding has been, in our opinion, an obstacle to the intelligibility of the concept of man in Foucault s thought. Like the other works of the archaeological period, Les mots et les choses (1966) is grosso modo a historical philosophical analysis of the conditions of possibility (the historical subsoil ) behind the emergence of some human sciences. However, unlike Histoire de la folie (1961) or Naissance de la Clinique (1963), works focusing on specific sciences (psychiatry and medicine) that consider man in his concrete depth, Les mots et les choses is, as its subtitle clearly indicates, an archaeology of the human sciences. The question of man is not only understood in a broader sense, but problematized as such in the form of a greater conceptual framework. It is clearly established in Les mots et les choses preface that one of the basic principles of the archaeological analysis is that all thought, knowledge or empirical perceptive experience is developed within an existent order, i.e., within a given relation between words and things. Being a fundamental and constitutive dimension a historical a priori, although not eternal or immutable, this order presents different and changeable historical modes of being. Each order establishes its own episteme, i.e., the general configuration of knowledge (savoir) that defines the conditions of thought and knowledge (connaissance) in a given time period. Being a historical philosophical analysis, archaeology is, however, quite distant from the traditional history of ideas or of science s ap Philosophica, 48, Lisboa, 2016, pp. 133-147. Philosophica 48.indd 133

134 proaches. While these privilege a retrospective and continuous narrative of the progress of knowledge (connaissance) and science, archaeology explores the historical modes of being of the order that constitute knowledge (savoir) in a certain period (episteme). In Les mots et les choses two great distinctive and discontinuous spaces of order, and consequently of knowledge (savoir), are identified: the classical episteme (XVII and XVIII centuries) and the modern episteme (from the XIX century to the present). From the Renaissance to Modernity, the archaeological analyses of Les mots et les choses consider mainly the domains of life, labour and language in each of their underlying epistemic configurations. It is in this temporal scope, and in these fields of knowledge, that Foucault problematizes the question of the concept of man. The conclusion of Les mots et les choses states two strong polemic and seemingly odd theses on the concept of man: man is a recent invention in the order of knowledge it only emerged and established itself as an epistemological object in Modernity that is maybe on the verge of disappearing ( the death of man ). Challenging an evidence more or less accepted since Socrates, Foucault sustains that man is not the most ancient and constant object of knowledge in history. It does not date from the Renaissance either, even if Man is commonly understood as the major example of the renaissance microcosm. Strongly permeated with a cosmological point of view, the renaissance episteme is ruled by the category of resemblance. In the great book of nature (macrocosm), knowledge is built on relations of analogy, and through the interpretation of similarities between signatures (words and things). Therefore, the knowledge that man may have of himself as a microcosm is formed based on the search and identification of resemblances with and in the macrocosm. This means that, in the Renaissance, man is reflected in the great mirror of the Cosmos, more than actually constituted as an object of knowledge. And it does not date from the Classical Age either, which is precisely the period in which man himself comes through as a rational being, closely connected with the figure of the Cartesian cogito. Ruled by the category of representation, the classical episteme has its paradigm in that very same figure. Analogously to Velázquez s Las meninas, understood as a representation of the classical representation, the Cartesian cognition is described as a process in which the subject is placed in an invisible central point that opens the space of the world and in which all the visible things are disposed, as subjects, to his sovereign gaze and the ordering force of Philosophica 48.indd 134

135 his representation. Nevertheless, like the absent sovereigns of Las meninas, man as subject cogito does not appear in the tableau of cognitive representation. Foucault shows it in the analysis of the classical sciences of life (natural history), labour (analysis of wealth) and language (general grammar). Since representation is an instance of the subject, existing and being developed inside him, and not of the things themselves, in the cognitive process man never places himself as otherness of that very representation of which he is, however, the founder. This means that man is not yet known as such, but presented in the image of God, with an infinite power of omni representation. Recalling Kant, Foucault will speak of a sort of representative metaphysics of reason under whose dogmatic sleep the classical thought and knowledge will fall. Consequently, despite the central and privileged role it has in the renaissance humanism and in classical rationalism, man did not exist as the epistemological object of a proper and specific domain of knowledge. In the threshold of the modern episteme, the empirical sciences (biology, economics, philology) and Kant s transcendental philosophy will open the possibility for a knowledge in which, according to Foucault, man will appear effectively seen and constituted as an epistemological object for the first time. The substantial change that occurs with the empirical sciences is the fact that a new relation is established between subject and object in knowledge. No longer ordered in the infinite representative instance inherent to the cogito, to the empirical sciences the object is now something that has a concrete and independent existence from the knowing subject. To the point that such a subject is now projected as an object of knowledge by those sciences, in his concrete otherness of human being. While studying the empirical phenomena of life, labour and language objects that have their own immanent laws of behaviour, independent of the cognitive subject the empirical sciences provide knowledge of man represented in his finitude, as a living animal being (biology) that produces, exchanges and desires things (economics) or speaks (philology). Kant s transcendental philosophy researches the human faculties in the cognitive process; it aims to determine the a priori conditions of possibility that allow the subject to be the founder of knowledge. However, unlike classical rationalism, in which knowledge is based on the infinite representative power of the cogito, Kant restricts the cognitive scope of human faculties. Knowledge is, in the subject, a synthesis between an intellectual representation (understanding) and a spatial temporal representation of the phenomenal diversity (sensibility). Inextricably linked to sensibility in the in Philosophica 48.indd 135

