Jeff Mitscherling, The Image of a Second Sun: Plato on Poetry, Rhetoric, and the Technē of Mimēsis

Similar documents
In order to enrich our experience of great works of philosophy and literature we will include, whenever feasible, speakers, films and music.

Why Pleasure Gains Fifth Rank: Against the Anti-Hedonist Interpretation of the Philebus 1

1. Physically, because they are all dressed up to look their best, as beautiful as they can.

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Ionuţ BÂRLIBA University of Konstanz & Al.I. Cuza University of Iasi ART AND RHAPSODY IN PLATO S ION

Volume, pace, clarity and expression are appropriate. Tone of voice occasionally engages the audience

Aesthetics Mid-Term Exam Review Guide:

English. English 80 Basic Language Skills. English 82 Introduction to Reading Skills. Students will: English 84 Development of Reading and Writing

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Surface Integration: Psychology. Christopher D. Keiper. Fuller Theological Seminary

An Outline of Aesthetics

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

Introduction and Overview

Round Table. Department of French and Spanish. Memorial University of Newfoundland

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Objective vs. Subjective

Greek Intellectual History: Tradition, Challenge, and Response Spring HIST & RELS 4350

COURSE SLO REPORT - HUMANITIES DIVISION

COURSE SLO ASSESSMENT 4-YEAR TIMELINE REPORT (ECC)

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Philosophy of Art. Plato

BASIC ISSUES IN AESTHETIC

COMPREHENSIVE EXAMINATION SAMPLE QUESTIONS

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

GORDON, J. (2012) PLATO S EROTIC WORLD: FROM COSMIC ORIGINS TO HUMAN DEATH. CAMBRIDGE, CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS.

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

2015 Arizona Arts Standards. Theatre Standards K - High School

Panel. Department of French and Spanish. Memorial University of Newfoundland

A Happy Ending: Happiness in the Nicomachean Ethics and Consolation of Philosophy. Wesley Spears

I love stories. I have for my entire life. They were a constant presence in my life; whether

Plato and Aristotle: Mimesis, Catharsis, and the Functions of Art

ENGL S092 Improving Writing Skills ENGL S110 Introduction to College Writing ENGL S111 Methods of Written Communication

Rhetoric - The Basics

Course Outline TIME AND LOCATION MWF 11:30-12:20 ML 349

observation and conceptual interpretation

Knowledge is not important when looking for the truths of the forms

Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla

CHAPTER 2 THEORETICAL FRAMEWORK

The Collected Dialogues Plato

Intention and Interpretation

Myth and Philosophy in Plato s Phaedrus

Art, Vision, and the Necessity of a Post-Analytic Phenomenology

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

An intelligent word graven in the soul of the learner Antonio Cosentino

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Pierre Hadot on Philosophy as a Way of Life. Pierre Hadot ( ) was a French philosopher and historian of ancient philosophy,

Course Syllabus. Ancient Greek Philosophy (direct to Philosophy) (toll-free; ask for the UM-Flint Philosophy Department)

Republic Of Plato By Out Of Print READ ONLINE

Poetry and Philosophy

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Department of Humanities and Social Science TOPICS IN LITERATURE AND SOCIETY SPRING 2016 ITB 213E WEEK ONE NOTES

ENGLISH LANGUAGE ARTS

PHILOSOPHY PLATO ( BC) VVR CHAPTER: 1 PLATO ( BC) PHILOSOPHY by Dr. Ambuj Srivastava / (1)

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

Summary. Key words: identity, temporality, epiphany, subjectivity, sensorial, narrative discourse, sublime, compensatory world, mythos

AESTHETICS. Key Terms

#11772 PLATO S REPUBLIC

Correlated to: Massachusetts English Language Arts Curriculum Framework with May 2004 Supplement (Grades 5-8)

SWU Aesthetics for Life W5: Aesthetics and Philosophy. 1 Introduction

O ne of the most influential aspects of

Overcoming Attempts to Dichotomize the Republic

PROFESSORS: George Fredric Franko (chair, philosophy & classics), Christina Salowey

John R. Edlund THE FIVE KEY TERMS OF KENNETH BURKE S DRAMATISM: IMPORTANT CONCEPTS FROM A GRAMMAR OF MOTIVES*

Curriculum Map-- Kings School District (English 12AP)

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

SpringBoard Academic Vocabulary for Grades 10-11

UNIT PLAN. Subject Area: English IV Unit #: 4 Unit Name: Seventeenth Century Unit. Big Idea/Theme: The Seventeenth Century focuses on carpe diem.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

