Non-Reducibility with Knowledge wh: Experimental Investigations

Similar documents
What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Intro to Pragmatics (Fox/Menéndez-Benito) 10/12/06. Questions 1

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

IF MONTY HALL FALLS OR CRAWLS

Lecture 24: Motivating Modal Logic, Translating into It

On Recanati s Mental Files

STAT 113: Statistics and Society Ellen Gundlach, Purdue University. (Chapters refer to Moore and Notz, Statistics: Concepts and Controversies, 8e)

Vagueness & Pragmatics

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The University of Hong Kong. American Speech-Language-Hearing Association Convention San Diego November Contact:

in the Howard County Public School System and Rocketship Education

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

When Do Vehicles of Similes Become Figurative? Gaze Patterns Show that Similes and Metaphors are Initially Processed Differently

The Roles of Politeness and Humor in the Asymmetry of Affect in Verbal Irony

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

Ridgeview Publishing Company

A critical pragmatic approach to irony

Types of perceptual content

Formalizing Irony with Doxastic Logic

Image and Imagination

Rhetorical Questions and Scales

This is a repository copy of Aesthetic Adjectives: Experimental Semantics and Context-Sensitivity.

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

RELATIVISM ABOUT TRUTH AND PERSPECTIVE-NEUTRAL PROPOSITIONS

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

Sound Recording Techniques. MediaCity, Salford Wednesday 26 th March, 2014

Acoustic Prosodic Features In Sarcastic Utterances

Print Books vs. E-books

Formalization: methodology and concrete examples

Approaches to teaching film

EXPRESSIONS FOR DISCUSSION AND DEBATE

1 The structure of this exercise

Jokes and the Linguistic Mind. Debra Aarons. New York, New York: Routledge Pp. xi +272.

Example the number 21 has the following pairs of squares and numbers that produce this sum.

Modeling memory for melodies

Estimation of inter-rater reliability

Sidestepping the holes of holism

1 Pair-list readings and single pair readings

Interpretivism and the Pragmatics of Legal Disagreement

Effect of Compact Disc Materials on Listeners Song Liking

Imperatives are existential modals; Deriving the must-reading as an Implicature. Despina Oikonomou (MIT)

Cambridge International Examinations Cambridge International Advanced Subsidiary and Advanced Level. Published

Critical Thinking 4.2 First steps in analysis Overcoming the natural attitude Acknowledging the limitations of perception

(1) Writing Essays: An Overview. Essay Writing: Purposes. Essay Writing: Product. Essay Writing: Process. Writing to Learn Writing to Communicate

Time Domain Simulations

4 Embodied Phenomenology and Narratives

Possible Ramifications for Superiority

Semantic Research Methodology

Moral Relativism in Context

The Influence of Visual Metaphor Advertising Types on Recall and Attitude According to Congruity-Incongruity

Reducing False Positives in Video Shot Detection

Pitch. The perceptual correlate of frequency: the perceptual dimension along which sounds can be ordered from low to high.

Paired plot designs experience and recommendations for in field product evaluation at Syngenta

In Defense of the Contingently Nonconcrete

The Embedding Problem for Non-Cognitivism; Introduction to Cognitivism; Motivational Externalism

When data collide: Traditional judgments vs. formal experiments in sentence acceptability Grant Goodall UC San Diego

A New Analysis of Verbal Irony

I like those glasses on you, but not in the mirror: Fluency, preference, and virtual mirrors

The Effects of Web Site Aesthetics and Shopping Task on Consumer Online Purchasing Behavior

The Role of Genre Expectation in Literary Readers Engagement in Interpretative Literary Reasoning. KATHRYN S. MCCARTHY B.A., Augustana College, 2009

Irony as Cognitive Deviation

SUPPLEMENTAL TESTIMONY OF ELIZABETH STANTON. A. My name is Elizabeth A. Stanton. I am a Principal Economist at Synapse Energy