136 itial foundation of its possibility, human knowledge is limited and finite. This means that, on the cognitive level, the transcendental position of the subject is always accompanied by the conscience of the limits of his human finitude. Due to this double position as object of empirical knowledge and transcendental subject of knowledge man assumes the strange position of an empirical transcendental doublet. Being at the same time a transcendental subject and an empirical object of knowledge, it is now possible to man, by means of a synthetic operation of thought, to place himself as target of his own knowledge. It is in this sense that Foucault holds the thesis that man only appears in the modern order of knowledge (savoir). Given his intrinsic transcendental limits and his projection as an empirical object, a constitutive finitude is inherent to that double position of man. To Foucault, the empirico transcendental finitude of man acquires the status of a positivity upon which modern thought and knowledge are grounded and constituted. To such an extent that one might say that the modern episteme has the Man Form. Modern philosophy will not avoid it. In fact, it is essentially anthropological and finds its major reference in the ultimate question of Kant s philosophical system (to which converged the questions of the three Critiques): Was ist der Mensch? Despite this lineage, unlike Kant, modern philosophy will not distinguish between the transcendental and the empirical levels. Due to this confusion, it is no longer the transcendental structures of the subject but rather man as an empirical transcendental finitude (in his undistinguishable anthropological whole) that is the positive foundation of thought and knowledge. Philosophical reflection takes then the form of an analytics of finitude, in which man incessantly and bi directionally exists and is known in those two poles : improperly assimilated as his exclusive property, the empirical modes of being of man are unfolded in a transcendental presumption; and it is in this tainted way that the transcendental groundwork considers, in its turn, those modes of being. Ensnared in the vicious circle of an endless analysis enclosed in human finitude, the Kantian transcendental is anthropologized and modern philosophical thought falls, according to Foucault, into a deep anthropological sleep. Embedded in the same epistemic magma, the human sciences reveal an even greater hybridism concerning the transcendental and the empirical levels. Presuming to abide the transcendental requirement, they are a knowledge that generates a new form of representation developed by means of a relational reduplication of the objectivities (about man) produced by their homologous empirical sciences. Psychology, sociology and Philosophica 48.indd 136

137 language analysis study the representations that man constructs of himself: as a living being (biology), as a social being that works, produces, exchanges and needs (economics), and as a speaking being (philology). This form of representation of the human sciences is the field in which is played the groundwork of his knowledge: a sort of transcendental mobility between what is given to representation (man s empirical modes of being) and the subject that makes that representation possible. Albeit having implicit the figure of man as an undistinguishable empirical transcendental doublet, the knowledge of the human sciences is not based on its own grounding: redoubling them, it is dependent of the relations established with (and between) the empirical sciences and the anthropological philosophy. This absence of proper grounds is manifest when Foucault, using the figure of a trihedron, analyses the position of the human sciences in the panorama of modern knowledge. In that trihedron each one of the faces corresponds to a given domain of knowledge: empirical sciences, formal sciences (mathematics, physics), philosophy; kinds of knowledge that preserve their own autonomous surface, insofar as they do not communicate by interpenetration. Human sciences do not even have a surface. Suspended in the vacuum of the trihedron s open base, they lack a proper grounding (that is, foundations). The human sciences only develop their knowledge by placing themselves inside the trihedron s volume, parasitizing the epistemological territories of the other three domains. In this sense, their groundwork comes from a mixture of and with those domains of knowledge, an amalgam from which they sustain and erect the eclectic construction of their object: man. In spite of their feeble foundations, human sciences were successful: namely, in their application in institutional domains in which the definition of man is at stake, as Foucault shows in his accounts of the asylum, the clinic or the prison. From the point of view of those sciences, the reason why they succeed in becoming a sort of supreme synthesis a more scientifically exact, comprehensive and proficient form of knowledge about man, is that they incorporated the concepts and methods of the formal and empirical sciences. In the opinion of Foucault, to whom the practical affirmation of a form of theoretical knowledge is inseparable from a relational exercise of power, the human sciences became predominant because, given precisely the amalgam of their feeble foundations, their conception of man was mouldable enough towards the strategies and objectives of institutional knowledge (that exercises power and imposes order) dealing with the resistances that, at the individual and social levels, rose against their implementation. Philosophica 48.indd 137