Advice from Professor Gregory Nagy for Students in CB22x The Ancient Greek Hero

Architecture as the Psyche of a Culture

web address: address: Description

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

CTI 310 / C C 301: Introduction to Ancient Greece Unique #33755, MWF 2:00 3:00 PM Waggener Hall, Room 308

8 Reportage Reportage is one of the oldest techniques used in drama. In the millenia of the history of drama, epochs can be found where the use of thi

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

Aristotle on the Human Good

REQUIRED RETAKE INSTRUCTIONS

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Riccardo Chiaradonna, Gabriele Galluzzo (eds.), Universals in Ancient Philosophy, Edizioni della Normale, 2013, pp. 546, 29.75, ISBN

0:24 Arthur Holmes (AH): Aristotle s ethics 2:18 AH: 2:43 AH: 4:14 AH: 5:34 AH: capacity 7:05 AH:

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

Haecceities: Essentialism, Identity, and Abstraction

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

Forms and Causality in the Phaedo. Michael Wiitala

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

AP English Language and Composition Summer Assignment: Analysis

EROS AND SOCRATIC POLITICAL PHILOSOPHY

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

2011 Tennessee Section VI Adoption - Literature

Antonio Donato 2009 ISSN: Foucault Studies, No 7, pp , September 2009 REVIEW

California Content Standards that can be enhanced with storytelling Kindergarten Grade One Grade Two Grade Three Grade Four

Public Forum Debate ( Crossfire )

English/Philosophy Department ENG/PHL 100 Level Course Descriptions and Learning Outcomes

SOCRATES AND ARISTOPHANES BY LEO STRAUSS

English 11 AP Language Summer Reading Assignment 2011

Transcription:

266 Symposium therefore, that she returns to her thesis that the Cinema books offer the clearest incarnation of Deleuze s political philosophy, a thesis which is bound to cinema s rethinking of time. She writes that the greatness of the filmmakers of time is that they were able to create other livable configurations of thought in images themselves. (79) This means that cinema itself is able to image an alternative to the action-image, an alternative to Hollywood s dream of a transformation of the world and the creation of a new nation. (79) By thinking a cinema of time, Marrati enacts a move from the belief in human agency to the possibilities of believing in the world, that is, of believing in an immanent, dynamic and changing world, rather than relying on a transcendent historical narrative. A Deleuzian politics, as expressed through the cinema books, then becomes a politics of immanence which believes in cinema s temporal ability to create new forms of life. Paradoxically, Gilles Deleuze: Cinema and Philosophy s greatest strength is also its greatest weakness. Throughout the text, Marrati makes clear use of many of the most difficult terms within Deleuze s lexicon. Generous explanations of new technical language are paired with sophisticated engagement with the concepts, ensuring that the book will have value to the introductory reader of Deleuze and cinema, while still appealing to an audience that is well-versed in Deleuzian/Bergsonian concepts. However, such attention to detail ends up reading as though Marrati spreads herself too thin, particularly in the last pages where rather than strengthening what is a very compelling argument, she gets somewhat lost in the definitions. The result, therefore, is that as the book closes, its thesis seems to slip through one s fingers, even though Marrati has added great depth to the temporality of Deleuzian cinema studies. Jeff Mitscherling, The Image of a Second Sun: Plato on Poetry, Rhetoric, and the Technē of Mimēsis. Amherst: Humanity Books, 2009; 468 pages. ISBN: 978-1591024316. Review by Aaron Landry, York University. This book engages one of the perennial topics of Platonic scholarship the presence (or absence) of poetry in the ideal city as constructed in the Republic. What is unique to Mitscherling s argument is the distinction between dramatic and non-dramatic forms of poetry, which is supposed to resolve the inconsistency between the early books and Book X. The book contains five chapters, ample endnotes and two appendices. The first appendix provides all of the refer-

