Six Questions on the Construction of Ontologies in Biomedicine

Similar documents
A Realism-Based Approach to the Evolution of Biomedical Ontologies

This is the published version of a paper published in Jinkou Chinou Gakkai rombunshi (Online).

-A means of constructing ontologies for knowledge representation -In domain of Chinese Medicine and Orthodox Medicine

Real Time Summarization and Visualization of Ontology Change in Protégé

An Introduction to Description Logic I

Introduction: What is Ontology for? Katherine Munn

Triune Continuum Paradigm and Problems of UML Semantics

Towards a Reference Terminology for Ontology Research and Development in the Biomedical Domain

Ontology Representation : design patterns and ontologies that make sense Hoekstra, R.J.

The Ontological Character of Classes in the Dewey Decimal Classification. Rebecca Green Michael Panzer OCLC Online Computer Library Center, Inc.

Multi-Agent and Semantic Web Systems: Ontologies

WSPI 2006: Contributions to the Third International Workshop on Philosophy and Informatics

Sidestepping the holes of holism

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Conceptions and Context as a Fundament for the Representation of Knowledge Artifacts

Images for life. Nexxis for video integration in the operating room

Discussing some basic critique on Journal Impact Factors: revision of earlier comments

Foundations in Data Semantics. Chapter 4

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Design Principles of the ACGT Master Ontology: Examples and Discussion

6JSC/Chair/8/DNB response 4 October 2013 Page 1 of 6

Applied Ontology. Katherine Munn Barry Smith (Eds.) An Introduction. ontos. verlag. Katherine Munn, Barry Smith (Eds.

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Guidelines for Manuscript Preparation for Advanced Biomedical Engineering

PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. Bowers (chair), George W. Ledger ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. Michalski (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A.

Lecture 10 Popper s Propensity Theory; Hájek s Metatheory

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

ITU-T Y.4552/Y.2078 (02/2016) Application support models of the Internet of things

Protégé and the Kasimir decision-support system

The Ontological Level

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Rubato: Towards the Gamification of Music Pedagogy for Learning Outside of the Classroom

Taxonomy Displays Bridging UX & Taxonomy Design. Content Strategy Seattle Meetup April 28, 2015 Heather Hedden

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

with a librarian at encyclopedia on your subject such as Mosby s Paramedic

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska

Meaning Machines CS 672 Deictic Representations (3) Matthew Stone THE VILLAGE

Thomas Kuhn s Concept of Incommensurability and the Stegmüller/Sneed Program as a Formal Approach to that Concept

Using Rules to support Case-Based Reasoning for harmonizing melodies

Designing a Deductive Foundation System

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Composition, Counterfactuals, Causation

How comprehensive is the PubMed Central Open Access full-text database?

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Scientific Philosophy

Modelling Intellectual Processes: The FRBR - CRM Harmonization. Authors: Martin Doerr and Patrick LeBoeuf

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Deep Neural Networks Scanning for patterns (aka convolutional networks) Bhiksha Raj

AN INSIGHT INTO CONTEMPORARY THEORY OF METAPHOR

Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement

Articles with short titles describing the results are cited more often

Visualize and model your collection with Sustainable Collection Services

Add note: A note instructing the classifier to append digits found elsewhere in the DDC to a given base number. See also Base number.

A Meta-Theoretical Basis for Design Theory. Dr. Terence Love We-B Centre School of Management Information Systems Edith Cowan University

Code Number: 174-E 142 Health and Biosciences Libraries

PRNANO Editorial Policy Version

How to Manage Color in Telemedicine

SOCIAL AND CULTURAL ANTHROPOLOGY

By Maximus Monaheng Sefotho (PhD). 16 th June, 2015

Table of contents

ARTEFACTS IN FORMAL ONTOLOGY

Recently Published Book Spotlight: The Theory and Practice of Experimental Philosophy

A Compararive Analysis of Design

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

A Hybrid Theory of Metaphor

Week 25 Deconstruction

Book Review of Rosenhouse, The Monty Hall Problem. Leslie Burkholder 1

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Philosophical foundations for a zigzag theory structure