How to Obtain a Good Stereo Sound Stage in Cars

Review of Epistemic Modality

Affective response to a set of new musical stimuli W. Trey Hill & Jack A. Palmer Psychological Reports, 106,

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Chapter Two: Long-Term Memory for Timbre

SURVEYS FOR REFLECTIVE PRACTICE

Empirical Evaluation of Animated Agents In a Multi-Modal E-Retail Application

abc Mark Scheme Statistics 3311 General Certificate of Secondary Education Higher Tier 2007 examination - June series

MORAL CONTEXTUALISM AND MORAL RELATIVISM

1.4.5.A2 Formalism in dance, music, theatre, and visual art varies according to personal, cultural, and historical contexts.

Set-Top-Box Pilot and Market Assessment

Today: What s the relationship between. interpretation and intentionality?

STAT 250: Introduction to Biostatistics LAB 6

Student Performance Q&A:

Moral Relativism. Entry for the Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. By Max Kölbel

BBC Trust Review of the BBC s Speech Radio Services

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension

Diachronic and synchronic unity

Internal Realism. Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

The Philosophy of Language. Grice s Theory of Meaning

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

Master thesis. The effects of L2, L1 dubbing and L1 subtitling on the effectiveness of persuasive fictional narratives.

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

The Fellow-Travellers: Intellectual Friends of Communism

Modeling perceived relationships between melody, harmony, and key

Sundance Institute: Artist Demographics in Submissions & Acceptances. Dr. Stacy L. Smith, Marc Choueiti, Hannah Clark & Dr.

Semantics and Generative Grammar. Conversational Implicature: The Basics of the Gricean Theory 1

Ferenc, Szani, László Pitlik, Anikó Balogh, Apertus Nonprofit Ltd.

Kees van Deemter: Not Exactly: In Praise of Vagueness

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

Introduction to Natural Language Processing This week & next week: Classification Sentiment Lexicons

observation and conceptual interpretation

BY RICHARD HIRSH* AND C. A. G. WIERSMA. Division of Biology, California Institute of Technology, Pasadena, California, U.S.A.

Acoustic and musical foundations of the speech/song illusion

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

Symbolization and Truth-Functional Connectives in SL

Sound visualization through a swarm of fireflies

Transcription:

Non-Reducibility with Knowledge wh: Experimental Investigations 1 Knowing wh and Knowing that Obvious starting picture: (1) implies (2). (2) iff (3). (1) John knows that he can buy an Italian newspaper at PaperWorld. (2) John knows where he can buy an Italian newspaper. (3) x s.t. J knows he can buy an Italian newspaper at x. General case: (4) iff (5). (4) J. knows [WH QUESTION] (5) p s.t. p is (a sufficient/a maximal/the best) answer to [WH-Q] and J. knows that p. (RT) Reducibility Thesis: Whether you know WH-Q depends only on which answers you know. RT is typical of theories of knowing wh. Why do we care about RT? Some variant of RT is found in virtually all such accounts, and is often found in treatments of other types of attitude-question ascription. RT plays well with important intuition: know that and know wh inovlve same know. RT account generalizes to other attitudes: agreeing, forgetting, certainty,... If RT fails, we ll want a new story for these connections. 1