Book Reviews / Comptes Rendus 267 ences direct quotations and allusions to the poets throughout the Platonic dialogues. The second provides all of the Homeric quotations in Republic. This is especially important given the role that Homer plays in Mitscherling s argument. In the first chapter, Mitscherling introduces the puzzle of Republic Book X, which is notorious not only for its apparent inconsistency with the position expressed in Books II and III but also for the extreme nature of its charge the banishment of the poets. The author rehearses six interpretations of Book X. They are: that the aim of Plato s critique is all art, illusionistic art, all poetry, only dramatic poetry, the Athenian educational system (pace Havelock) and finally the Sophists (pace Gadamer). The latter two are further specified to mean respectively: the way poetry functioned in Athenian education and the influence of the sophists on general culture. Finally, Mitscherling offers his own interpretation, which limns Plato to be exclusively focussed on the technē of mimēsis (imitation). This technique consists in persuading by appearing to be what one is not, or by merely seeming to speak the truth. (71) Accordingly, insofar as the poets and Sophists participate in mimēsis, they are synonymous and constitute the object of Plato s critique. Mitscherling proceeds to rehearse the pre-platonic conceptions to poetry Homer, Hesiod, Archilochus and others with the aim of identifying the degree to which poetry and mimēsis are historically linked. In Homer, for instance, we have a dual notion of poetry, one as the result of a technē, and one as divinely inspired. They function in tandem and there is no evidence to suggest that anyone thought the two conceptions were incompatible. Indeed, Mitscherling points out that this same bipartite account emerges in Hesiod and Archilochus as well, although with the latter the prestige of the Muses, often associated with inspiration, is beginning to wane. During the tumultuous period of Socrates and Democritus, a new distinction was established between technē and sophia (knowledge or wisdom). Whereas in Archaic Greece, poetry had been treated, in part, as a species of sophia, that is, as exemplary knowledge, it is now treated as just another ordinary technē. One could respond to this division in two ways. First, one could think that the poets did not possess exceptional wisdom. Or, one could distinguish the poet s greatness from his skill, and bequeath his prestige by some other means. Democritus notion of the poet as inspired follows this latter route. In the third chapter, Mitscherling turns to the Platonic dialogues and examines the conception of poetry in dialogues other than the Republic. Poetry is ubiquitous in the dialogues and does not easily embody a unified account. For instance, consider inspiration in the Ion,

268 Symposium which Socrates claims is the origin of Ion s rhapsodic ability. As we saw in Homer, the notion of inspiration has Archaic origins but it is transformed in Plato. Inspiration is contrasted with technē, specifically the charioteer, the doctor and the general. In other words, poetry is not technical knowledge. Reason is completely absent. Yet, when we turn to consider dialogues like the Meno and the Symposium, inspiration is identified as true opinion and occupies an intermediary position between knowledge and ignorance. That true opinion has practical value seems to contradict the hard distinction established in the Ion. Rather than explain these differences as developmental stages in Plato s philosophical life, Mitscherling introduces the distinction between lyric and dramatic poetry. Whereas the former is the referent in the Ion, the latter is discussed in the Meno and the Symposium. The Phaedrus is the final dialogue considered, and for good reason, since philosophy is now connected with poetry in that both are products of inspiration. Mitscherling concludes the chapter by noting the sophistic influence on education at the turn of the 4 th century BCE. This event privileged poetry s technical aspects and had the effect of uniting the genres of poetry epic, lyric, tragedy, comedy under one rubric. Thus, as Homer became perceived as a tragedian, his work was diminished because it was conceptualised as the result of inspiration. It could not compete with the sophistic logos, which enchanted with appearances of the truth rather than truth itself. Mitscherling sees Plato as responding directly to this cultural development. In Chapter 4, Mitscherling turns to the Republic s conception of poetry. He first discusses Books II and III. One of the most noteworthy features of the Republic is its silence on the notion of inspiration. This is especially conspicuous given the continuities between inspiration and the youth s vision of beauty, which seems akin to a mystical experience. Furthermore, Mitscherling points to the various mischaracterisations of poetic genres. The most prevalent is Homer s association with dramatic poetry, which will become a full-scale identification in Book X. As well, tragedy and comedy are treated as wholly imitative. Since epic and lyric are conjoined with tragedy and comedy, as we see by the treatment of Homer, Mitscherling concludes that the radical conclusion of Book X is already latent in these early Books. Nevertheless, these considerations lead Mitscherling to note that Plato cannot be seriously advocating the banishment of all poetry. Indeed, recall the six possible interpretations of the poets in the Republic. For Mitscherling, the final four interpretations coalesce under the rubric of the technē of mimēsis; this is Plato s actual target throughout the Republic. This technē produces appearances, mere images devoid of meaningful

