Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press,

Similar documents
Peirce's Remarkable Rules of Inference

Background to Gottlob Frege

Lecture 7. Scope and Anaphora. October 27, 2008 Hana Filip 1

Introduction p. 1 The Elements of an Argument p. 1 Deduction and Induction p. 5 Deductive Argument Forms p. 7 Truth and Validity p. 8 Soundness p.

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

1 The structure of this exercise

Intensional Relative Clauses and the Semantics of Variable Objects

The Language of First-Order Predicate Logic

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

General enquiries and questions regarding potential submissions may be sent to the Editor, Professor Mark Wynn:

Glossary alliteration allusion analogy anaphora anecdote annotation antecedent antimetabole antithesis aphorism appositive archaic diction argument

For every sentences A and B, there is a sentence: A B,

11. SUMMARY OF THE BASIC QUANTIFIER TRANSLATION PATTERNS SO FAR EXAMINED

Scientific Philosophy

I-language Chapter 8: Anaphor Binding

MONOTONE AMAZEMENT RICK NOUWEN

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

What s New in the 17th Edition

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

OKLAHOMA SUBJECT AREA TESTS (OSAT )

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Singular Propositions, Abstract Constituents, and Propositional Attitudes

Comparatives, Indices, and Scope

The Debate on Research in the Arts

6.034 Notes: Section 4.1

! Japanese: a wh-in-situ language. ! Taroo-ga [ DP. ! Taroo-ga [ CP. ! Wh-words don t move. Islands don t matter.

Disquotation, Conditionals, and the Liar 1

By Tetsushi Hirano. PHENOMENOLOGY at the University College of Dublin on June 21 st 2013)

LESSON 30: REVIEW & QUIZ (DEPENDENT CLAUSES)

Philosophy Department Expanded Course Descriptions Fall, 2007

Possible Ramifications for Superiority

ARISTOTLE ON LANGUAGE PARALOGISMS SophElen. c.4 p.165b-166b

Genuine Process Logic

Designing a Deductive Foundation System

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

An Aristotelian Puzzle about Definition: Metaphysics VII.12 Alan Code

8. Numerations The existential quantifier Exemplification Overview

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

Linking semantic and pragmatic factors in the Japanese Internally Headed Relative Clause

THE SUBSTITUTIONAL ANALYSIS OF LOGICAL CONSEQUENCE

CAS LX 522 Syntax I. Islands. Wh-islands. Phases. Complex Noun Phrase islands. Adjunct islands

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

Language and Mind Prof. Rajesh Kumar Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Symbolization and Truth-Functional Connectives in SL

Ideas of Language from Antiquity to Modern Times

LOGICO-SEMANTIC ASPECTS OF TRUTHFULNESS

STYLISTIC ANALYSIS OF MAYA ANGELOU S EQUALITY

Elements of Style. Anders O.F. Hendrickson

STRUCTURES AND STRUCTURALISM IN CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

winter but it rained often during the summer

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

8. Numerations The existential quantifier Overview

Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes* Tyler Burge

The Prenective View of propositional content

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

House Style for Physical Geography at Keele. Updated 25 th September 2012, Peter G Knight

MATTHEWS GARETH B. Aristotelian Explanation. on "the role of existential presuppositions in syllogistic premisses"

Curriculum Map: Academic English 11 Meadville Area Senior High School English Department

February 16, 2007 Menéndez-Benito. Challenges/ Problems for Carlson 1977

Simplicity, Its Failures And a Naturalistic Rescue?

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Knowledge Representation

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

Robert Pirsig offers a critique of academic writing.

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

How Does it Feel? Point of View in Translation: The Case of Virginia Woolf into French

How to Analyze a Text Some Aspects to Consider

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

Tropes and the Semantics of Adjectives

CHAPTER 15. Five Theses on De Re States and Attitudes. Tyler Burge

Non-Classical Logics. Viorica Sofronie-Stokkermans Winter Semester 2012/2013

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

THE PROBLEM OF INTERPRETING MODAL LOGIC w. V. QUINE

Replies to the Critics

Advanced Placement English Language and Composition Mrs. Ellie Kenworthy 2016 Summer Reading Assignment

- 1 - I. Aristotle A. Biographical data 1. Macedonian, from Stagira; hence often referred to as "the Stagirite". 2. Dates: B. C. 3.

