AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY A PLEA FOR A PEIRCEAN TURN IN ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY

Similar documents
Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

PHI6500: seminar times to be arranged early in the course. Short Essay deadline: Thursday 29th November (Thursday week 10)

Pragmatism and Idealism

COURSE SYLLABUS. 1. Information about the programme

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY. The History of Reception of Charles S. Peirce in Greece 1

Science as a Form of Life and Cross-disciplinarity: Mariano Artigas and Charles S. Peirce

SCHOLARSHIP ON THE RELATIONS BETWEEN LUDWIG WITTGENSTEIN AND CHARLES S. PEIRCE *

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

WILLIAM JAMES STUDIES VOLUME 14 NUMBER 1 SPRING 2018 PP

SYNTHESE LIBRARY STUDIES IN EPISTEMOLOGY, LOGrC, METHODOLOGY, AND PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE. Managing Editor: Editors:

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Peirce and Semiotic an Introduction

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Richard Rorty s Pragmatism

Kent Academic Repository

IS SCIENCE PROGRESSIVE?

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Richard J. Bernstein and the Pragmatist Turn in Contemporary Philosophy

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

Meaning and Modernity Social Theory in the Pragmatic Attitude

Thinking of or Thinking Through Diagrams? The Case of Conceptual Graphs.

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

Conceptual Change, Relativism, and Rationality

The Self as an Object of Criticism: Richard Rorty s Denial of the Objectivity of Truth. Do Kien Trung, Kobe University, Japan

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

International conference on William James and Pragmatism

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

The Ancient Philosophers: What is philosophy?

VALUES AND VALUING [Adapted from Carl Mitcham, ed., Encyclopedia of Science, Technology, and Ethics (New York: Macmillan Reference, 2005).

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

CHAPTER - II. Pragmatism of Charles Sanders Peirce

Bent Sørensen and Torkild Leo Thellefsen

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

The History of Philosophy. and Course Themes

The Concept of Nature

Nature's Perspectives

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

On Recanati s Mental Files

References DOI: /

The Humanities as Conversation and Edification: On Rorty s Idea of a Gadamerian Culture

PHIL/HPS Philosophy of Science Fall 2014

138 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 11. Meaning. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/meaning

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

NATURE FROM WITHIN. Gustav Theodor Fechner and His Psychophysical. Michael Heidelberger. Translated by Cynthia Klohr. University of Pittsburgh Press

Inquiry and the Fourth Grade of Clearness

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

Confines of Democracy

PH 360 CROSS-CULTURAL PHILOSOPHY IES Abroad Vienna

A Semiotic View of Information: Semiotics as a Foundation of LIS Research in Information Behavior

I n t r o d u c t i o n t o a n d C o m m e n t a r y o n J e n n i f e r H o r n s b y s Truth: The Identity Theory GILA SHER

French theories in IS research : An exploratory study on ICIS, AMCIS and MISQ

Immanuel Kant s Critique of Pure Reason

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

The Pennsylvania State University. The Graduate School. College of the Liberal Arts THE SLOW PERCOLATION OF FORMS: CHARLES PEIRCE S WRITINGS ON PLATO

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

PRAGMATIST METAETHICS

In inquiry into what constitutes interpretation in natural science. will have to reflect on the constitutive elements of interpretation and three

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

44 Iconicity in Peircean situated cognitive Semiotics

Terminology. - Semantics: Relation between signs and the things to which they refer; their denotata, or meaning

The Philosopher George Berkeley and Trinity College Dublin

Nordic Studies in Pragmatism

The Pragmatic Turn, by Richard J. Bernstein. Cambridge: Polity, 2010,, The Pragmatic Turn, Polity, Cambridge Malden 2010, xi pp.

FIFTY KEY CONTEMPORARY THINKERS

Symposium on Semiotics and Mathematics with the Special Theme 'Peirce, the Mathematician', June 11 13

Two Roads to Wisdom? Chinese and Analytic Philosophical Traditions, edited by Bo Mou (La Salle, Illinois: Open Court, 2001; pp. xvii, 381).

