Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Similar documents
INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

Hoyningen Symposium Systematicity: The Nature of Science

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.


Feminism, Underdetermination, and Values in Science

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

What is Science? What is the purpose of science? What is the relationship between science and social theory?

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

EXPANDED COURSE DESCRIPTIONS UC DAVIS PHILOSOPHY DEPARTMENT SPRING, Michael Glanzberg MWF 10:00-10:50a.m., 176 Everson CRNs:

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Thomas Kuhn's "The Structure of Scientific Revolutions"

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Art, Social Justice, and Critical Theory Colloquium:

observation and conceptual interpretation

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Normative and Positive Economics

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Thesis-Defense Paper Project Phi 335 Epistemology Jared Bates, Winter 2014

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Colloque Écritures: sur les traces de Jack Goody - Lyon, January 2008

George Levine, Darwin the Writer, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, 272 pp.

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Wittgenstein On Myth, Ritual And Science

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant

Aristotle on the Human Good

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

NOTES ON COLLINGWOOD S PRINCIPLES OF ART

Course Outcome. Subject: English ( Major) Semester I

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Pragmatism and Idealism

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

SpringBoard Academic Vocabulary for Grades 10-11

Hear hear. Århus, 11 January An acoustemological manifesto

Philosophy in the educational process: Understanding what cannot be taught

Post-positivism. Nick J Fox

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

In retrospect: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

Lilie Chouliaraki Solidarity and spectatorship. Book (Excerpt)

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Critical discourse analysis as dialectical reasoning: the Kilburn Manifesto

Chaïm Perelman s New Rhetoric. Chaïm Perelman was a prominent rhetorician of the twentieth century. He was born in

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

An essay on Alasdair MacIntyre s Relativism. Power and Philosophy

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

MARXIST LITERARY CRITICISM. Literary Theories

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Emerging Questions: Fernando F. Segovia and the Challenges of Cultural Interpretation

The Debate on Research in the Arts

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

M E M O. When the book is published, the University of Guelph will be acknowledged for their support (in the acknowledgements section of the book).

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

Hume s Sentimentalism: What Not Who Should Have The Final Word Elisabeth Schellekens

Significant Differences An Interview with Elizabeth Grosz

Zhu Xi's Reading of the Analects: Canon, Commentary, and the Classical Tradition (review)

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Feminist Research and Paradigm Shift in Anthropology

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

CHAPTER 1 INTRODUCTION. Grey s Anatomy is an American television series created by Shonda Rhimes that has

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Tradition and the Individual Poem: An Inquiry into Anthologies (review)

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF. the oxford handbook of WORLD PHILOSOPHY. GARFIELD-Halftitle2-Page Proof 1 August 10, :24 PM

Philip Joseph Kain. Santa Clara University Scotts Valley, CA Santa Clara, CA fax

Critical Theory. Mark Olssen University of Surrey. Social Research at Frankfurt-am Main in The term critical theory was originally

Columbia University Center for Contemporary Critical Thought. Fall 2015 Seminar. The Idea of a Critical Political Theory. Professor Linda Zerilli

By Maximus Monaheng Sefotho (PhD). 16 th June, 2015

Where is the understanding?

Ethnographic R. From outside, no access to cultural meanings From inside, only limited access to cultural meanings

Transcription:

Reading across Borders: Storytelling and Knowledges of Resistance (review) Susan E. Babbitt Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp. 203-206 (Review) Published by Indiana University Press DOI: 10.1353/hyp.2006.0018 For additional information about this article http://muse.jhu.edu/journals/hyp/summary/v021/21.3babbitt.html Access provided by Penn State Univ Libraries (21 Feb 2016 10:39 GMT)