Original Research (not to exceed 3,000 words) Manuscripts describing original research should include the following sections:

Melody classification using patterns

A Bayesian Network for Real-Time Musical Accompaniment

Semi-automating the manual literature search for systematic reviews increases efficiency

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

A bibliometric analysis of publications by staff from Mid Yorkshire Hospitals NHS Trust,

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Improving MeSH Classification of Biomedical Articles using Citation Contexts

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

JOURNAL OF PHARMACEUTICAL RESEARCH AND EDUCATION AUTHOR GUIDELINES

Role of Color in Telemedicine Applications. Elizabeth A. Krupinski, PhD

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

NEUROSURGICAL ENCYCLOPEDIA- ENCYCLOPEDIA NEUROCHIRURGICA INSTRUCTIONS FOR AUTHORS Contact : gdechambenoit(at)neurochirurgie.

HEARING SOLUTIONS JAN 2013 MONTHLY MEETING TINNITUS PRESENTED BY DR KUPPERMAN

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Research Ideas for the Journal of Informatics and Data Mining: Opinion*

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

REQUIREMENTS FOR MASTER OF SCIENCE DEGREE IN APPLIED PSYCHOLOGY CLINICAL/COUNSELING PSYCHOLOGY

Echocardiography Research

Building blocks of a legal system. Comments on Summers Preadvies for the Vereniging voor Wijsbegeerte van het Recht

Exploiting Cross-Document Relations for Multi-document Evolving Summarization

RDA RESOURCE DESCRIPTION AND ACCESS

Date Inferred Table 1. LCCN Dates

Relational Logic in a Nutshell Planting the Seed for Panosophy The Theory of Everything

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Transcription:

Six Questions on the Construction of Ontologies in Biomedicine Anand Kumar a, Anita Burgun b, Werner Ceusters c, James J. Cimino d, James Davis e, Peter Elkin f, Ira Kalet g, Alan Rector h, Jim Rice i, Jeremy Rogers h, Stephan Schulz j, Kent Spackman l, Davide Zaccagini m, Pierre Zweigenbaum n, Barry Smith a,k a IFOMIS, University of Saarland, Saarbruecken, Germany b LIM, University of Rennes, France c ECOR, University of Saarland, Saarbruecken, Germany d Department of Biomedical Informatics, Columbia Univ. College of Physicians & Surgeons, NY, USA e Department of Computer Science and Engineering, University of South Carolina, Columbia, SC, USA f Mayo Clinic College of Medicine, Rochester, MN, USA g Radiation Oncology Department, University of Washington, WA, USA h Department of Computer Science at University of Manchester, UK i Muskegon Surgical Associates, MI, USA j Department of Medical Informatics, Freiburg University Hospital, Germany k Department of Philosophy, SUNY at Buffalo, NY, USA l Oregon Health & Science University at Portland, OR, USA m Department of Health S&T, Harvard-MIT, MA, USA n Assistance Publique - Paris Hospitals, STIM; INSERM, U729; INALCO, TIM, Paris, France Abstract Best practices in ontology building for biomedicine have been frequently discussed in recent years. However there is a range of seemingly disparate views represented by experts in the field. These views not only reflect the different uses to which ontologies are put, but also the experiences and disciplinary background of these experts themselves. We asked six questions related to biomedical ontologies to what we believe is a representative sample of ontologists in the biomedical field and came to a number conclusions which we believe can help provide an insight into the practical problems which ontology builders face today. Keywords: Biomedical ontology, Formal ontology, Knowledge representation Introduction This communication has been prepared on the basis of an email and face-to-face discussion among AMIA s Knowledge Representation Special Interest Group (KR- SIG) members regarding the best practices for ontology building in biomedicine. Much has been written on this topic and conceptions of what are best practices for ontologies seem to vary between different groups, depending on field of application, experience and expertise. [1,2,3] The objective of this paper is to provide some answers to practical problems which builders of ontologies, terminologies and vocabularies typically face in the biomedical domain. Our goal is to provide a clear answer to the question whether different fundamental approaches to ontology-building lead to substantial differences in ontologies or rather affect only the representation of a small number of especially problematic classes. In polling the views of experts in biomedical ontologies we found that their views are not so far apart as they sometimes seem to be. Among the authors, there is a consensus that the term ontology should be used in a broad sense which does not exclude any of those artifacts commonly referred to as biomedical vocabularies in the medical informatics community. We addressed 6 questions to the KR-SIG members: P1. Are ontologies about concepts or entities in reality? P2. & P3. Should we impose the rule of single inheritance in ontologies? Should we create ontologies embodying multiple partitions? P4. Should we support the negative classes such as: invertebrate, anosmia, or even unlocalized of the type explicity represented within some ontologies? P5. Is it always possible to construct ontologies in such a way as to involve only pairwise disjoint siblings? P6. Is it always possible to construct ontologies in such a way that they will represent jointly exhaustive siblings? P1. Concepts vs. Reality While many definitions for terms like concept, class, type, universal, etc. exist, we will consider the following definitions here, noting that entity (representing the top, all-inclusive category) is for the purposes of this discussion treated as a primitive notion.