Inter-subjective Judgment

Community of Inquiry and Inquiry- based learning

Philip Joseph Kain. Santa Clara University Scotts Valley, CA Santa Clara, CA fax

Pragmatism, Semiotic mind and Cognitivism

Course Structure for Full-time Students. Course Structure for Part-time Students

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Rorty, Dewey, and Incommensurability

BOOK REVIEW: JOHN DEWEY BETWEEN PRAGMATISM RECONSTRUCTING DEMOCRACY, RECONTEXTUALIZING DEWEY: PRAGMATISM AND INTERACTIVE CONSTRUCTIVISM

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

Rereading Kuhn REVIEW ARTICLE. Jouni-Matti Kuukkanen

Ideology the Metalanguage of Culture

Aesthetics By Nicolai Hartmann

Cultural Pragmatism and the Life of the Sign. Gary Richmond City University of New York

Capstone Design Project Sample

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

EUROPEAN JOURNAL OF PRAGMATISM AND AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Anyone interested in George Herbert Mead has much occasion to rejoice. Review Essay/ Essai Bibliographique. Mead

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Transcription:

AMERICAN PHILOSOPHY A PLEA FOR A PEIRCEAN TURN IN ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY Jaime Nubiola Universidad de Navarra ABSTRACT: Criticisms of analytic philosophy have increased in intensity in the last decade, denouncing specifically its closing in on itself, which results in barrenness and ignorance of real human problems. The thought of C. S. Peirce is proposed as a fruitful way of renewing the analytic tradition and obviating these criticisms. While this paper is largely a reflection on Hilary Putnam s study of the historical development of analytic philosophy, not only can some of its main roots be traced back to Peirce, but also the recent resurgence of pragmatism can be regarded as a pragmatist renovation of the analytic tradition. Further, Peirce s thought offers suggestions for tackling some of the most stubborn problems in contemporary philosophy, thereby enabling us to shoulder once more the philosophical responsibility which has been abdicated by much of twentieth-century philosophy. The most accurate understanding of Peirce is to see him as a traditional and systematic philosopher, but one dealing with the modern problems of science truth, and knowledge from a valuable personal experience as a logician and an experimental researcher in the bosom of an interdisciplinary community of scientists and thinkers. "Most people have never heard of him, but they will" W. Percy, "The Divided Creature", 80 Criticisms of analytic philosophy have increased in intensity in the last decade, denouncing specifically its closing in on itself, resulting in barrenness and ignorance of real human problems. It is not only the genius loci, nor the echoes of his Sesquicentennial Congress held here in Boston in September, 1989, but within the solemn framework of a World Congress of Philosophy on the threshold of a new century, I wish to propose the study of Charles Sanders Peirce's thought as a fruitful way there may be others of renewing the analytic tradition and obviating those criticisms. On the one hand, not only can some of the main roots of analytic philosophy be traced back to Peirce, but the recent resurgence of pragmatism (Bernstein, 1992) can also be regarded as a pragmatist renovation of analytic philosophy. On the other hand, Peirce's thought offers suggestions for tackling some of the most stubborn problems in contemporary philosophy, and in particular he may help us to shoulder once again the philosophical responsibility which has been largely abdicated by much of 20th century philosophy (Debrock, 1992: 1). 3