Book Reviews 203 Reading across Borders: Storytelling and Knowledges of Resistance. By SHARI STONE-MEDIATORE. NewYork: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003. Susan Babbitt In Reading across Borders: Storytelling and Knowledges of Resistance, Shari Stone- Mediatore defends the critical importance of storytelling in the pursuit of mature political consciousness, and suggests means for evaluating such stories. Traditional philosophy, she claims, does not recognize the epistemic value of more subjective, storylike representations of the world (see, for example, 9, 185), being more concerned about truth and objectivity and preferring the resoluteness it associates with rational thought (185). Stone-Mediatore claims that personal stories are not mere stories (161); they can be justified, she argues, according to their contribution to understanding and critical engagement (179 91). Drawing upon specific examples, Stone-Mediatore shows how personal stories of struggle are able to challenge basic norms and categories (143), such as assumptions about identity (147f) and agency (149f). Moreover, such stories are not always strictly autobiographical at least not in a standard sense but rather are stories about peoples, and about national goals, intending specifically to reclaim and revalue (152) the experience of the oppressed. By stories or narratives the author has in mind a pattern of identifiable actors and action-units that are qualified through metaphor and other poetic devices and that are related together through a coherent structure of beginnings and endings (3). While it might seem that such a definition describes any theoretical account explanations themselves are stories, with actors, actions, beginnings, and endings the stories Stone-Mediatore refers to in Reading across Borders are significantly constitutive of the actors, actions, and events they describe. That is, they bring about possibilities for understanding by allowing readers to test and revise their community s taken-for-granted narrative paradigms through experience of more marginalized perspectives (185). The creative, engaged, tentative character of writing from outside ruling institutions (190), when engaged seriously, allows readers to imagine the world as it might be. Thus, such stories involve more explicitly moral and political objectives for bringing about democracy, justice, and communication. Stone-Mediatore describes, for example, to the genre of testimonios in Latin America that aims to retell histories in order to bring about possibilities for national identity and direction. She refers specifically to Cuba, where in 1959 the new government recognized that the country s history must be retold to include the stories of the plantations, in order to bring about new and more appropriate values, such as an antiracist way of thinking (151). Drawing upon Immanuel Kant and Hannah Arendt, among others, Stone- Mediatore suggests criteria for assessing the critical merits of stories. In the

204 Hypatia author s view, storytelling can change expectations about what, and who, gets recognized. Passionate stories of others lives and aspirations make us aware of our unself-conscious expectations because when we engage such realities we encounter those expectations (see, for example, 149, 167). But not all such accounts are useful. The author s proposal for the standard of enlarged thought (184f) is, roughly, that stories contribute to our knowledge when they promote self-examination, responsible participation in public life, and accountability to others (190). Personal stories are epistemically useful when they promote relevant sorts of ethical development, that is, when they provide access to things we need to know to become more humanely aware and motivated. Reading across Borders is valuable for its insight into the fascinating role of stories of struggle in self- and social understanding. However, the presentation of the problem is misleading, perhaps undermining the philosophical significance of work in this area some women in the global South have already done. Stone- Mediatore presents the importance of personal stories in feminist work as if the epistemic role of stories is something that philosophers, especially epistemologists, have not recognized. In philosophy, she claims, there exists a longstanding opposition between truth and story-telling (5). Yet philosophers have long been aware of the role of storytelling in understanding the world. Aristotle, for example, was famously interested in storytelling, and philosophers of science have argued since the middle of the twentieth century that theories are like stories. Darwin did not defend a principle, Philip Kitcher argues in Abusing Science: The Case against Creationism (1984). Rather, Darwin justified his theory by telling stories about phenomena in the world for which stories were needed. Additionally, Thomas Kuhn revolutionized philosophy by telling a story about the history of science in which scientists interpret the world according to their background myths, social symbols, and personal belief structures, moral and otherwise, recognizing, as Stone-Mediatore does about marginalized persons stories, the radically situated nature of knowledge pursuits (Kuhn 1962). It is true that traditional philosophy has been insensitive to, or even sometimes unaware of, the problem of the oppressed, more specifically the problems that arise when we consider that some people are unrecognized, within philosophical or political theory, as full persons. But certainly this insight is not original to feminist scholarship. Trappist monk and philosopher Thomas Merton, writing about the power of stories, specifically of black fiction and personal memoirs in 1961, said, The deep elemental stirrings that lead to social change, begin within the hearts of men whose thoughts have hitherto not been articulate or who have never gained a hearing or whose needs are therefore ignored, suppressed and treated as if they did not exist. There is no revolution without a voice.... The