Class: In the set-theoretic sense, a class is the set of objects instantiating a given universal (or: instantiating a given universal at a given time); i.e. it is the extension of a universal. In the literature on ontologies, however, class is sometimes used as a synonym for universal. Universal: a general entity an invariant in reality, which can be instantiated in a range of particular instances; thus the sort of entity to which a general term like cell or gastrulation (e.g. appearing in a scientific textbook) corresponds. Type and kind are synonyms of universal. Instance: a particular entity which instantiates a universal; thus it is the sort of entity to which a proper name or an indexical expression ( this bone here ) corresponds. Token is a synonym of instance. The responses to our questions can be divided in light of two cross-cutting oppositions: between formal and informal representations, and between congnitivist/conceptualist and realist representations. The arguments pertaining to the former concern the added value which is to be gained from providing rigorous logical structure (defended e.g. by GALEN 1 ) vs. the more intuitive structures targeted to human users preferred for example by the representatives of the Gene Ontology 2 (GO). and by the proponents of the kind of approach typified by the Read codes 3. The most prominent conceptualist ontologies include the Unified Medical Language System 4 (UMLS), the National Cancer Institute Thesaurus 5 (NCIT), and GALEN; realist ontologies are, for instance, the Foundational Model of Anatomy 6 (FMA), SNOMED CT 7 and (increasingly) GO. As GALEN makes clear, not all conceptualist approaches are informal; as GO makes clear, not all realist ontologies are formal. Conceptualists start with concept (or some equivalent) as their root class, and realists with entity. 8 Conceptualists see no difference between the representation of existing and non-existing entities, thus unicorn and uremia are treated in the same way. Realists, on the other hand, exclude classes like unicorns from their representations. For obvious reasons the opposition in question has led to arguments pertaining to the existence criteria for classes/concepts. 1 http://www.cs.man.ac.uk/mig/galen/index.html 2 www.geneontology.org 3 http://www.equip.ac.uk/readcodes/docs/index.html 4 http://www.nlm.nih.gov/research/umls/ 5 http://nciterms.nci.nih.gov/ncibrowser/startup.do 6 http:// sig.biostr.washington.edu/projects/fm/aboutfm.html 7 http://www.snomed.org/ 8 HL7 Reference Information Model (RIM) has act and entity as their root class. They do not consider act to a subclass of entity; rather they represent act and entity as mutually exclusive classes. Another apparent difference between the two methodologies is characterized by the example, thumb part_of hand In a realist ontology hand and thumb are classes of individual things. Only individuals can have parts. Therefore this relation must be understood e.g. as a disguised assertion about individuals, to the effect that every instance of the universal hand has some instance of the universal thumb as instance-level (mereological) part. Such all-some assertions are on the other hand problematic, since hands without thumbs do after all exist. A conceptualist, in contrast, would look not at individual hands, but rather at the mental representation associated with the natural language expression hand. In this mental representation a hand has a thumb, and the above relation is thereby justified. Alternative ways of solving the apparent invalidity within a realist ontology include: a. introduce more specific classes, e.g. hand without thumb, whose instances do not have a thumb as its part. hand without thumb is_a hand xy(inst(x, hand without thumb) & inst(y, thumb) not(part_of (y, x))) hand with thumb is_a hand x(inst(x, hand with thumb) y(inst(y, thumb) & (part_of (y, x))) where inst is the relation of instantiation between an instance and a universal, part_of is the parthood relation on the level of instances, and x signifies: for all values of x) b. Define the parthood and instantiation relationships in such a way as to take account of time [1]: A part_of B =def xt(inst (x, A, t) y(inst (y, B, t) & part_of(x, y, t) where x signifies: for some value of x. Thumbs are always parts of hands at the initial moment of their existence. c. Another way to deal with this issue is to provide cardinalities to the relations. For example, to represent hand could have either one or no thumb as part: hand has_part(0,1) thumb On the other hand, a thumb is always a part of a hand. thumb part_of(1,1) hand Beyond this point, formally correct ontologies, whether conceptual or real are similar. If Health Level 7 9 (HL7) s Reference Information Model (RIM), has document is_a act 9 http://www.hl7.org/ diagnosticimage is_a act