In order to show this, my paper is divided in four sections: 1) A brief description of the decline of analytic philosophy; 2) the return of the history of philosophy as a key to its recovery; 3) Charles S. Peirce's relevance, and finally, 4) Peirce and analytic philosophy. 1. The decline of analytic philosophy When Wolfgang Spohn became the managing editor of the new Erkenntnis he referred to its first eight volumes as "a historically singular document, signaling a new era in philosophy with great enthusiasm and optimism" (Spohn, 1990:1). But sixty years after the founding of Erkenntnis it is really difficult to be so enthusiastic about analytic philosophy when one notices the decline of logical empiricism, the bewildering specialization within philosophical inquiry, and contemporary disorientation and eclecticism in philosophy. These trends can be seen as the price of pluralism, as Spohn thought, but also as the derailment of analytic philosophy. According to the standard view analytic philosophy in the hands of European émigrés took over the departments of Philosophy in the American universities in the fifties, becoming the dominant philosophy of the sixties and seventies. The striking fact as Rorty vigorously pointed out was that that philosophy which had promised to solve all the genuine philosophical problems arising from scientific activity, thirty years later, it was defined neither by a set of problems systematically studied, nor by some common methods of dealing with them, but only by a mere style or argumentative ability (Rorty, 1982: 211-230). The increasing diversity of issues enabled Rorty to assert that "'Philosophy' in the narrow and professional sense is just whatever we philosophy professors do" (1982: 220). This situation springs from the failure of the foundationalist project of scientific philosophy, which left as its legacy an aggressive cultural relativism which has pervaded academic philosophy until today. But this is not the only possible reading of the recent history of philosophy. It is also possible to identify in the analytic philosophy of the last decade the beginning of a renewal. Although analytic philosophy claimed to be a piecemeal philosophy, its 'motor' as Putnam (1983: 303) described was logical positivism. With the shipwreck of the foundationalist program, analytic philosophy began to lose shape as a tendency. What current analytic philosophers are trying to do is not to save the wreckage of foundationalism, but to reach an understanding of the history of its failure and of the nature of philosophical reflection itself. Philosophy might then be understood as being very similar to art, literature and history (Wittgenstein, 1980: 70), and along these lines it might be possible to close the gap between philosophy as an academic discipline and the deepest aspirations of men and women to know and to live a 'good life'. 4

2. The return of the history of philosophy as a key to its recovery The overwhelming dominance of the analytic tradition in the Anglo-American world in the last forty years has resulted in neglect of the study of history of thought. As Hilary Putnam wrote, "The long dominance of the idea that 'philosophy is one thing and history of philosophy is another' is now visibly coming to an end" (Putnam, 1997: 200). In some sense, Putnam's own intellectual biography can be understood as an iterated reflection on analytic tradition overcoming its scientism, its "refusal to hear other sorts of philosophy" (Putnam, 1997: 202), and trying to link the problems of philosophers with the problems of men and women, because "it is part of the task of a responsible philosophy to bring out the connection" (Harlan, 1992: 22). The kantian dualism between two concepts of philosophy, Schulbegriff and Weltbegriff, has probably reached its paroxysm in current Anglo-American Universities, in which Nietzsche, Derrida and other continental philosophers have been exiled to the departments of literature and the history of philosophy has been generally downgraded in philosophy departments. In this sense, the high tradition of analytic philosophy which traces its roots back to the seminal writings of Frege, Russell and the Vienna Circle can be understood as the fullest realization of the aspiration of philosophy in its Schulbegriff (Conant, 1990: xxvi). The only alternative to 'metaphysical realism', i. e., to scientism, is not some form of skepticism à la Rorty. Putnam's attempt to rediscover American pragmatist tradition is really attractive: both concepts of philosophy are complementary aspects of a single field of activity. Philosophical enterprise can achieve full fruition when it is pursued under the aspect of each. The analytic tradition might recover its position of leadership in philosophy if it openly rejects "any form of metaphilosophical dualism that takes twin aspirations of rigor and human relevance as the hallmarks of two distinct and incommensurable kinds of philosophical activity" (Conant, 1990: xxxii). A key source for this 'flashback' process, for this retrieval of 'old good philosophy', is the discovery of a continuous tradition within American thought, which has its beginnings in the debates at Harvard between Royce and James, in the work of Peirce and Dewey, and in the teaching of Lewis (Putnam, 1990: 267), and which is flourishing today. American pragmatism has commonly been seen by European philosophers as something parochial and outside the mainstream of philosophy. Pragmatism is often understood as an 'American way' of dealing with knowledge and truth, but as something alien to the general discussion. As Rorty noted, although philosophers in Europe study Quine and Davidson, "they tend to shrug off the suggestion that these contemporary philosophers share their basic outlook with American philosophers who wrote prior to the so-called linguistic turn" (Rorty, 1990: 1). It becomes more and more apparent that there has been a continuous development of thought from Peirce to Quine, Sellars, Putnam and so on, and that this tradition of thought as Bernstein suggested "not only challenges the characteristic Cartesian appeal to foundations, but adumbrates an alternative understanding of scientific knowledge without such foundations" (Bernstein, 1983: 71-72). 5

