Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3

Similar documents
Perceptions and Hallucinations

The Invalidity of the Argument from Illusion

Early Modern Philosophy Locke and Berkeley. Lecture 6: Berkeley s Idealism II

Types of perceptual content

Faculty of Philosophy, University of Cambridge Part IB: Metaphysics & Epistemology

The Problem of Perception

Against Metaphysical Disjunctivism

Being About the World - An Analysis of the. Intentionality of Perceptual Experience

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

IS THE SENSE-DATA THEORY A REPRESENTATIONALIST THEORY? Fiona Macpherson

Affect, perceptual experience, and disclosure

Mental Representations: the New Sense-Data? Chuck Stieg Department of Philosophy University of Minnesota. Abstract

Selection from Jonathan Dancy, Introduction to Contemporary Epistemology, Blackwell, 1985, pp THEORIES OF PERCEPTION

Review of David Woodruff Smith and Amie L. Thomasson, eds., Phenomenology and the Philosophy of Mind, 2005, Oxford University Press.

Image and Imagination

John J. Drummond Fordham University. Intentionality is most broadly characterized as mind s directedness upon something.

A New Approach to the Paradox of Fiction Pete Faulconbridge

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

WHY PHENOMENAL CONTENT IS NOT INTENTIONAL

The Direct/Indirect Distinction in Contemporary Philosophy of Perception

6 Bodily Sensations as an Obstacle for Representationism

A Succession of Feelings, in and of Itself, is Not a Feeling of Succession

The central and defining characteristic of thoughts is that they have objects. The object

This essay provides an overview of the debate concerning the admissible. contents of experience, together with an introduction to the papers in this

Naïve Realism, Hallucination, and Causation: A New Response to the Screening Off Problem

UNDERSTANDING HOW EXPERIENCE SEEMS

Philosophy of Mind and Metaphysics Lecture III: Qualitative Change and the Doctrine of Temporal Parts

Openness to the World: an Enquiry into the Intentionality of Perception

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

24.500/Phil253 topics in philosophy of mind/perceptual experience

1/10. Berkeley on Abstraction

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Transparency in Perceptual Experience. Austin Carter Andrews. A dissertation submitted in partial satisfaction of the. requirements for the degree of

Volume 59 Number 236 July 2009

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

What s Really Disgusting

Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes* Tyler Burge

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Epistemological Problems of Perception

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

The red apple I am eating is sweet and juicy. LOCKE S EMPIRICAL THEORY OF COGNITION: THE THEORY OF IDEAS. Locke s way of ideas

Sensuous Experience, Phenomenal Presence, and Perceptual Availability. Click for updates

observation and conceptual interpretation

In The Mind and the World Order, C.I. Lewis made a famous distinction between the

CHAPTER 15. Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes. Tyler Burge

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

The Unity of the Manifest and Scientific Image by Self-Representation *

Spectrum inversion as a challenge to intentionalism

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Varieties of Nominalism Predicate Nominalism The Nature of Classes Class Membership Determines Type Testing For Adequacy

Berkeley s idealism. Jeff Speaks phil October 30, 2018

NATURALIZING QUALIA. ALESSANDRA BUCCELLA University of Pittsburgh abstract

Naturalizing Phenomenology? Dretske on Qualia*

Spring 2014 Department of Philosophy Graduate Course Descriptions

We know of the efforts of such philosophers as Frege and Husserl to undo the

KANT ON THE OBJECT-DEPENDENCE OF INTUITION AND HALLUCINATION

Realism and Representation: The Case of Rembrandt s

RESEMBLANCE IN DAVID HUME S TREATISE Ezio Di Nucci

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

MODES OF PRESENTATION AND WAYS OF APPEARING: A CRITICAL REVISION OF EVANS S ACCOUNT*

Perceptual Presence. Jason Leddington. [Pacific Philosophical Quarterly 90 (2009) ]

Do Universals Exist? Realism

Aristotle s Metaphysics

On Crane s Psychologistic Account of Intentionality

Subject and Object in the Contents of Visual Experience

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Dawn M. Phillips The real challenge for an aesthetics of photography

INTRODUCTION. Clotilde Calabi. Elisabetta Sacchi. Università Vita-Salute San Raffaele

For Peer Review. Philosophy Compass. Philosophy Compass. Sensory Experience and Intentionalism

