Intelligent design: going back to Darwin for a better computational model of creation

Similar documents
CHALLENGES AND FALLACIES IN COMPUTER APPLICATIONS OF THE EVOLUTIONARY ANALOGY IN DESIGN METHODOLOGY

EVOLVING DESIGN LAYOUT CASES TO SATISFY FENG SHUI CONSTRAINTS

Toward a New Comparative Musicology. Steven Brown, McMaster University

Varieties of emergence

Normative and Positive Economics

Open Problems in Evolutionary Music and Art

Sudhanshu Gautam *1, Sarita Soni 2. M-Tech Computer Science, BBAU Central University, Lucknow, Uttar Pradesh, India


Architecture is epistemologically

Darwinian populations and natural selection, by Peter Godfrey-Smith, New York, Oxford University Press, Pp. viii+207.

DJ Darwin a genetic approach to creating beats

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

STEM Science Notebook

Information Theory Applied to Perceptual Research Involving Art Stimuli

Music Composition with Interactive Evolutionary Computation

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Exploring Persian Rug Design Using a Computational Evolutionary Approach

Book review - Alain Pottage and Martha Mundy (eds) (2004) - Law, Anthropology and the Constitution of the Social: Making Persons and Things

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Algorithmic Music Composition

Is Architecture Beautiful? Nikos A. Salingaros University of Texas at San Antonio May 2016

Durham Research Online

Evolutionary Explanation and the Hard Problem of Consciousness. Steven Horst Wesleyan University

Necessity Chance Design

Keynote speech evolutionary biology Example of an existing collaboration and highlight of recent research results A Keynote

Research for Cultural DNA in Design

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

Thought Experiments in Biology

Penultimate Draft- Final version forthcoming in Philosophical Psychology

Research Methodology for the Internal Observation of Design Thinking through the Creative Self-formation Process

Natural Kinds and Concepts: A Pragmatist and Methodologically Naturalistic Account

Objectives: Performance Objective: By the end of this session, the participants will be able to discuss the weaknesses of various theories that suppor

CRITIQUE OF PARSONS AND MERTON

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Evolutionary jazz improvisation and harmony system: A new jazz improvisation and harmony system

The Moral Animal. By Robert Wright. Vintage Books, Reviewed by Geoff Gilpin

George Levine, Darwin the Writer, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, 272 pp.

Glen Carlson Electronic Media Art + Design, University of Denver

Title Psychology of Creativity. Liane Gabora. Affiliation University of British Columbia, Canada

Mating Intelligence, Moral Virtues, and Methodological Vices

Thought Experiments in Biology

Free Ebooks How The Mind Works

University of Huddersfield Repository

Evolving Musical Counterpoint

Evolutionary Computing. Evolutionary Art. Bu-Ali Sina University Computer Engineering Dep. Fall 2015

Eden: an evolutionary sonic ecosystem

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Course Description: Required Texts:

Exploring Choreographers Conceptions of Motion Capture for Full Body Interaction

Consumer Choice Bias Due to Number Symmetry: Evidence from Real Estate Prices. AUTHOR(S): John Dobson, Larry Gorman, and Melissa Diane Moore

SURVIVAL OF THE BEAUTIFUL

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

1 Introduction to evolutionary psychology

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

M.A.R.Biggs University of Hertfordshire, Hatfield,UK

SOCI 421: Social Anthropology

METADESIGN. Human beings versus machines, or machines as instruments of human designs? Humberto Maturana

University of Huddersfield Repository

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Mass Communication Theory

Systemic and meta-systemic laws

Creativity in Performance

Principles of Genetics, Spring 2016

Exploration of New Understanding of Culture. Yogi Chaitanya Prakash, Osaka University, Japan

The Nature of Philosophy and the Philosophy of Nature. Peter Godfrey-Smith (2014) Philosophy of Biology. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University press.

Kant on wheels. Available online: 24 Jun 2010

Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement

Brain.fm Theory & Process

Word count: title, abstract, body, notes, references = 4,342; figures 300 each = 600; total 4,942.

Conceptions and Context as a Fundament for the Representation of Knowledge Artifacts

The Mystery of Prime Numbers:

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Information in Biology. The Harvard community has made this article openly available. Please share how this access benefits you. Your story matters.

PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY

Science: A Greatest Integer Function A Punctuated, Cumulative Approach to the Inquisitive Nature of Science

The Public Thing: On the Idea of a Politics of Artefacts

MITOCW MIT7_01SCF11_track01_300k.mp4

Ridgeview Publishing Company

Comparing aesthetic measures for evolutionary art

Science as evolution of technologies of cognition

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

Between Concept and Form: Learning from Case Studies

The study of design problem in design thinking

DEMOGRAPHIC DIFFERENCES IN WORKPLACE GOSSIPING BEHAVIOUR IN ORGANIZATIONS - AN EMPIRICAL STUDY ON EMPLOYEES IN SMES

Assess the contribution of symbolic interactionism to the understanding of communications and social interactions

Doctor of Philosophy

Complexity, Neuroaesthetics, and Computational Aesthetic Evaluation

THE EVOLUTION OF RELIGION AND THE EVOLUTION OF CULTURE TAYLOR THIEL DAVIS. B.Sc., The University of Georgia, 2000 M.A., Tufts University, 2011

Etna Builder - Interactively Building Advanced Graphical Tree Representations of Music

Using Evolutionary Methods for Design Case Adaptation

A Critical Response to The Psychology of Creativity: A Critical Reading

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

Intelligent Skin - towards an architectural logics of the circumstantial"

PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. Bowers (chair), George W. Ledger ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. Michalski (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A.

The Generative Audiovisual Narrative System

Evolution essay titles. Evolution essay titles.zip

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Enabling editors through machine learning

Transcription:

Intelligent design: going back to Darwin for a better computational model of creation Sean Hanna Bartlett School of Graduate Studies, University College London, UK Models of creativity based on natural evolution have taken the genetic code of modern genetics, and ignored the goal-less nature of Darwin s original theory. This paper uses the comparison with evolutionary theory to suggest that exactly the opposite approach should be taken if we plan to more accurately model the processes of human design creativity. 1.0 Introduction Evolution in nature has been held as a paradigmatic model for creativity, and is exploited in design via evolutionary computation such as genetic algorithms [1] and genetic programming [2]. While these computational processes have been shown effective for optimisation, optimisation is not the same thing as creative design. The ultimate objectives of evolution in nature and design are similar, but the mechanism is different, and unfortunately evolutionary computation differs from natural evolution in exactly the opposite way to the way design does. This position paper suggests there are two popular errors in these evolutionary models of creative design: Models of creative thought that require an end goal are fundamentally mistaken. On this point they should be more like evolution. Models of creative thought that are based on the manipulation of a symbolic code are fundamentally mistaken. On this point they should be more like design. Design will be compare with evolution to illustrate this position. It will be suggested that creativity has more in common with Darwin s original proposition than with the subsequent additions of modern genetics. 1 Design Computing and Cognition DCC 10. J.S Gero (ed), pp. xx-yy. Springer 2010

2 S. Hanna 2.0 Nature has no telos, and neither does design Perhaps the most radical and contentious implication of Darwin s theory of evolution at the time it was proposed was that it did away with the notion of a telos, or end goal in nature. The mechanism of selection from random variation made this unnecessary at two scales: at the global level in the long term it required no divinely held model of perfection to which successive generations would approach, and within each generation there was no Lamarckian process of adaptation by the effort of individual organisms to their own goals. These teleological objectives were replaced by the single criterion of survival, which could be achieved by any means strength, agility, camouflage, poison or an unusually large and adaptable brain to suit and exploit any number of possible niches in an ecosystem. It is exactly this ability to provide what appear to be good solutions to problems that had never been posed as such that makes evolution such a powerful model for design. Design tasks the really creative ones are also rarely posed explicitly. They consist of what Rittel and Webber [3] call wicked problems, in that they are ill-defined and their so-called solutions have unforeseeable consequences. Rosenman [4] suggests the lack of prior knowledge about a problem is the indication of how much creativity is required. A priori goal setting is at odds with creative design. The real power of Darwinian evolution to cope with a lack of goal is that rather than setting instructions for an outcome beforehand, it can select the results after they have been produced, and thereby make evaluations holistically. Steadman [5] notes the difference between instructive and elective processes in design as equivalent to the theories of Lamarck and Darwin respectively. The complexity of an organism, or of a design in its social, cultural, stylistic and functional context, means that it cannot be reduced to its parts the way these act and interact together produce the emergent and unforeseeable consequences referred to above. The simple explanation in Darwin s theory is that such emergent complexity is possible simply because it works. By requiring only survival, evolution will both select for the whole package and allow the apparent definition of fitness to change. Most thorough accounts of the design process [6,7] emphasise the reflective processes (e.g. sketching and discussion) that redefines design objectives over time in this way. There is evidence to suggest that human designers are also able to evaluate a great deal more in a design than they are able to instruct [8].