3. Charles S. Peirce's relevance The figure of Charles S. Peirce has an ever-increasing relevance in very different areas of knowledge (Fisch, 1980): in astronomy, metrology, geodesy, mathematics, logic, philosophy, theory and history of science, semiotics, linguistics, econometrics, and psychology. In all these fields Peirce has been considered a pioneer, a forerunner or even a 'father' or 'founder' (of semiotics, of pragmatism). It is very common to find general evaluations like Russell's "beyond doubt... he was one of the most original minds of the later nineteenth century, and certainly the greatest American thinker ever" (Russell, 1959: 276) or Umberto Eco's "Peirce was... the greatest American philosopher of the turn of the century and beyond doubt one the greatest thinkers of his time" (Eco, 1989: x-xi). Even among academic philosophers it has become a commonplace to say that Peirce is the most original philosophical mind that the United States has yet produced (Nagel, 1982: 303) and his seminal role in a wide range of philosophical problems has been alluded to by many philosophers: Popper described Peirce as "one of the greatest philosophers of all times" (Popper, 1972: 212) and Putnam called him "a towering giant among American philosophers" (Putnam, 1990: 252). Factors which have increased the growing interest in Peirce's thought are his personal participation in the scientific community of his time, his valuable contribution to the logic of relatives, and his sound knowledge of the philosophy of Kant as well as of the Scholastic tradition, in particular Duns Scotus. For these reasons and owing to his deep original and creative mind it is possible to find in Peircean thought a way to broaden the analytic mind. At the very root of American analytic philosophy, Peirce can provide a deeper perspective and make possible a renewal of analytic philosophy where human concerns will have a central importance. But also, since Peirce's semiotic took its origins from Scholastic philosophy (Beuchot, 1991; Deely, 1995), it is possible to understand his framework as a renovation of that tradition which has had a central role in Western philosophy. The main difficulty in the study of Peirce is probably the aforementioned air of provincialism that still hovers around pragmatism. A second difficulty of no less importance is that the interpretation of Peirce's thought has for years provoked a wide disagreement amongst Peirce scholars, in part due to the fragmentary and chaotic presentation of his work in the Collected Papers, and in part due to his going against the grain. The fact is that Peirce is not a philosopher easy to classify: some considered him a systematic thinker, but with four successive systems (Murphey, 1961); others see him as a contradictory thinker (Goudge, 1950), or a speculative metaphysician of an idealist type (Esposito, 1980). But in more recent years a deeper understanding of the architectonic nature of his thought and of his whole evolution from his early writings in 1865 until his death in 1914 has been gaining general acceptance (Hausman, 1993: xiv-xv; Houser and Kloesel, 1992: xxix). In the last decade all Peirce's scholars have clearly acknowledged the basic coherence and undeniable systematization of Peirce's thought (Santaella-Braga, 1993: 401). 6