2 False Beliefs & Non-Reducibility Claim: knowledge wh doesn t just depend on answers you know. It also depends on what false (potential) answers you believe. Claim contradicts RT. Instead, knowledge wh reduces to knowledge that + false belief that. Non-reducible mention-some George (2011, 2013): know one true item + don t believe any false items. Non-reducible mention-all Spector (2005); Cremers and Chemla (2016): know every (positive) true item + don t believe any false items. Both just ask whether there are false beliefs; dont look at how many. 3 George s 2011; 2013 Judgment Reported judgment: (6) true in AllTrue, false in Mixed. (6) Sue knows where she can buy an Italian newspaper. This is a slight variation on George s example, equivalent (AllTrue) Sue is standing on the street near a store called Newstopia. Sue s friend, Bob, a native of the city who is normally very well-informed and trustworthy, told her that she can buy an Italian newspaper at Newstopia. Having no reason to doubt this, Sue took Bob at his word. Bob was correct about Newstopia, which does sell Italian newspapers. (Mixed) Sue is standing on the street near two stores: one called Paper- World, and another called Newstopia. Sue s friend, Bob, a native of the city who is normally very well-informed and trustworthy, told her that she can buy an Italian newspaper at PaperWorld, and also at Newstopia. Having no reason to doubt this, Sue took Bob at his word. However, Bob completely misinformed Sue about PaperWorld, which does not sell newspapers, but actually just sells stationery and office supplies. Bob was correct about Newstopia. for purposes of the relevant theories. Sue s beliefs in AllTrue: The facts in AllTrue: The facts in Mixed: Sue s beliefs in Mixed: Newstopia sels Italian papers? YES YES YES YES PaperWorld sells Italian Papers? N/A N/A NO YES 2

George claims (6) true in AllTrue, not in Mixed. Available RT accounts predict (6) has same truth value in AllTrue and Mixed. Problem: Judgment more fragile than optimal. George proposes part of an account of knowledge wh that derives this result. Some derive readings where it s false in both. Problem: Is apparently degraded truth a semantic/conventional matter, or truth-with-infelicity? Problem: Untrue how? Just false, or something more exotic? Problem: Proportions seem relevant. Available theories predict 1% false beliefs as bad as 99% false beliefs. Is this plausible? 4 An Initial Test We began with a a simple test of ordinary English speakers truth assessments of (6) in both AllTrue and Mixed. 4.1 Design Participants read the vignettes AllTrue (in which Sue knows an answer and has only true beliefs) and Mixed (in which Sue knows an answer and has relevant false beliefs) in counterbalanced order. After reading each vignette, participants were asked to indicate their agreement with (6) on a scale from 1 ( Completely disagree ) to 7 ( Completely agree ). 103 participants (53 females, M age = 34.32, SD age = 12.11) were recruited from Amazon s Mechanical Turk. (6) Sue knows where she can buy an Italian newspaper. 4.2 Results Participants tended to agree with (6) more strongly in AllTrue than in Mixed. M = 6.23 vs. M = 4.88, t(79.83) = 3.75, p <.001, d =.757 Additional analyses revealed that participants responses were not affected by the order in which they completed the study. 2 participants were excluded from the analyses because they reported that English was not their native language. No main effect of order, χ 2 (1) = 0.17, p =.682, and no interaction effect, χ 2 (1) = 2.51, p =.113. 3

Knowledge Ascription Agreement 6 4 2 Agent's Beliefs All true Mixed Figure 1: Boxplots of participants agreement rating in the AllTrue and Mixed conditions. Dots depict individual participants responses, the box plots show the 25th and 75th percentiles and the dark line indicates the median response. 4.3 The upshot Some initial evidence that ordinary truth value judgments distinguish AllTrue from Mixed. Also worth noting that participants level of agreement in the Mixed case also differs from what would be expected in a clearly false case. 5 A More Robust Test We then replicated and expanded on this initial study in three ways: We included a comparison case in which the agent s beliefs were all false. We included negated knowledge wh ascriptions. We looked at several related where questions, as in (7-a) (7-c). (7) a. Sue knows where she can buy an Italian newspaper. b. Sue knows where to buy an Italian newspaper. c. Sue knows where she should buy an Italian newspaper. These negated ascriptions should shed some light on whether the judgments of reduced truth we saw in the first test were the result of at-issue falsehood, or some other status such as presupposition failure or vagueness-associated borderline falsehood. 4