Book Reviews 205 more the cry of the oppressed is ignored, the more it strengthens itself with a mysterious power that is to be gained from myth, symbol and prophecy. There is no revolution without poets who are also seers. There is no revolution without prophetic songs. (Merton 1980, 72) Instead of apparently dismissing the philosophical tradition as mostly positivistic, it might have been more helpful if Stone-Mediatore had situated feminist work within the broader traditions of epistemology, which mostly by now recognize the epistemic role of particular circumstances and conditions, including background beliefs, myths, and dramatic scenarios. In particular, since the middle of the last century, when positivism failed to explain the thoroughgoing theory-ladenness of all aspects of scientific activity, analytic philosophy of science has contributed to our understanding of objectivity and truth. Whereas Stone-Mediatore suggests that stories in feminist work especially feminist work from the global South are not about objectivity, one could think that personal stories of struggle contribute to our understanding of the world in just the way Darwin s stories did: they explain aspects of the world that need explaining (in this case, the lack of global justice) but which had before not been recognized as needing explanation, at least not in that specific way. Darwin s particular stories about such phenomena as the degenerate limbs of boa constrictors demonstrated the merits of his broader, more general theory of evolution. Such particular stories were able to explain what needed explaining within the story being told, thereby demonstrating the merits of the broader story upon which the particular story draws (Boyd 1991). Domitila Barrios de Chungara s personal account of her struggles in the Bolivian mines, for instance, contributes to our understanding of more general concepts like identity and agency because Barrios s reliance upon certain understandings of such concepts explains the particular life story she tells, a story that convinces us precisely because of its particular explanatory capacity as regards aspects of human experience. As Stone-Mediatore argues in her final chapter, we evaluate personal stories precisely in this way: we measure the contribution of such stories to our political and moral understanding, that is, their explanatory power as regards issues we need to understand, issues the stories themselves raise, such as identity, agency, and ethical responsibility. We look for stories that promote selfreflexivity, public accountability, and open-mindedness (190). Setting the work of feminist scholars against objectivity and truth, as Stone-Mediatore often does, undermines the work of some feminist scholars who aim precisely to tell us something about the nature of knowledge and what we need to do to get things right about the world. Nkiru Nzegwu s work on Nigerian women s associations is not most importantly personal and particular, although it is based upon her own

206 Hypatia experience; rather, it aims to tell us something about the nature of explanation and how it is that scholars, including feminists, get wrong the significance of Africans stories (Nzegwu 2006). Her specifically epistemological point is that feminists cannot hear Africans stories as having to do with such questions as the nature of knowledge and truth as long as they hear them as stories of others. Rather than thinking from others lives, in Nzegwu s view, feminists need to rethink their own lives, especially the philosophical assumptions grounding national identity, so that the others are no longer others, but rather the same, namely, human. Reading across Borders moves in this direction, showing how others stories help us to think differently about ourselves. But Stone-Mediatore s contribution is undermined by her distracting insistence that the important thing about feminists stories is that they are personal and particular, something other than theoretical discourse (1). Jacqueline M. Davies s analyses of narrative ethics, for instance, argues that storytelling in feminist work is about the nature of ethical knowledge and justification (Davies forthcoming). The most intriguing claims in Reading across Borders suggest that the significance of feminist work, particularly that from feminists in the global South, is not that it is personal, open-minded, tentative, creative, and so on, but rather that it contributes, because of the knowledge brought to the question, to a more objective and truthful understanding of the human condition, and the moral obligations implied therein for all of us. References Boyd. R. N. 1991. Observations, explanatory power, and simplicity: Toward a non- Humean account. In The philosophy of science, ed. P. Gaspar Boyd and J. D. Trout. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Davies, Jacqueline M. Narrative ethics. Forthcoming. Kitcher, Philip. 1984. Abusing science: The case against creationism. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press. Kuhn, Thomas. 1962. Scientific revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Merton, Thomas. 1980. Seeds of destruction. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux. Nzegwu, Nkiru. 2006. Family matters: Feminist concepts in African philosophy of culture. Albany: SUNY Press