Following Hookway to some extent (1985: 1-3), I think that the most accurate understanding of Peirce is to see him as a traditional and systematic philosopher, but one dealing with the modern problems of science, truth and knowledge from a very valuable personal experience as a logician and an experimental researcher in the bosom of an international community of scientists and thinkers. 4. Peirce and analytic philosophy In recent years Alasdair MacIntyre has provided good arguments in defense of cooperative work in philosophy, ethics and the social sciences. The scientific exercise of reason requires learning and the flourishing of intellectual and ethical virtues, and this can only take place in the context of research communities. A century ago Peirce propounded this notion of a community of inquirers, so essential to scientific rationality (Peirce, 1931-58, 5.311). It is well known that this is one of the main themes in the "transcendental pragmatics" of Karl-Otto Apel, whose interpretation establishes that Peirce's thought is the milestone in the semiotic transformation of transcendental philosophy into analytic philosophy. Most of the hallmarks of analytic philosophy are already present in Peirce. Many of the issues and insights that have emerged in recent philosophy of science, language, and action were not only anticipated by Peirce, but also explored by him with depth and originality. In recent decades his originality has been recognized, as has his almost uncanny anticipation of those problems and issues now taken to be at the heart of philosophy (Bernstein, 1981: xxi). The best approach to Peirce seems to be to assume that he sought something similar to the analytic philosophy of language: his underlying motivation and basic ideas have much in common with it (Hookway, 1985: 141) and Peirce according to Wright (1993: 41) could even be counted with Frege, Russell and Wittgenstein, as one of the founding fathers of analytic philosophy. Thirty years ago, in his first published paper, Rorty claimed that Peirce's thought envisaged, and repudiated in advance, the stages in the development of empiricism which logical positivism represented, arriving at a group of insights and a philosophical mood much like those of Philosophical Investigations (Rorty, 1961: 197-198). But in fact British analytic philosophy was ignorant of Peirce, with the exception of F. P. Ramsey and the sketchy account of Peirce in The Meaning of Meaning (1923). The proximity between Wittgenstein and Peirce has been well studied (Boghossian and Drewniak, 1995; Nubiola, 1996), but the study of Peirce's thought can shed great light on the way to integrate better the variety of piecemeal issues within the framework of philosophy. As Hookway suggests, in Peirce's work there is not just the parallel development of themes found in the work of Frege, Russell or Wittgenstein, but also the framework for an integrated theory of culture (Hookway, 1985: 120). A Peircean approach to philosophy offers both deep involvement in currently highly specialized and technical philosophical discussion, and the resources to participate in the general conversation of mankind. It maintains in 7

stable equilibrium both kantian concepts of philosophy, and is thus probably the best way in which analytic philosophy can be fully renovated and be opened to show in Putnam's expression a more human face. One hundred years ago, in February and March of 1898, Charles S. Peirce gave a course of eight lectures at 168 Brattle Street, Cambridge, on Reasoning and the Logic of Things. In the introduction to the first publication of that course only six years ago, K. L. Ketner and H. Putnam wrote that "this set of lectures offers to both expert and layperson the most convenient and complete means for gaining access to those ideas and insights in Peirce's philosophy which are specially relevant to a number of contemporary issues" (Peirce, 1992: 3). I want to finish my defense of the study of Peirce as a royal road to renovating analytic philosophy with a short quotation from the first of those lectures: "In philosophy... the investigator who does not stand aloof from all intent to make practical applications, will not only obstruct the advance of pure science, but what is infinitely worse, he will endangers his own moral integrity and that of his readers" (Peirce, 1992: 107). And as you know, and the history of philosophy provides a lot of evidence to this effect, the "lack of intellectual integrity is apt, in the long run and on the whole, to impede inquiry" (Haack, 1996: 59). Notes (1) I thank Guy Debrock and Moris Polanco for their suggestions, and to Ruth Breeze for her help with the English version. Bibliographic References R. J. Bernstein, "Introduction", in K. Apel, Charles S. Peirce. From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism, University of Massachusetts Press, Amherst, MA, 1981, xix-xxvi. R. J. Bernstein, Beyond Objectivism and Relativism: Science, Hermeneutics, and Praxis, Blackwell, Oxford, 1983. R. J. Bernstein, "The Resurgence of Pragmatism", Social Research 59, (1992), 813-840. M. Beuchot, "La filosofía escolástica en los orígenes de la semiótica de Peirce", Analogía 2 (1991), 155-166. P. G. Boghossian y E. Drewniak, "Wittgenstein and Peirce on Meaning", Diálogos 30 (1995), 173-188. 8