5.1 Design Participants were randomly assigned to read AllTrue, Mixed, or AllFalse. (AllFalse) Sue is standing on the street near a store called Paperworld. Sue s friend, Bob, a native of the city who is normally very well-informed and trustworthy, told her that she can buy an Italian newspaper at Paperworld. Having no reason to doubt this, Sue has always assumed that Bob was right. However, Bob completely misinformed Sue about Paperworld, which does not sell newspapers, but actually just sells stationery and office supplies. 989 participants (362 females, M age = 29.98, SD age = 9.77) were recruited from Amazon s Mechanical Turk. After reading the vignette, participants were either asked to rate their agreement with (7-a) (7-c) or were asked to rate their agreement with the negated form of one of these three knowledge wh ascriptions (8-a) (8-c). (8) a. Sue doesn t know where she can buy an Italian newspaper. b. Sue doesn t know where to buy an Italian newspaper. c. Sue doesn t know where she should buy an Italian newspaper. 5.2 Results Knows where Doesn't know where 22 participants were excluded from the analyses because they reported that English was not their native language. Knowledge Ascription Agreement 6 4 2 Agent's Beliefs All true Mixed All false Figure 2: Boxplots of participants agreement rating with the nonnegated (left) and negated (right) knowledge ascriptions in the All- True, Mixed and AllFalse conditions for all three forms of knowledge wh statements. 5

First, consider participants agreement ratings with the the non-negated knowledge wh ascriptions: Participants agreed more in the AllTrue than in the Mixed conditions. (M = 6.24) vs. (M = 4.24), t(213.87) = 10.00, p <.001, d = 1.285. Participants agreed more in the Mixed than in the All false conditions. (M = 4.24) vs. (M = 1.97), t(205.08) = 12.08, p <.001, d = 1.432. Participants first-trial responses revealed a main effects of False Beliefs, χ 2 (2) = 549.73, p <.001 and a False Belief Negation interaction effect χ 2 (2) = 29.345, p <.001. Next, consider participants agreement ratings with the the negated knowledge wh ascriptions: Participants agreed less in the AllTrue than in the Mixed conditions. (M = 2.84) vs. (M = 3.50), t(219.52) = 2.41, p =.017, d = 0.322. Participants agreed less in the Mixed than in the All false conditions. 5.3 The upshot (M = 3.50) vs. (M = 5.66), t(205.08) = 12.08, p <.001, d = 1.232. Robust evidence for an effect that supports non-reducibility. At the same time, Mixed clearly differs from All false, suggesting that we may want to try accounting for the effect without appealing to a semantic/conventionalized account. 6 The Naive Relevance-Implicature Approach One natural worry to have is that we may have been unintentionally varying the relevance of the knowledge facts to the implied problem-at-hand (cf. Grice (1975)). We assessed this possibility by varying whether the person to whom knowledge is ascribed shares a language in common with the person looking for a newspaper. If usefulness as a problem-solving resource is driving a relevance implicature effect responsible for the pattern of judgments, we should expect false beliefs and lack of a shared language to produce similar degraded truth judgments. 6.1 Design We randomly assigned participants to read either (9), in which a woman named Sue and a man named Bob do not share a common language or (10), in which they do. 257 participants (84 females, M age = 29.53, SD age = 9.12) were recruited from Amazon s Mechanical Turk. (9) No Shared language: Sue, who speaks only Italian and English, needs to buy an Italian newspaper. She is standing on the street near two stores: one called PaperWorld, and one called Cellulose City. Sue sees a man named Bob nearby. Bob is a native of the city who is normally very well-informed and trustworthy. 6