M. Chirimuuta s Adverbialism About Color. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. I. Color Adverbialism

Felt Evaluations: A Theory of Pleasure and Pain. Bennett Helm (2002) Slides by Jeremiah Tillman

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

On Recanati s Mental Files

Truth and Tropes. by Keith Lehrer and Joseph Tolliver

Perceptual Demonstrative Thought: A Property-Dependent Theory

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

PERCEPTION AND ITS OBJECTS

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

REVELATION AND THE NATURE OF COLOUR

COLOUR FOR REPRESENTATIONALISTS

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

Russellian perceptual theory and constancy, page 1

McDowell, Demonstrative Concepts, and Nonconceptual Representational Content Wayne Wright

of perception, elaborated in his De Anima as an isomorphic motion of the soul. It will begin by

Exploring touch: A review of Matthew Fulkerson s The First Sense

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

The Phenomenological Negation of the Causal Closure of the Physical

The Philosophy of Language. Grice s Theory of Meaning

There Are No Easy Problems of Consciousness 1

Internal Realism. Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

The ambiguity of definite descriptions

Book Reviews Department of Philosophy and Religion Appalachian State University 401 Academy Street Boone, NC USA

Determinables and Brute Similarities

The Introduction of Universals

No Proposition can be said to be in the Mind, which it never yet knew, which it was never yet conscious of. (Essay I.II.5)

Transcription:

Perception and Mind-Dependence Lecture 3 1 This Week Goals: (a) To consider, and reject, the Sense-Datum Theorist s attempt to save Common-Sense Realism by making themselves Indirect Realists. (b) To undermine the Phenomenal Principle, and thus the Argument from Illusion. 2 Direct and Indirect Perception We can rejig the Argument so as its conclusion isn t so radical: The Base Case Stage (i) When one is subject to an illusory experience, there sensibly appears to one to be something which has a sensible quality, F, which the ordinary object supposedly being perceived does not actually have. (ii) (Revised Phenomenal Principle) When, in perceptual experience, it sensibly appears to one that something has a sensible quality, F, then there is something of which one is directly aware which does have this quality. Therefore, (iii) (Revised Interim Negative Claim) In cases of illusion, one is not directly aware of the ordinary object one is supposedly perceiving. The Spreading Step (iv) The same account of experience must apply to both illusory and veridical experiences. Therefore, (v) (Revised Negative Claim) One is never directly aware of ordinary objects in perceptual experience. We can work with this understanding of Indirect Awareness: Indirect Awareness S is indirectly aware of x iff S is aware of x in virtue of being aware of a distinct thing y. (Here y serves as a perceptual proxy or mediator.) 1

Indirect Realism There are mind-independent material objects (Realism). And we are sometimes perceptually aware of them. But our awareness of them is only ever indirect, that is, we are only ever aware of them in virtue of being aware of distinct sense-data (Indirectness). A claim about the structure of our perceptual awareness of ordinary objects: that it is mediated. With that in mind consider the following from Russell (1912) what the senses immediately tell us is not the truth about the object as it is apart from us, but only the truth about certain sense-data which, so far as we can see, depend upon the relations between us and the object. Thus what we directly see and feel is merely appearance which we believe to be a sign of some reality beyond (p. 6). Russell moves from a point in epistemology to a point in the philosophy of perception: we are focused just on the point about perception. Indirect Realism is not an innocent position, it faces difficult theoretical questions: Why should direct awareness of a sense-datum distinct from an ordinary object give one indirect awareness of the ordinary object? Russell refers to the sense-data as signs of the ordinary objects behind them. We might say: we are aware of entities which represent ordinary objects, and that is why awareness of such entities gives us awareness of ordinary objects (Representative Realism). Only sketchy beginnings of an account. Why/how do the sense-data represent what they do? In order to make Indirect Realism work the Sense-Datum Theorist needs to give us much more about what sense-data are. And this requires the Indirect Realist to go beyond the resources of the Argument from Illusion. Difficult questions aside, Indirect Realism promises us this result: Saving Common-Sense Realism Common-Sense Realism says that we are sometimes perceptually aware of ordinary objects, the revised Argument from Illusion and Indirect Realism is perfectly consistent with this. It just insists that we are only ever indirectly aware of such objects. But this doesn t work. For Common-Sense Realism should take a direct realist form. The idea that perceptual awareness of objects is mediated needs philosophical reflection, argument, and theory. A more untutored and common-sense perspective doesn t make use of the idea of such perceptual proxies for typical cases. Such cases strike us as cases simply as cases of being given ordinary objects. Common-sense descriptions of the character of our experiences are given with reference to the aspects of the world out there we take ourselves to perceive, without the need for appeal to mediating proxies; sense-data, ideas, images, impressions, and what have you. Perceptual proxies have no place in a common-sense perspective on mundane cases of experience. In many cases, when we reflect upon our own experiences, they strike us transparent to the ordinary objects in the world. If asked to direct our attention to the sensuous character of such experiences, we see right through to those ordinary objects and qualities out there themselves. 2