J. Conant, " Introduction" in H. Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1990, xv-lxxiv. G. Debrock, "Peirce, a Philosopher for the 21st Century. Introduction", Transactions of the Ch. S. Peirce Society 28 (1992), 1-18. J. Deely, "Common Sources for the Semiotic of Charles Peirce and John Poinsot", Review of Metaphysics 48 (1995), 539-566. U. Eco, "Introduction", in C. K. Ogden and I. A. Richards, The Meaning of Meaning, 4th ed., Harcourt, San Diego, CA, 1989, v-xi. J. Esposito, Evolutionary Metaphysics. Ohio University Press, Athens, OH, 1980. J. Harlan, "Interview with Hilary Putnam", The Harvard Review of Philosophy, Spring (1992), 20-24. M. Fisch, "The Range of Peirce's Relevance", The Monist 63 (1980), 269-276; 64,123-141. T. Goudge, The Thought of C. S. Peirce. University of Toronto Press, Toronto, 1950. S. Haack: "Concern for Truth: What it Means, Why it Matters", in P. R. Gross et al, eds., The Flight from Science and Reason, Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 775 (1996), 57-63. C. Hausman, Charles S. Peirce s Evolutionary Philosophy, Cambridge University Press, New York, 1993 C. Hookway, Peirce, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1985. N. Houser and C. Kloesel, eds., The Essential Peirce. Selected Philosophical Writings, Indiana University Press, Bloomington, IN, 1992. M. G. Murphey, The Development of Peirce's Philosophy, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1961. E. Nagel, "Peirce's Place in Philosophy", Historia Mathematica 9 (1982) 302-310. J. Nubiola, "Scholarship on the Relations between Ludwig Wittgenstein and Charles S. Peirce", in I. Angelelli y M. Cerezo, eds., Studies on the History of Logic. Proceedings of the III Symposium on the History of Logic, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin, 1996, 281-294 C. K. Ogden and I. A. Richards, The Meaning of Meaning, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1923. 9

C. S. Peirce, Collected Papers, vols. 1-8, C. Hartshorne, P. Weiss and A. W. Burks, eds., Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1931-58. C. S. Peirce, Reasoning and the Logic of Things. The Cambridge Conferences Lectures of 1898, K. L. Ketner, ed., Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1992. W. Percy, "The Divided Creature", The Wilson Quarterly 13 (1989), 77-87. K. R. Popper, Objective Knowledge: An Evolutionary Approach, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1972. H. Putnam, Realism and Reason, Philosophical Papers III, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,1983. H. Putnam, Realism with a Human Face, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA, 1990. H. Putnam, "A Half Century of Philosophy, Viewed From Within", Daedalus 126 (1997), 175-208. R. Rorty, "Pragmatism, Categories, and Language", Philosophical Review 70 (1961), 197-223. R. Rorty, Consequences of Pragmatism (Essays: 1972-1980), University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1982. R. Rorty, "Pragmatism as Anti-Representationalism", in J. P. Murphy, Pragmatism from Peirce to Davidson, Westview, Boulder, CO, 1990, 1-6. B. Russell, Wisdom of the West, Doubleday, Garden City, NY, 1959. L. Santaella-Braga, "Difficulties and Strategies in Applying Peirce s Semiotics", Semiotica 97 (1993), 401-410. W. Spohn, "Editorial Note", Erkenntnis 33 (1990) 1-4. L. Wittgenstein, Culture and Value, G. H. von Wright, ed., Blackwell, Oxford, 1980. G. H. von Wright, The Tree of Knowledge and Other Essays, Brill, Leiden, 1993. 10