Intelligent design 3 Our assumption of teleology in design may come from a common sense perception of the creative act as a personal, individual phenomenon, and from a design profession that does apparently have goals. Social models of creativity [9] suggest that this may not actually be so. Even professional designers draw the bulk of their output by working within existing types so ubiquitous as to be unquestioned and unnoticed, and the small remaining portion that is actually novel may still be inspired by what already exists. The position of this paper is that all novelty is actually derived from what already exists; the mechanism for this is described in the following section. 3.0 Nature has genotypes, but design does not The major non-darwinian contributions to our modern understanding of evolution, from Mendel s [10] description of the laws of inheritance to Watson and Crick s [11] discovery of the molecular structure of DNA, pertain to the mechanism by which nature s designs are produced. The notion of an underlying code has such an affinity to computation that it is no surprise that they have often been adapted as a mechanism for supposedly creative systems. This relationship may be partly historical, as the years immediately following the discovery of the biological code also focused on formal symbol systems [12] as the basis for intelligence and language [13]. Much of this work paralleled the central dogma of molecular biology, in which information can only be passed in one direction from genotype (the code, or DNA) to phenotype (the organism s traits), and never the reverse [14]. But this has little to do with how design really works, for the simple reason that nothing like this dogma holds for human creativity. Instead of the genotype, it is precisely the phenotype, or traits of designed artefacts, that as designers we are able to copy or modify in creating a new work. In some cases where a genotype is proposed as an analogy to our understanding of human artefacts, it is specifically inverted [15] such that information can flow back. To propose a plausible model of creative thought with some that resemblance to evolution, it is the notion of a genotype, or any fixed symbolic representation, that must be rejected. The importance of operating at the level of the phenotype is that while a genotype is a fixed, symbolic representation that can only be translated in one way, it is at the level of final traits that multiple interpretations may be made. The act of reinterpretation has often been identified as important to creative thought: Schön [16] calls this seeing-as ; Koestler [17] discusses the bissociation of matrices. I would go further to suggest that this act is

4 S. Hanna not only the very root of creative insight and the generation of novelty, but it is only through the ability to make multiple interpretations of a single phenotype (violating the dogma of molecular biology) that we have the ability to be creative in design. The argument is not based on new empirical evidence, but because existing alternative assumptions have less explanatory power. There is a general consensus that creativity requires the apparently paradoxical combination of novelty and utility [18], and this novelty is built in to computational models. Evolutionary computation such as genetic algorithms and genetic programming rely on a simple random number generator to produce mutations and control gene crossover. Some models are more refined with goal directed behaviour, such as Saunders and Gero s [19] creative agents, who are given a pre-programmed optimal balance between too much and too little novelty as suggested by Berlyne [20], but still the generation of that novelty is given by random generation. Although a random number generator can be said to fill in for real variation in the world, and agents might be modelled on a belief that we are imbued with an innate élan vital [21], these models still beg the question of the explanation of that novelty. The ability to make multiple interpretations of a single phenotype explains how novelty can occur. It can happen in at least two different ways roughly analogous to those known to occur in the genotype. Genetic mutation is essentially a copying error in DNA. When an attempt is made to faithfully copy phenotype traits of a designed artefact, there is inevitably some capacity for unintentional change, becoming more likely the less is known about the process by which the original was made (its genotype). Genetic crossover is the combination of two dissimilar sets of DNA via sex. This is the really big creative bang Koestler s bissocation of dissimilar matrices, or the eureka moment. Had Archimedes been constrained to think in terms of the genotypic properties of baths and votive crowns (e.g. the ideal water temperature; how to shape a gold-silver alloy) he would not have made a creative leap that depended on phenotypic traits, or resultant effects, such as water displacement and density. This ability of seeing-as, explains this emergence of novelty without the need for goal-seeking behaviour or resort to imposed randomness. We get something from nothing in that innovation emerges naturally as a consequence simply of observing. Many of the apparent contradictions or paradoxes of creativity concerning the trade-off between novelty and utility can be explained. Berlyne [20] suggests a curve based on Wundt [22] gives an optimal level of novelty, but there is little to suggest any intrinsic benefit of novelty. Udo Lindemann recently questioned such motives at a recent SIG Design Creativity workshop (DESIGN 2010, notes: Tom Howard), in that it is generally