then, it does not matter if act here designates a concept or an entity: it is still incorrect. Rather, we should have on the left-hand side of these two assertions something like: act of taking documentation and image-based diagnostic act respectively. When the UMLS Semantic Network asserts: bacteria causes experimental model of disease then the problem here has to do not with the realism vs. conceptualism debate, in the sense that representatives from both sides would find the given assertion puzzling. When the National Cancer Institute Thesaurus asserts: tissue is_a other anatomical concept then the problem is not that tissue has been classified as a concept, but that the term other anatomical concept has no coherent meaning from the ontological point of view. Thus even if we find it correct to classify tissue as a concept, it should properly be classified is as a child of say anatomical entity concept, which would then in turn be classified as a child of concept. There are situations where we need to represent the relation of prevention, even though entities in the corresponding prevented classes then do not, by definition, exist. So, for example, a contraceptive drug prevents conception and SNOMED CT correspondingly has a class prevented pregnancy. We need to distinguish such classes from cases such as unicorn or goblin. Of course, the following relation is incorrect prevented pregnancy is_a pregnancy But it is true that, pregnancy prevention event part_of contraception event Builders of vocabularies and ontologies have often failed to take such differences between ontologies into consideration, and they have thus tended to create representations portions of which are realistic and others conceptualistic. This practice should be avoided. P2. Single vs. Multiple Inheritance & P3. Partitions in ontologies Binomial ontologies has been used as a justification for making all taxonomies into trees, however some argue that single inheritance is not a sufficient answer in many classifications. [4,5,6,7] Another opinion is that the structure of ontology should be chosen to accurately represent the real world and that the decision to use single or multiple inheritance is domain-specific. Yet another opinion favors the use of single inheritance only. An ontology is partitioned when only one criterion is used for its classification. There are many partitions which are present within multiple inheritance and within each such partition, there are further subclassifications. For example, within the pathology partition, there are subclassifications of the sort: by infection: (e.g., Granulomatous pancreatitis) by type of malignancy: (e.g., Adenocarcinoma pancreas) by metabolism: (e.g., Diabetes Mellitus) These disparate views can be reconciled on the basis of following practices: a. A clear distinction should be made between primitive and defined classes. b. At any level the primitive siblings should be disjoint and any primitive should have only one primitive parent. c. All multiple inheritance should be achieved using formal classification based on explicit definitions. The rationale behind this proposal is: i. Representational clarity. Ontology split into partitions brings clarity of structure. [2] ii. Modular interfaces. The cross-module definitions and restrictions (semantic links, conditions, and constraints) provide the interface between modules. iii. Explicitness. When some universal is a child of two parents, the reason stating why the dual subsumption is present provides explicitness and helps in the drawing of inferences and in avoiding coding errors. iv. Ease of maintenance. Modular ontologies are easier to maintain and error-check e.g. with Description Logicbased tools v. User-friendliness. The users of ontologies find it easier to navigate a modular ontology as they can choose which tree they want to traverse. vi. Usage of user-defined classes. A terminology restricted only to those classes users want to see is often too complicated for them to find what they want to see, and then one is left with the problem of how to filter and otherwise process the content in order to deliver what the user needs. In that case, having more detail than any user actually needs can provide the key leverage needed to give specific users what they actually want and such detailed representations are easier in a modular ontology. [2] of Pancreas of Pancreas Inflammatory Pancreatitis Pancreatitis Fig. 1. Example of multiple inheritance Inflammatory The is_a relations represented by the arrows in figure 1 mean, for example:

every instance of chronic pancreatitis is thereby also an instance of: chronic disorder of pancreas, pancreatitis, and chronic inflammatory disorder Where such relations are asserted in an ontology, a computer can derive that chronic pancreatitis has three parents. But the computer needs also to derive the reasons why the corresponding is_a relations obtain. There are at least two ways to achieve this information. a. Via the relational assertions we can make concerning the class chronic pancreatitis, namely: has_pathology inflammation has_onset chronic has_location pancreas For each of the three corresponding parent classes one of these relations is not assertible. Thus, for chronic inflammatory disorder not has_location pancreas; for pancreatitis not has_onset chronic, and for chronic disorder of pancreas not has_pathology inflammation. Then, however, one can assert the non-is_a relations only, and one would not explicitly need to represent the multiple inheritance. This is what the OIL plug-in in Protégé allows. 10 b. The non-is_a relations are represented as in case a. However, the is_a relations are further specified in terms of the reason for subsumption. Thus we could assert of chronic pancreatitis that it: is_pathology_specification_of chronic disorder of pancreas is_onset_specification_of pancreatitis is_location_specification_of chronic inflammatory disorder In order to understand the reason for a given subsumption the computer then does not need to look into the various relations of the class. Thus, every multiple inheritance can be decomposed via the sort of normalization described in [2]. Such partitions are used in processors like GRAIL for GALEN or SMK to drive PEN&PAD. According to one s perspective they can be seen either as promoting multiple inheritance or as helping to eliminate it. But clear, these alternatives reflect no genuine underlying difference. P4. Use of negative classes Should ontologies support negative classes, for example, invertebrate, anosmia, unlocalized? All three are currently used in existing ontologies. Some apparently negative classes are perfectly acceptable to the realist, as for example those which figure in oppositions like: insulin-dependent vs. non-insulin dependent diabetes mellitus, or gram-positive vs. gram-negative bacteria, 10 http://www.ontoknowledge.org/oil/ because they are not genuinely negative classes, and the same view can be held of anosmia. Similarly, the distinction between VHL+ Kidney Carcinoma and VHL- Kidney Carcinoma is real (referring to the Von Hippel Lindau (VHL) mutation, an important parameter in renal cancer. [8] There are other situations where seemingly negative classes point in fact to entities acceptable to the realist. For example, blindness is defined as: lacking or deficient in sight; especially: having less than 1/10 of normal vision in the more efficient eye when refractive defects are fully corrected by lenses. This definition tells us that blindness signifies not something negative but rather the impairment of a function. P5. Pairwise disjunction A classification C 1,..., C n is pairwise disjoint if and only if no pair of distinct classes share a common instance. Pairwise disjointness can be achieved within ontologies, but only when the ontology is modularized/partitioned in such a way as to eliminate multiple inheritance along the lines suggested under P2-P3 above. In a multiple inheritance hierarchy this will not be possible, but it can be achieved within each of the partitions. For example, acute hepatitis, subacute hepatitis, chronic hepatitis and viral hepatitis are not pairwise disjoint. However, within a partition in which hepatitis is classified on the basis of time of onset, acute, subacute and chronic hepatitis will be pairwise disjoint. Most common classes of endurants (continuants) are unproblematically pairwise disjoint. No cell is an organ, No head is a foot, and oxygen is not hydrogen. When representing anatomy, mereological disjointness is also commonly encountered.. Another approach to this representation is to distinguish between primitive and defined classes and allow negative classes only within the defined classes built over the primitives. The problem is that then one would need to draw a distinction between which classes are primitive and which are defined; a boundary hard to agree upon. P6. Jointly exhaustive classes A classification C 1,, C n is jointly exhaustive if and only if every individual in the relevant domain instantiates some class in the classification. One should not try to achieve joint exhaustiveness except in cases where the subdivision of a class is done within a single partition. But one should not try to force