Suppose a non-philosophical observer gazing idly through a window. To him we address the request, Give us a description of your current visual experience, or How is it with you, visually, at the moment? Uncautioned as to exactly what we want, he might reply in some such terms as these: I see the red light of the sun setting filtering through the black and thickly clustered branches of the elms; I see the dappled deer grazing in groups on the vivid green grass and so on (Strawson (1979, p. 43)). Thus Common-Sense Realism should be understood as minimally direct realist: we are sometimes directly aware of ordinary objects. So the Indirect Realist move doesn t save Common-Sense Realism. 3 Representationalism An alterntative: the Representational Theory of Experience or Representationalism (sometimes also the intentional theory of experience or intentionalism, see e.g., Crane (2001, 2009, 2013) and Searle (1983))). Let s consider the the view with reference to two questions we want any theory of perceptual experience to answer: Question 1: What is the nature of perceptual experience? Question 2: Why do things appear the way they do in experience? 3.1 What is the Nature of Perceptual Experience? Bob sees the wall as white in colour: (1) Bob s experience has a subject-matter: it is about or concerns something. His experience concerns the wall. (2) Bob s experience is a state of mind involving a certain mode: it is a perceptual experience as opposed to a hope, or a desire (or whatever), and it is a visual experience, not an auditory or olfactory experience (or whatever). (3) Bob s experience has a certain representational content. That is, his experience represents the subject-matter (the wall) in a certain way. Bob s experience represents the wall as white. (Different experiences may have different contents, despite sameness of subject-matter. E.g., you may visually represent the wall as yellow.) This makes Bob s experience akin to other representational states of mind: consider belief : Bob s belief that Nigel Farage is a bigot: (1) Bob s belief has a subject-matter: it is about or concerns Nigel Farage. (2) Bob s belief is a state of mind in a certain mode: it is a belief as opposed to a hope, or a perception, or whatever. (3) Bob s belief has a representational content: it represents Farage as being a bigot. (Different beliefs may have different contents, despite sameness of subject-matter e.g., you may believe that Farage is a moron your belief thus represents Farage in a different way to Bob s). 3

(Other terminology: subject-matter gets called intentional object, and this aspect of states of mind reflects their intentionality the idea of the mind s directedness on its objects. Mode gets called attitude. And representational content gets called intentional content.) Open questions: What sort of representational content does experience have? Is it the same sort as what beliefs and/or linguistic representations have? Is it more like what paintings have? Is it something else? Does it require the subject of the experience to possess the concepts which characterize it? (That is, is it conceptual content?) What sort of mode of representation is experiencing. Can it be assimilated to a sort of believing or knowing? Or perhaps experiencing is a sui generis mode of representing. 3.2 Why Do Things Appear The Way They Do? What gives perceptual experiences their sensuous characters? Explaining Sensuous Character In seeing the wall as white, the wall appears white to Bob because of his experience s representational nature: that is, because Bob s experience concerns the wall, and because it is a representing of the wall as white (in the visual mode), the wall appears white to Bob. The way things look to Bob is accounted for in terms of the way Bob s experience represents the world as being, and the mode in which his experience represents things. The representationalist holds that if we change the sensuous character of Bob s experience (e.g., things go from looking white to Bob to looking yellow to Bob), then we must have a change in the underlying representational facts e.g., changes to any or all of the subject-matter, mode, or representational content. (They might also hold that if we change the representational facts, we thereby change the sensuous character.) 3.3 Contrasts with the Sense-Datum Theory Experiences are Representations not Relations The representationalist thinks that experiences have a subject-matter: they are of or as of or are about or concern things. But experiences are conceived as representations of a subject-matter not relations to it. Experiences are not constituted by relations of direct awareness, but representations. Representations Lack Existential Import A representation of x doesn t require the existence of x, but a relation to x does. (A representation in a picture of a unicorn doesn t require the existence of a unicorn. But kicking a unicorn bearing that sort of relation to it does.) Put this together and: 4