138 Foucault considered this moulding possibility: based on the relational reduplication of man s representation as a living being gifted with functions in his adaptation to the social environment (biology), with conflicting needs and interests (economics), and whose conducts have meaning (philology), psychology, sociology and language analysis formulate, respectively, norms of adjustment, rules of organization and systems of signs to interpret those conducts. The order of the terms will be, however, inverted: norms, rules and systems will become the foundation and explicative principle of the biological functions, socio economic conflicts and human meanings. Given the wide ranging assumption of the human sciences, these principles constitute a sort of universal categorical imperative (ought to be) that covers the entire human dimension, postulating (ought to have) such and such ends. This grants a positivist optimism to their knowledge in what concerns the possibility to control the nature and being of man freeing him from subjection and alienation based on that categorical net of norms, rules and systems. To Foucault that possibility is not only illusory but also, and fundamentally, potentially dangerous. Expansion of an inversion erected on an amalgam of feeble foundations, there is a kind of malleability inherent to those categories that, specifically in their institutional application, makes them susceptible of being adapted according to the ends intended (sometimes justified by philosophical and/or moral humanist ideologies). This not always brings about the best results. For instance, when the human sciences entered the asylum (Histoire de la folie) or the prison (Surveiller et punir), instead of freeing man, they contributed to his subjection and alienation. This is why Foucault states, in Les mots et les choses, in a somewhat anti humanist way, that anthropologization is the major internal danger of modern knowledge (savoir). However, the debility that makes human sciences potentially dangerous is also what places them in danger, what makes them precarious. That debility is manifest in three particular domains of knowledge psychoanalysis, ethnology, linguistics that Foucault names human counter sciences. Mostly, they reveal the epistemological error in which human sciences fall into when they pretend to ground the origin of man s knowledge exclusively in man, that is, in the alleged a priori principles that emanate from his being and grant him the possibility to constitute, in his sovereign finitude, the knowledge of himself. In this sense, psychoanalysis shows that the nucleus of thought is not in the conscience but in the unconscious; when one analyses individual behaviour one finds instincts and drives, one does not find man. Ethnology, on the other hand, shows that other societies are irreducible to the regulating principles of western Philosophica 48.indd 138

139 society; when one analyses the way in which a society functions one finds organizing structures, one does not find man. Finally, linguistics shows that language has pre existing autonomous laws within which we speak: it is in those laws, and not in man, that the analysis of meaning is carried out. So, without using the concept of man, showing that they can provide a more positive knowledge of man, the counter sciences cause an epistemological rift in the human sciences, helping the disaggregation and dissolution of man (as an empirical transcendental doublet) on whose representation they lay and erect their knowledge. This dissolution is reinforced by history. History shows that, in their historicity, the empiricities (life, labour, language) that human sciences anthropologize in order to provide knowledge not only possess an autonomous dimension, pre existing man, but cannot be assimilated as exclusively human (in both cases, the most obvious example is life). The counter sciences and history show that the constitution of the knowledge that man has of himself is made in connexion with what is not (exclusively) human, that the foundations of that knowledge obey to conditions that elude his control and to which human sciences (and philosophy) are necessarily indebted. These not exclusively human determinant foundations (individual and social unconscious, language), given their greater positivity and temporal scope, lay bare that man as a subject of knowledge that does not sovereignly and absolutely hold his conscience or his language is more constituted than the constitutive place of the knowledge of himself, a sort of epiphenomenon. Therefore, man does not occupy the place of the king in the order of knowledge (of himself) that the human sciences and philosophy grant him. In an epistemological and ontological conceptual dimension, the counter sciences and history show that man, the human being, is essentially characterized by his transitivity, in a triple sense: he is a place of transit in what regards less transitive dimensions (life, language); he needs the complementation of those less transitive dimensions in order to constitute himself (in his being and in his knowledge); historically, he is something transitory, something whose form is always becoming. Insofar as he needs less transitive dimensions (specifically, language), it is in this transitivity that man is archeologically understood throughout Les mots et les choses. Unlike the partisans of humanist philosophies who, based on the essentialist presupposition of a teleological or dialectical progress of human reason in history, conceive man as a temporal but perfectible being, Foucault does not consider that man possesses an intemporal essence or nature. Far from that kind of ideal horizon, Foucault Philosophica 48.indd 139