Bob speaks only Cantonese and Hungarian. He believes that Paper- World and Cellulose City sell Italian newspapers. He would be happy to tell this to Sue if she asked and he understood her. However, Bob would not be able to understand Sue s question, since they can t speak the same language. (10) Shared language: Sue, who speaks only Italian and English, needs to buy an Italian newspaper. She is standing on the street near two stores: one called PaperWorld, and one called Cellulose City. Sue sees a man named Bob nearby. Bob is a native of the city who is normally very well-informed and trustworthy. Bob speaks only English and Hungarian. He believes that PaperWorld and Cellulose City sell Italian newspapers. He would be happy to tell this to Sue if she asked and he understood her. Moreover, Bob should be able to understand Sue s question, since they can speak the same language. In each case, Bob s beliefs about where to buy an Italian newspaper could have been AllTrue (11-a), Mixed (11-b), or AllFalse (11-c). (11) a. Bob is right about both stores: PaperWorld and Cellulose City both sell Italian newspapers. b. Bob is right about PaperWorld. However, Bob is mistaken about Cellulose City, which does not sell Italian newspapers. (It is actually a stationery shop.) c. Bob is completely mistaken about PaperWorld and Cellulose City, neither of which sells Italian newspapers. (They are actually both stationery shops.) Participants rated their agreement with (12) on a scale from 1 ( Completely disagree ) to 7 ( Completely agree ). (12) Bob knows where Sue can buy an Italian newspaper. Additionally, participants completed an item that tests whether we had been successful in manipulating the relevance-implicature (13). (13) Because Sue needs an Italian newspaper, she calls her friend Mary, to ask her what she should do, and happens to mentions that she sees Bob nearby. Mary, who knows that Bob likes to keep up with the latest news from Italy, tells Sue Bob knows where you can buy an Italian newspaper. Given everything you know about Bob, how useful will Mary s information be to Sue? Participants answered on a scale from 1 ( Not at all useful ) to 7 ( Very useful ). 7 At the end of the study, participants also completed a comprehension questions that tested whether they thought that Bob would understand Sue s question if she asked it in English

6.2 Results First, consider participants answers to the usefulness question (13): 6 All true Mixed All false 8 participants were excluded from the analyses because they indicated that English was not their native language. An additional 16 participants were excluded for failing to correctly answer the first comprehension question. Usefulness Rating 4 Agent's Language Shared Unshared 2 Figure 3: Boxplots of participants ratings of the usefulness of the knowledge wh ascription. Participants found the knowledge ascription to be much less useful overall when Bob and Sue did not share a language than when they did. F (1, 227) = 42.04, p <.001 η 2 p =.156 More importantly, when Bob and Sue did not share a language, participants usefulness judgments were not significantly affected by whether Bobs beliefs were AllTrue or Mixed. (M = 3.93) vs. (M = 3.46), t(73.34) = 0.991, p =.325, d = 0.222. This provides a test case for asking whether we still get a significant difference in the truth value judgments between these two cases The 2 (Language: Shared vs No Shared) x 3 (Belief: AllTrue vs Mixed vs AllFalse) Analysis of Variance (ANOVA) also revealed a main effect of false beliefs, F (2, 227) = 56.11, p <.001 η 2 p =.327, and more importantly, a Language False Belief interaction, F (2, 227) = 42.04, p <.001 η 2 p =.077 We next considered participants truth value assessments of (12): Participants truth value judgments were not overall significantly affected by whether or not Sue and Bob shared a language. F (1, 227) = 3.58, p =.060 η 2 p =.016 More importantly, when Bob and Sue did not share a language, participants usefulness judgments were significantly affected by whether Bobs beliefs were AllTrue or Mixed. 8 The 2 (Language: Shared vs No Shared) x 3 (Belief: AllTrue vs Mixed vs All False) Analysis of Variance (ANOVA) also revealed a main effect of the truth of Bob s false beliefs, F (2, 227) = 256.17, p <.001 η 2 p =.693, and more importantly did not reveal a Language False Belief interaction effect, F (2, 227) = 0.26, p =.773 η 2 p =.002.