Lesson 50: Theater (20-25 minutes)

The essential and the derivative moods of Aristotelian syllogism

AP English Language and Composition Summer Assignment 2017

English II STAAR EOC Review

QUANTIFICATION IN AFRICAN LOGIC. Jonathan M. O. Chimakonam Ph.D Department of Philosophy University of Calabar, Nigeria

Principal version published in the University of Innsbruck Bulletin of 4 June 2012, Issue 31, No. 314

From Pythagoras to the Digital Computer: The Intellectual Roots of Symbolic Artificial Intelligence

ELA Scope and Sequence Grade 5 (Revised 6/16)

The structure of this ppt

Re-appraising the role of alternations in construction grammar: the case of the conative construction

COMMONLY MISUSED AND PROBLEM WORDS AND EXPRESSIONS

Please allow myself to introduce myself. The reflexive ("self") pronouns only have two purposes:

ACT English Test. Instructions. Usage and Mechanics Punctuation (10 questions) Grammar and Usage (12 questions) Sentence Structure (18 questions)

Similarities in Amy Tans Two Kinds

First Order Logic. Xiaojin Zhu Computer Sciences Department University of Wisconsin, Madison. [Based on slides from Burr Settles]

SNP Best-set Typesetter Ltd. Article No.: 583 Delivery Date: 31 October 2005 Page Extent: 4 pp

Transcription:

Articulating Medieval Logic, by Terence Parsons. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014. Pp. xiii + 331. H/b 50.00. This is a very exciting book that makes some bold claims about the power of medieval logic. But it is self-confessedly not an introduction to medieval logic (p. 5). Rather, it represents the animadversions of a twentieth- (or even twenty-first)- century philosopher of logic and linguistics suddenly finding himself working within the framework of fourteenth-century logic (rather as Mark Twain s Connecticut Yankee found himself at the court of King Arthur cf. p. 4). Nonetheless, the book seems to have had its origins as such an introduction to the logic of medieval times. This is most apparent in the exercises (labelled Applications ) that punctuate the text every few pages. They are in fact surprisingly useful in testing for him or herself the reader s comprehension. Unfortunately, there are no worked solutions in the book, and so no assistance for the reader as Parsons formal system becomes more and more complex chapter by chapter. Readers may, therefore, wish to consult https://sites.google.com/site/tparsons5555/home/articulating-medieval-logic, where the author gives solutions to many of the exercises, lists errata and summarises the formation rules and rules of inference. The idea for articulating medieval logic is this: the medievals, following Aristotle s lead, did not formalize their logic, but regimented natural language. For example, Aristotle forced propositions into the straitjacket of the A, E, I and O forms: P belongs to every, no, some, or not every S. Syllogistic validity is formal in the 1

sense that it must hold whatever terms replace the schematic letters in the three two-premise schemata distinguished by the position of the middle term that connects the premises. Parsons opens his book by rehearsing Aristotelian logic as seen by the medievals. But the medievals went far beyond Aristotle. Indeed, Parsons claims (ch. 9) that the whole of first-order predicate logic can be represented in medieval logic, and concludes that chapter by attempting to express Peano s postulates for arithmetic in his regimented notation. Parsons dubs his regimented language Linguish, a system of logical forms based on medieval Latin. As such, Linguish inherits the grammar of Latin married strictly speaking to the vocabulary of Latin too, but expressed using English vocabulary, for the convenience of English readers (p. 84). Latin is at root an SOVlanguage, that is, the word order of the simplest sentences places the verb at the end (subject-object-verb), and so does Linguish. In its simplest form, introduced in ch. 4, the only verb is the copula, is. The syntax and vocabulary of Linguish are steadily expanded through the book, so that by the end one has a system of grammatical construction and derivational licence which merits the epithet baroque. One unfortunate (but understandable) omission is a summary, perhaps at the end of the book, of the full system of rules of both grammar and derivation. As it is, one must try to trace the successive extensions of the initial formulation in ch. 4 made in subsequent chapters. But such a summary would be contrary to the spirit of the book and intention of the author. The book does not claim to have exhausted the possibilities for extension and expressive power. Indeed, the proof of completeness (that is, of capturing modern logic within Parsons medieval 2

system) is followed by further complications concerning tense and modality in a final chapter 10. The most notable difference between Linguish and modern logic is that it has no variables. Variables in modern logic serve, among other things, to connect different syntactic positions in a formula, the subject of one predicate with the object of another and a quantifier which binds both. The latter function is provided by grammatical markers in Linguish, the former by the theory of anaphora. In the markers, Parsons takes the notion of theta-role from Cartesian linguistics, whereby each verb requires further syntactic elements to perform certain thematic roles, e.g., those of agent, patient or goal. In Linguish, logical forms are generated successively by rules which prepose denoting phrases ( Socrates, every man, some horse ), each with its own marker, and the particle not, to a verb, thereby closing the unbound markers attached to the verb. No two denoting phrases may share a marker, nor may verbs share markers. Consequently, there is a one-one relation between each denoting phrase (singular term or quantified expression) and each theta-role assigned to a verb. Linguish is basically a term logic; conjunctions, disjunctions and conditionals come later. Once a logical form has been generated, further rules interpret it by converting it to a surface form which bears some resemblance to a regimented sentence of English. Other rules yield the truth-conditions of the logical form, and yet others give an account of deducibility between logical forms. Parsons gives a Henkin-style completeness proof for the basic system presented in ch. 4. 3