140 analyses man as a concept in his historical constitution and functions in the domain of knowledge (savoir): man appeared, and acquired a given form that, in time, can be transformed or even disappear. Therefore, it is in this epistemological conceptual sense and, obviously, not in an organic or vital one that Foucault announces that man, that recent invention in western knowledge, is maybe on the verge of disappearing as the major figure that shapes the modern episteme (to which we eventually belong). Signs of this possible epistemological change are, on the one hand, the already mentioned transitivity of man exposed by the counter sciences (which have some affinities with some of the theoretical positions of structuralism), and, on the other hand, a certain inflexion in the fundamental question of contemporary philosophy: not so much what is man? (Kant) but rather, more and more, what is being? (Heidegger). Incidentally, this disquiet in the modern archaeological subsoil, symptom of a possible and impending disappearance of man, was already suspected by Nietzsche. We find it in the prophecy that the death of God would imply, but not immediately, the death of man that would be a preparation to the future advent of the Übermensch. Indeed, although having killed God, man did not emancipate himself of all the related divine omni attributes. In order to compensate the void left by such a death, man (in his fundamental finitude) sought to transfer the essence of those attributes metamorphosing and consubstantiating them to a rational Subject understood as origin and foundation of knowledge, as master of his conscience and freedom that accomplishes and destinies himself teleologically in the world. It is a reconfigured and essentialist image of man, reassuring concerning his place in the world, that the ancient and tenacious humanism, now under a new guise (close to the positivist optimism of the human sciences and the anthropological philosophy), adopts and redefines, reinforcing the anthropological sleep in which modern thought has fallen. However, as the archaeological analyses of Les mots et les choses have shown, pointing to an eventual evanescence of the humanist ideal, it is an image not only epistemologically feeble and illusory but also, on an ideological and political level, potentially manipulatable and dangerous. Facing a humanism that stubbornly considers man in his sacred unquestionable essence, the polemic death of man seems to be the assumption of a kind of active nihilism that is the previous and indispensable condition to awaken and free the modern thought from the anthropological lethargy in which it is incarcerated. It is therefore in the context of a critical diagnosis of Modernity, whose episteme has the Man Form, that Philosophica 48.indd 140

141 one may understand Foucault s anti humanism. This liberating nihilism connected to the death of man (which is not an end in itself) does not imply, however, a gap to fill. It rather aims to unfold a space, potentially communicative, where it will become truly possible to think anew. In this sense, man will tend to disappear from the order of modern knowledge (savoir) as soon as a new form is found. Eventually placed in the threshold of a new episteme, that different exercise of thought may give place and contribute to the constitution of another form of knowledge (savoir), that to us is still undetermined, i.e., heterotopic. To conclude, besides trying to elucidate that the often misunderstood death of man has a liberating intention for modern thought (challenging it), our hermeneutical analysis of Les mots et les choses aimed to show that for Foucault there is no irreducible secret nature or essence of man whose truth one must unveil or that, as a knowing subject, man might constitute himself as an intransitive instance and seminal place of the groundwork of knowledge. Unlike the traditional historian of ideas, seeking to provide a continuous and teleological sense of unity of man in time, to the archaeologist, man is analysed as a subsidiary and operative concept inside determinant but provisory historical conditions. Dissertation full text available online at: http://hdl.handle.net/10451/12208 Bruno Giancarli, Il concetto di Grazia nel pensiero del primo Lukács. Tese de Mestrado em Filosofia, Faculdade de Letras da Universidade de Lisboa, 2016. Orientador: José Barata Moura. Premissa Expor uma dissertação significa mostrar não apenas o seu conteúdo mas também a sua forma lógica. Esta sinopse estará dividida em duas partes: na primeira serão indicadas as razões da tese em si, ou seja, as suas premissas metodológicas, e na segunda os motivos fundamentais que a compõem. Trata se de uma operação preferível ao simples resumo. Convém, portanto, começar por explicar tudo o que está implícito na tese. Contextualização A premissa fundamental da dissertação é essencialmente uma: o trabalho faz sentido apenas a partir de uma perspectiva hegeliana. Sem consi Philosophica 48.indd 141