Intelligent design 5 more important just to do things in the best way, rather than a new way. For Cropley [18] it is paradoxical that creativity requires deviating from social norms, but doing this in a way that the society can tolerate. These points are only contradictory if novelty is measured by a standard metric, as would be the case with genotypes. Multiple interpretations of a phenotype imply that there is no single standard, so something may be highly unusual in one axis of measurement while at the same time instantly recognisable in another. My novel is not your novel. Although little has been done in terms of reinterpreting the phenotype, evolution improves simply by changing features of genetic representation such as the numerical base [23]. Phenotype operations should be even faster at producing innovation, a point on speed that is often made in comparing cultural with biological evolution. If this is so, then it would form the latest of a set of radical changes in how evolution functions: the beginning of mutation in the genome 3.8 billion years ago; sexual crossover 1.2 billion years ago; and the cultural copying at the level of the phenotype within the last several hundred thousand years. Each of these steps has been accompanied by a dramatically increased rate of change. 4.0 Where research should focus The relationship between design and evolution has more to do with the capacity to naturally select good solutions holistically to emergent criteria than with the underlying genetic code that is so often assumed. Design thus has more in common with Darwin s model, prior to the discovery of a coded genotype. In the sense that creativity is often thought to be a somewhat vague and slippery concept, the rejection proposed here both of set goals and clear codes is perhaps not surprising, but does raise questions of how research might continue. While optimisation can focus on better means of search, what can be done without the telos or the code? We are not left without a mechanism. For novelty, we need to know how interpretation of artefacts occurs. AI is now beginning to explore this, through e.g. machine learning and vision, embodied robotics and the commonplace manipulation of unprecedented amounts of data by Google. For utility, without a telos this seems more difficult, but in design we also rely on existing artifacts to guide our choices, basing our assumptions on things tested in the real world, where unspecifiable goals constantly arise by emergent process. Both elective, goalless processes and novelty generation are based on observing or interpretation, and these mechanisms provide much to investigate.

6 S. Hanna References 1. Holland J H (1975) Adaptation in Natural and Artificial Systems An Introductory Analysis with Applications to Biology, Control, and Artificial Intelligence. University of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor. 2. Koza JR (1992) Genetic programming : on the programming of computers by means of natural selection, MIT Press. 3. Rittel HWJ and Webber MM (1984) Planning problems are wicked problems. In Cross N (ed.) Developments in Design Methodology, John Wiley and Sons. 4. Rosenman, M: 1997, The Generation of Form Using an Evolutionary Approach, in Dasgupta, D and Michalewicz, Z (eds), Evolutionary Algorithms in Engineering Applications, Springer-Verlag, pp. 69-86. 5. Steadman P (2008) The Evolution of Designs. Routledge. 6. Schön DA (1983) The Reflective Practitioner. Basic Books, New York. 7. Snodgrass AB and Coyne RD (1997) Is designing hermeneutical? Architectural Theory Review, 2(1), pp.65 97. 8. Piaseki M and Hanna S (2010) A Redefinition of the Paradox of Choice. Proceedings of Design Computing and Cognition '10, Springer. 9. Czikszentmihalyi M (1988), Society, culture, and person: a systems view of creativity, in Sternberg, RJ (ed), The nature of creativity: Contemporary psychological perspectives, Cambridge University Press, pp. 325-339. 10. Mendel G (1965) Experiments in plant hybridisation, English translation eds. Fisher RA and Bennett JH, Oliver & Boyd. 11. Watson JD and Crick FHC (1953) A Structure for Deoxyribose Nucleic Acid Nature 171, 737-738. 12. Newell, A. and Simon, H. (1976). Computer Science as Empirical Enquiry: Symbols and Search. Communications of the Association for Computing Machinery 19: 105-32. 13. Chomsky N, (1957). Syntactic Structures. Mouton, The Hague. 14. Crick, F. (1970): Central Dogma of Molecular Biology. Nature 227, 561-563. 15. Hillier B and Hanson J: 1984, The Social Logic of Space. Cambridge University Press. 16. Schön DA (1963) Displacement of Concepts. Tavistock, London. 17. Koestler A (1964) The act of creation. Hutchinson. 18. Cropley, AJ: 1999, Definitions of creativity, in MA Runco and SR Pritzer (eds.), Encyclopedia of Creativity, Academic Press, San Diego, pp. 511 524. 19. Saunders R and Gero JS (2001) Artificial creativity: A synthetic approach to the study of creative behaviour, in JS Gero and ML Maher (eds), Computational and Cognitive Models of Creative Design V, pp. 113-139. 20. Berlyne DE (1971) Aesthetics & psychobiology. Appleton-Century-Crofts. 21. Bergson H (1911) CreativeEvolution, Mitchell A (trans.), Macmillan, London. 22. Wundt WM, (1874) Grundzüge de physiologischen Psychologie. Engelman, Leipzig. 23. Dekker L and Kingdon J (1995) The shape of space, 1st International Conference on Genetic Algorithms in Engineering Systems, pp 543 548.