Important Difference On the representational view, one can have an experience in which there sensibly appears to be something which has a sensible quality F, even in the absence of an F thing. The subject-matter just needs to be represented not really present. The Phenomenal Principle demands that such experiences involve the real presence of an F thing which one is directly aware of. The representational view denies this. Illustration: Pink Rat Example One can have an experience in which there seems to be a pink rat in the corner even in the absence of any such rat in the corner. Both sides agree on this. But there is divergence: Sense-Datum View: The Sense-Datum Theorist then says: but one must be directly aware of a pink thing nonetheless, a pink sense-datum distinct from the rat. Therefore, there must be a pink thing, since awareness is a relation, and relations entail the existence of their relata. The real presence of the pink thing explains how the experience gets its pinkish senuous character. Representational View: The Representationalist says that having this experience doesn t require direct awareness of anything (rat or otherwise). It is merely a matter of the representation of pink rat in the corner. And like representations more generally, this doesn t require the existnece of the subject-matter represented, whether a pink rat, or a pink thing. The pinkish sensuous character of the experience comes from the representation of that colour quality as opposed to other colour qualities. Given this, we can see how a Representationalist will account for illusion: Representational Account of Illusion When Bob sees the white wall as yellow, the experience he has is a representational state, in the visual mode, in which Bob represents the wall as yellow. The yellowish sensuous character of his experience comes not from the the real presence of anything yellow, but rather from the representing, in the visual mode, of the wall as yellow. Since the wall is not yellow, the experience is inaccurate. 3.4 Conclusions? The Representational View provides an alternative explanation of the phenomenological facts which seems just as good as the Sense-Datum Theorist s exaplantion. But broader explanatory considerations seem to put Representationalism ahead: (i) Cogntive Science Consideration: Representationalism makes good sense of how cognitive science treats experiences. 5

(ii) Parsimony Consideration: Representationalism doesn t posit sense-data distinct from ordinary objects. (iii) Representationalism does, whereas the Sense-Datum Theory doesn t, save Common-Sense Realism. Challenge One: Representationalism does away with the relation of awareness in its analysis of experience. But according to Common-Sense Realism we are sometimes directly aware of ordinary objects in illusory or veridical experiences. Answer: Experience itself is understood in non-relational terms. But this is consistent with being aware of ordinary objects. Bob has an experience which represents the wall as F. That may be illusory or veridical. It is a visual representational state which represents the wall in a certain way. The wall itself is external to the state. The state itself is not constituted by a relation to the wall. But as long as in fact the wall is appropriately hooked up to the experience (e.g., by causing it in the right sort of way), Bob will count as seeing the wall, and thus as being aware of the wall. Challenge Two: But if Bob is representing the wall, then surely he is aware of it indirectly. Answer: No. Representationalism admits no perceptual proxies. There is just the wall which Bob directly sees. There is a representational content. But this is not an object of awareness. (Representationalism is not Representative Realism, but a form of direct realism.) The Conclusion: We have not refuted, but undermined the Phenomenal Principle: it is inadequately motivated. We have an alternative which also explains the phenomenological facts, and seems more plausible than the Phenomenal Principle. We can thus reject the Argument from Illusion, at least until we get a firmer motivation for the Phenomenal Principle which tells us why we should accept it and not Representationalism. Next week: Finally, I ll tell you how I want to resist the Argument. We can do it even if we hold on to the Sense-Datum Theory. References Crane, Tim (2001). Elements of Mind: An Introduction to the Philosophy of Mind. Oxford: Oxford University Press. (2009). Intentionalism. In: Oxford Handbook to the Philosophy of Mind. Ed. by Brian P. McLaughlin, Ansgar Beckermann, and Sven Walter. Oxford: Oxford University Press, pp. 474 493. (2013). The Objects of Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Russell, Bertrand (1912). The Problems of Philosophy. London: Williams and Norgate. Searle, John (1983). Intentionality. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Strawson, P. F. (1979). Perception and its Objects. In: Perception and Identity: Essays Presented to A. J. Ayer with His Replies. Ed. by Graham Macdonald. London: Macmillan. Craig French (cf397) 27/10/14 6