Book Reviews / Comptes Rendus 269 content (250), and it is this privileging of appearance over reality that necessitates ethical relativism, which is another harbinger Plato seeks to quash. In the final chapter, Mitscherling sketches a Platonic aesthetics, which explicitly draws on the phenomenology of Ingarden and the hermeneutics of Gadamer. This cashes out as the division between human psychology and the mimetic nature of art. Again, further extrapolating the discontinuities in the Republic, Mitscherling argues that whereas Books II and III exhibit the frail psychology of people, Book X deals with the precise nature of mimēsis and why it is contemptible. The argument runs as follows: first, there is the familiar ontological criticism that mimēsis is distant from reality. Second, mimēsis has the potentially dire consequence of nurturing the nonrational parts of the human psyche. Consequently, censure is appropriate. Mitscherling then details aesthetic experience from a hermeneutical perspective. He draws principally on Gadamer and outlines three theses. First, the work of art is akin to a symbolic gesture. Second, it is a creation (Gebilde). Finally, it is self-sufficient. For Mitscherling, Plato s aesthetics embodies these claims. As should now be clear, this book deals with a wide scope of material. In my view, this breadth has the regrettable consequence of making several sections irrelevant to the main argument of the book. In particular, I have difficulty seeing the relevance of extrapolating a Platonic aesthetics when there is so much more to defend. For instance, contra White and Havelock, who maintain that Greek poetry was inextricably bound to performance, Mitscherling holds that that the two are distinct. He cites Aristotle s Poetics as evidence for this conclusion. The problem is a diachronic one. Mitscherling fails to appreciate that from Archaic Greece down to Aristotle, there was a slow transition from an oral culture to a literate one, or in other words, from a conception of the poet as singer (aoidos) to one of maker (poiētēs). Such a transition diminished oral features of poetry intonation, costume and dance but promoted textual features like meter and plot. Still, poetic performance remained integral not only to the Greek educational system, but also to how Plato conceives of the ideal city. It is the poets, after all, who will disseminate the appropriate content to the citizenry. The hymns to the gods and encomia of good people are both permitted and poetic in the ideal state. Such considerations, together with further continuities that exist between the Republic and the Laws on the function of poetry in the ideal state, may not end up being decisive against Mitscherling s account, but they do complicate it and deserve more treatment. So while the premise of the book is promising, the argument contains too many scholarly holes for

270 Symposium the reviewer to recommend. Finally, on the technical level, the table of contents does not match the page numbering. Christopher Watkin, Difficult Atheism: Post-Theological Thinking in Alain Badiou, Jean-Luc Nancy, and Quentin Meillassoux. New York: Edinburgh University Press, 2011; xiii + 281 pages. ISBN: 978-0748640577. Review by Jason Harman, York University. Upon surveying the salons of 19th century Europe, Søren Kierkegaard noted the eagerness with which hungry minds sought to go beyond the drab palette offered by religion. Abraham, however, he told his readers, did not seek to go beyond religion. In fact, for Abraham, faith was an endeavour that requires a lifetime. In reviewing Christopher Watkin s Difficult Atheism, I am reminded of these words, for, as Watkin shows, the task of overcoming religion is an arduous one that ultimately begs the question: what are we really going beyond? Watkin s text seeks to chart contemporary French thought s attempt to attain a thinking that is truly without God (1), through an analysis and critique of Alain Badiou, Jean-Luc Nancy, and Quentin Meillassoux. It should be noted upfront that for sheer breadth and depth Watkin s work is astounding. Watkin, I am led to suspect, feels perfectly at ease inhabiting the minds of Badiou, Nancy and Meillassoux. Further, where contemporary French philosophy often dallies in the obscure, Watkin s rendering with ample citations from a wide selection of primary texts both clarifies and sharpens. Throughout this text, Watkin ushers the reader into the intimate circle of philosophy s leading minds certainly no small feat. Indeed, I can offer nothing short of praise for the text s descriptive and explanatory qualities, though I do have reservations regarding the method and criteria used to judge the philosophies in question. For starters, Watkin does little to actually clarify for us what God, religion, theology, or faith is. Though he reminds us early on that there are many atheisms (12), at least one for each of the prominent French philosophers whom occupy the text, there appears to be only one theology for which, consensus indicates, we must proceed beyond. (239) Watkin, following Nietzsche, whose name and philosophy he invokes early on, at times uses the phrase Platonic-Christian to designate the metaphysical structure that post-theological thought must overcome. (11) Yet, at other times for example, in critiquing Jean-Luc Nancy for Christian hyperbole (240) his concern seems to