this artificially. If one partitions all the infectious pneumonias according to their etiologies, we would have to either create siblings for every possible etiology (including ones that have never been observed nor are likely to be) or have some other sibling, as in ICD- 9/ICD-10 11 to provide a place to add new concepts when they are observed. Sometimes, negative classes can be of use to solve the problem. For example, for a viral hepatitis caused by a virus with is neither A nor B nor C, instead of using other forms of viral hepatitis, one could use non-a, non-b, non-c viral hepatitis. Although these classes emphasize absent features (i.e., the features present in the complement class), we argue that they essentially correspond to valid, genuine classes for which no specific positive name or names have as yet been crafted. [8] As for negative classes, for both pairwise disjunction and jointly exhaustiveness, we need to make distinctions that these are present for primitive classes and defined classes might not always have these properties. Conclusion The main conclusions reached are: There is no difference when one uses conceptual or realist ontologies, as long as the concepts created directly correspond to the object in the reality. Creation of formal ontologies should be encouraged over informal ones. In building an ontology one should be consistent in using either exclusively realist principles or exclusively conceptualist principles. It is useful to begin with single inheritance trees while building ontologies on the basis of a single partition that is a single cause for subsumption within one tree. This helps in ontology creation and maintenance, and also in the drawing of inferences and in navigation and information retrieval. When is_a relations are specified in terms of the module in which it is present, only one relationship is needed to understand the reason behind a subsumption. On the other hand, we need to recompute the relations of the child and parent class when multiple inheritance is present, in order to understand those reasons. Such reasons for subsumption are useful for navigation across the tree and for drawing inferences. Ontologies should support classes which represent minimization or lack of certain functions or attributes. However negative classes such as unlocalized, disease not otherwise specified should be avoided. Jointly exhaustive and pairwise disjoint classes should be represented when the ontology where the subdivision of class is carried out within a single partition. In those situations where this is not achievable, ontologies should use the open world assumption that missing classes within the ontology will be filled up at a later date and thus avoid making artificial classes to cover those cases. References [1] Smith B, Ceusters W, Klagges B, Koehler J, Kumar A, Lomax J, Mungall C, Neuhaus F, Rector A, Rosse C. Relations in biomedical ontologies. Genome Biology:; 2005 (in press) [2] Rector A. Modularisation of domain ontologies implemented in Description Logics and related formalisms including OWL. Knowledge Capture 2003, (Sanibel Island, FL, 2003), ACM, 121-128. [3] Bodenreider O, Smith B, Kumar A, Burgun A: Investigating subsumption in DL-based terminologies: A case study in SNOMED CT. KR-MED 2004: 12-20 [4] Russell S. and Norvig P. Artificial Intelligence: A modern approach. Chs. 10.6 and 10.7. [5] Brachman R. and Levesque H. (Eds.) Knowledge representation and reasoning (2004), Ch. 9. [6] Caviedes JE, Cimino JJ. Towards the development of a conceptual distance metric for the UMLS. J Biomed Inform. 2004 Apr;37(2):77-85. [7] Smith B, Koehler J, Kumar A. On the application of formal principles to life science data: A case study in the Gene Ontology. DILS 2004;:79-94. [8] Bodenreider O, Smith B, Burgun A. The ontologyepistemology divide: A case study in medical terminology. Proc. FOIS, 4-6 November 2004. Acknowledgement We are thankful to the AMIA staff and KR-SIG chair for providing the infrastructure for this discussion. IFOMIS members are supported by the Wolfgang Paul Program of the Alexander von Humboldt Foundation, the European Union Network of Excellence entitled Semantic Interoperability and DataMining in Biomedicine (SemanticMining) and the Volkswagen Foundation project Forms of Life. Contact Information Anand Kumar, IFOMIS, University of Saarland, Postfach 151150, D-66041 Saarbruecken, Germany. Email: akumar@ifomis.uni-saarland.de 11 http://www.cdc.gov/nchs/icd9.htm