All true Mixed All false Knowledge Ascription Agreement 6 4 2 Agent's Language Shared Unshared Figure 4: Boxplots of participants agreement ratings with the knowledge wh ascription. (M = 6.63) vs. (M = 5.21), t(49.34) = 4.89, p <.001, d = 1.111. This case provides a clear instance in which false beliefs are affecting participants truth value judgments in a way that cannot be explained by differences in the relevance of the knowledge wh ascriptions. 6.3 The upshot These results count strongly against the relevance-implicature explanation of the non-reducibility effect. They do not, of course, rule out all possible pragmatic accounts, but we ll set this issue to one side until some other specific proposal is offered. 7 Proportional Knowledge wh While the previous studies were informative in demonstrating that false beliefs affect truth assessments of knowledge wh ascriptions, they are not particularly informative as to how false beliefs affect participants truth assessments. We designed a final test that allowed us to come closer to parametrically varying the proportion of the agent s beliefs that were false. This should allow us to begin measuring how participants truth assessments of knowledge wh ascriptions vary as function of the increasing presence of false beliefs. One possibility is that previous analyses were correct in providing a semantic/conventionalized account of the role for false beliefs in knowledge wh, but wrong in the particulars of the role that they were given (see, George s (2011; 2013)). 9

7.1 Design All participants read a vignette in which a woman named Sue was told where to buy a newspaper by her friend Bob (14). (14) Sue is standing on the street near three stores: one called PaperWorld, one called Cellulose City, and one called Newstopia. Sue s friend, Bob, a native of the city who is normally very well-informed and trustworthy, told her that PaperWorld, Newstopia, and Cellulose City all sell Italian newspapers. Having no reason to doubt this, Sue has always assumed that Bob was right. 171 participants (46 females, M age = 29.61, SD age = 9.83) were recruited from Amazon s Mechanical Turk. Participants were told that Bob was either correct about all three stores (15), correct about two of the three stores (16), correct about only one of the stores (17), or incorrect about all of the stores (18). (15) Bob was correct about all three stores, which do in fact all sell Italian newspapers. (16) However, Bob completely misinformed Sue about PaperWorld, which does not sell newspapers, but is actually a stationery shop. Bob was correct about Newstopia and Cellulose City. (17) However, Bob completely misinformed Sue about PaperWorld and Cellulose City, which do not sell newspapers, but are actually both stationery shops. Bob was correct about Newstopia. (18) However, Bob completely misinformed Sue about all three stores, none of which sell Italian newspapers. PaperWorld and Cellulose City, are actually both stationary shops, and Newstopia is an ironically misnamed shop that sells T-shirts with obnoxious political slogans. After reading the vignette, participants rated their agreement with (6), as in previous studies. (6) Sue knows where she can buy an Italian newspaper. 7.2 Results Participants agreement ratings were strongly affected by the proportion of the agent s beliefs that were false. F (3, 164) = 52.74, p <.001 η 2 =.491 Participant s judgments differentiated each of the four cases from each other. 3 participants were excluded from the analyses because they reported that English was not their native language. p s <.05; d s >.56 Additionally, in the 2 of 3 false beliefs condition, participants actually tended to disagree with the knowledge wh ascription. M(SD) = 3.77(2.01) 10

Knowledge Ascription Agreement 6 4 2 Agent's Beliefs 0 of 3 false 1 of 3 false 2 of 3 false 3 of 3 false Figure 5: Agreement rating with the knowledge wh ascription as a function of the portion of the agent s beliefs that were false. 7.3 The upshot Truth assessments of knowledge wh ascriptions are sensitive not only to the presence of false beliefs but also to the proportion of the agent s beliefs that are false. When the agent had proportionally more false than true beliefs, we observed overall disagreement with the knowledge wh ascription. These results motivate an account of knowledge wh with the resources to handle the sort of proportionality effect we observe here. 8 General Discussion What s the lesson? It s complicated. There is a false belief effect. This effect isn t easily handled by obvious releavnce implicature story. There are proportionality effects that nobody seems to predict. Of course, this is hard to rule out entirely, and we ve onyly provided a first step here. 11