But that system is far from complete, for as noted, an essential aspect of modern logic, and of natural language, is missing, anaphoric reference what the medievals called the theory of relative terms. Without a theory of anaphora, Parsons conjectures (p. 261), his theory is decidable; with it, he shows (pp. 265 ff.), it can capture the standard example of a serial irreflexive transitive relation, whose domain must be infinite. The simplest, naïve account of relatives is that they can be replaced by their antecedents. But this is true only of singular terms, Parsons claims (p. 228; cf. p. 239 n.). To extend the account to general (or common) terms, one needs some account of their semantics, and that was given in medieval logic by their distinctive, and idiosyncratic, account of what they called the supposition of terms. For discrete (i.e., singular) terms, this is similar to reference; for common terms, it is an account of quantification. Parsons is unduly modest in mentioning only briefly ( 7.12, pp. 223-6) what is arguably his most significant contribution (before the present volume) to our understanding of medieval logic, the notion of global quantificational import. A common term in its normal use not only supposits for certain objects, it supposits for them in a certain way these are the so-called modes of common (personal) supposition : these modes are determinate (wide-scope existential quantificational import in Parsons terms); (confused and) distributive (universal quantificational import); and (merely) confused (narrow-scope existential import). Through the notion of quantificational import, Parsons is able to explain a long-standing puzzle about the mode of supposition of the predicates of O-propositions relative to E-propositions (of the form Not every S is P and No S is P, respectively). The medievals claimed, to a 4

man, that P has distributive supposition in both. But whereas No S is P is equivalent to a conjunction of propositions of the form No S is this P, Not every S is P is not equivalent to any such conjunction. But it does entail such a conjunction, for whereas P in No S is P has wide-scope universal import, in Not every S is P it has narrow-scope universal import. By distinguishing wide- from narrow-scope universal import, Parsons is able to restore symmetry to the application of the modes to the four corners of the traditional square of opposition. To return to relatives: although relatives with quantified antecedent cannot be replaced by their antecedents (while preserving sense and truth), their mode of supposition is determined by them. The theory is similar to that of so-called E-type pronouns in contemporary philosophy of language: to capture their mode of supposition, we replace the pronoun with a restrictive relative clause. Example: A man coughed. He was ill. We cannot replace he with a man on pain of changing the meaning, but we can explain its supposition by replacing it with the man who coughed. The supposition of the pronoun is the same as that of its antecedent, but singled for its antecedent. Parsons follows Hülsen in generalizing the notion of singulation which they find in the medievals to explain the E-type pronoun. One of the most significant achievements of the medievals was their account of the logic of so-called oblique terms. Although the theory was not fully worked out by them, it certainly answers and silences De Morgan s famous criticism of traditional logic, that it could not account for inferences involving such terms. But traditional logic of his time was a poor echo of the theory developed in the heyday of medieval logic, the fourteenth century. Parsons shows (p. 163) how to derive 5

Every horse s head is an animal s head from Every horse is an animal. The genitives here are an example of oblique terms as also are accusatives such as the direct objects of transitive verbs. In Linguish, they create what Parsons calls parasitic terms (p. 130 note that variable in the definition on that page, and elsewhere, e.g., p. 157, is a typo for marker ): a parasitic term is one that incorporates a (grammatical) marker. If Cicero sees a donkey, he is of-a-donkey acc a seeing thing; if he owns a donkey, he is a donkey-possessor and his donkeys are of-cicero. Theta-roles are here extended to track these connections. Despite the apparent conclusiveness implied by Parsons answer to De Morgan, by his completeness proof, and by his demonstration that modern logic can be represented in (his elaboration of) medieval logic, Parsons actually presents us with a programme with a challenge, in fact. He has shown how to use insights from medieval logic to construct a regimented natural language that elucidates many of the logical features of our language which modern logic captures only by forcing it into an unnatural Procrustean form. The books lacks a conclusion because that task is not completed. Other features of natural language remain to be incorporated tense for one. A start is made on this in the final chapter. But there is enough in this rich volume to inspire future researchers to adapt medieval insights to further aspects of the rich logic of natural language. Arché Research Centre University of St Andrews 17-19 College St. STEPHEN READ 6

St Andrews, Fife KY16 9AA Scotland, U.K. 7