9 One Candidate Account: Threshold/Standard-Sensitivity Old story: (19) true iff (20) is. (19) John knows where he can buy an Italian newspaper. (20) There is x s.t. J. knows he can buy an Italian newspaper at x. George (2011, 2013) proposed: (19) true iff both (20) and (21) are. (21) For every x s.t. J. believes he can buy an Italian newspaper at x, he in fact can. New family of proposals: (19) true iff both (20) and (22-a) (22-b) (22-c) are. (22) a. For many x s.t. J. believes he can buy an Italian paper at x, he in fact can. (Where the amount that constitutes many is in part determined by conversational context.) b. For enough x s.t. J. believes he can buy an Italian paper at x, he in fact can. (Where the amount that constitutes enough is in part determined by conversational context.) c. For n% of the x s.t. J. believes he can buy an Italian paper at x, he in fact can. (Where n is a contextually supplied threshold.) Coupled with a theory where different speakers can have different ideas about threshold, and where threshold-vagueness-induced truth value uncertainty results in intermediate truth judgment reports, this plausibly derives gradability effect. More exploration required. Above approach assumes more-or-less bivalent semantics - gradable truth would provide another set of tools. 12

A A Digression on Knowledge that It seemed to us intuitively clear that the key knowledge that claims are simply true in both the AllTrue and Mixed scenarios. However there is, in general, reason to think that false beliefs about related propositions can sometimes render otherwise good knowledge that ascriptions untrue (cf. Goldman (1976)). To check our intuition, we conducted an experiment to assess the truth of knowledge that claims in the situations described by vignettes AllTrue, Mixed, and AllFalse. A.1 Design The methods for this study are similar to those in Section 5 except that participants were instead asked to rate their agreement with knowledge that ascriptions. In the cases where all of Sue s beliefs were true and where Sue s beliefs were both true and false, participants rated their agreement with (23-a). Participants who read the case in which Sue s belief was simply false instead rated their agreement with (23-b), since the this vignette did not mention Newstopia. 161 participants (41 females, M age = 31.17, SD age = 10.27) were recruited from Amazon s Mechanical Turk. (23) a. Sues knows that she can buy an Italian newspaper at Newstopia. b. Sue knows that she can buy an Italian newspaper at Paperworld. After rating their agreement, participants were asked to provide a summary of what they read and then completed series of demographic items including a question asking whether English was their native language. A.2 Results An analysis of the remaining participants agreement ratings with (23-a)revealed that there was no significant difference in their agreement ratings when Sue had only true beliefs (M(SD) = 5.94(1.22)) and when Sue had both true and false beliefs (M(SD) = 5.64(1.86)), t(71.01) = 0.830, p =.409, d = 0.184. For comparison, participants did agree significantly disagree with (23-b) (i.e., with a mean agreement rating below 4) when Sue had only false beliefs (M(SD) = 2.86(1.99)), t(82) = 5.244, p <.001 (Fig. 6). 3 participants were excluded from the analyses because they reported that English was not their native language. A.3 The upshot While we saw above in Sections 4 and 5 that false beliefs reduce truth judgments for knowledge wh ascriptions, we find no analogous effect for knowledge that ascriptions. This suggests that we have a genuine challenge to reductive accounts: the different scenarios support the same facts regarding knowledge that, suggesting that knowledge that does not suffice to determine knowledge wh. 13

6 Know-that Ascription 4 Agent's Beliefs All true Mixed All false 2 Figure 6: Boxplots of participants agreement rating with the knowledge that ascription in the AllTrue, Mixed and AllFalse conditions. References Cremers, A. and Chemla, E. (2016). A psycholinguistic study of the exhaustive readings of embedded questions. Journal of Semantics. George, B. R. (2011). Question Embedding and the Semantics of Answers. PhD thesis, University of California, Los Angeles. George, B. R. (2013). Knowing- wh, mention-some readings, and nonreducibility. Thought: A Journal of Philosophy, 2:166 177. Goldman, A. I. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. The Journal of Philosophy, pages 771 791. Grice, H. P. (1975). Logic and conversation. In Cole, P. and Morgan, J. L., editors, Syntax and semantics, volume 3. New York: Academic Press. Spector, B. (2005). Exhaustive interpretations: what to say and what not to say. presented at the LSA workshop on Context and Content. 14