The Reality of Vagueness

Similar documents
George Levine, Darwin the Writer, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, 272 pp.

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

CONTINGENCY AND TIME. Gal YEHEZKEL

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Peircean concept of sign. How many concepts of normative sign are needed. How to clarify the meaning of the Peircean concept of sign?

Challenging Form. Experimental Film & New Media

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

138 Great Problems in Philosophy and Physics - Solved? Chapter 11. Meaning. This chapter on the web informationphilosopher.com/knowledge/meaning

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

Trying Not to Try: The Art and Science of Spontaneity by Edward Slingerland (review)

Slide 1. Slide 2. Slide 3 Historical Development. Formalism. EH 4301 Spring 2011

Introduction to Postmodernism

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

CHAPTER SEVEN CONCLUSION

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Modernism s

Scientific Philosophy

Summary. Key words: identity, temporality, epiphany, subjectivity, sensorial, narrative discourse, sublime, compensatory world, mythos

On Meaning. language to establish several definitions. We then examine the theories of meaning

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Tradition and the Individual Poem: An Inquiry into Anthologies (review)

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Examiners report 2014

CRITICAL THEORY BEYOND NEGATIVITY

Aaron Preston (ed.) Analytic Philosophy: An Interpretive History [Book review]

RESEMBLANCE IN DAVID HUME S TREATISE Ezio Di Nucci

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

Reality According to Language and Concepts Ben G. Yacobi *

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Renaissance Old Masters and Modernist Art History-Writing

7. This composition is an infinite configuration, which, in our own contemporary artistic context, is a generic totality.

The Ancient Philosophers: What is philosophy?

Narrative Case Study Research

Revitalising Old Thoughts: Class diagrams in light of the early Wittgenstein

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Examination papers and Examiners reports E045. Moderns. Examination paper

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

DEPARTMENT OF ENGLISH CENTRAL UNIVERSITY OF JAMMU

FORUM: QUALITATIVE SOCIAL RESEARCH SOZIALFORSCHUNG

By submitting this essay, I attest that it is my own work, completed in accordance with University regulations. Caroline Sydney

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

Care of the self: An Interview with Alexander Nehamas

Lithuanian Philosophy in Exile

Foundations in Data Semantics. Chapter 4

The Sensory Basis of Historical Analysis: A Reply to Post-Structuralism ERIC KAUFMANN

Owen Barfield. Romanticism Comes of Age and Speaker s Meaning. The Barfield Press, 2007.

Film-Philosophy

Credibility and the Continuing Struggle to Find Truth. We consume a great amount of information in our day-to-day lives, whether it is

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

ENGL204: Essay Prompts and Self-Grading Rubric

Role of Form and Structure in Adding Meaning to a Piece of Literature

Course Syllabus. Professor Contact Information. Office Location JO Office Hours T 10:00-11:30

Hamletmachine: The Objective Real and the Subjective Fantasy. Heiner Mueller s play Hamletmachine focuses on Shakespeare s Hamlet,

On Recanati s Mental Files

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

1000 Words is Nothing: The Photographic Present in Relation to Informational Extraction

The Question of Equilibrium in Human Action and the Everyday Paradox of Rationality

School of Philosophical & Anthropological Studies

Issue 5, Summer Published by the Durham University Undergraduate Philosophy Society

Université Libre de Bruxelles

The concept of Latin American Art is obsolete. It is similar to the concept at the origin

Modernism. Suhan Poovaiah, Carolyn Malsawmtluangi & Arjun Prakash PG Dept. of English, St. Philomena s College (Autonomous) Mysore

Spatial Formations. Installation Art between Image and Stage.

A RE-INTERPRETATION OF ARTISTIC MODERNISM WITH EMPHASIS ON KANT AND NEWMAN DANNY SHORKEND

THE DIFFERENT LANGUAGES OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH

ON T HE DIFFERENCE BET WEEN ART IST IC RESEARCH AND ART IST IC PRAC T ICE

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

2 nd Grade Visual Arts Curriculum Essentials Document

Mass Communication Theory

Spring 2014 Department of Philosophy Graduate Course Descriptions

International Seminar. Creation, Publishing and Criticism: Galician and Irish Women Poets. Women, Poetry and Criticism: The Role of the Critic Today

J D H L S Journal of D. H. Lawrence Studies

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

WILLIAM JAMES STUDIES VOLUME 13 NUMBER 2 FALL 2017 PP

EXPERTS ARE PUZZLED. by LAURA RIDING

September 12. Modern. Andrew Goldstone Ian Bignall

Virginia English 12, Semester A

David Anton Spurr. Published by University of Michigan Press. For additional information about this book. Accessed 13 Jun :25 GMT

School of Undergraduate Studies Ambedkar University Delhi

UFS QWAQWA ENGLISH HONOURS COURSES: 2017

Towards a Methodology of Artistic Research. Nov 22nd

Transcription:

The Reality of Vagueness Luke Mueller Journal of Modern Literature, Volume 40, Number 4, Summer 2017, pp. 190-195 (Review) Published by Indiana University Press For additional information about this article https://muse.jhu.edu/article/671617 Access provided by Villanova University (3 Nov 2017 17:36 GMT)

The Reality of Vagueness Luke Mueller Megan Quigley. Modernist Fiction and Vagueness: Philosophy, Form, and Language. New York: Cambridge UP, 2015. xiv, 228 pp. $95.00 cloth; $76.00 ebook. In Modernist Fiction and Vagueness, Megan Quigley establishes the historical connections between vague language in the works of Henry James, Virginia Woolf, James Joyce, and T.S. Eliot and the philosophical problem of vagueness in early twentieth-century Anglo-American philosophy. She argues that these literary modernists saw vagueness not as a problem, but as a fundamental aspect of experience. They rejected philosophical attempts to create logically precise languages because logical precision fails to capture the complexity of concepts and experience. Quigley thus orients modernist aesthetics toward practical concerns: modernists sought to represent the vagueness of reality rather than simply detaching themselves from the real world. Quigley advocates Fuzzy Studies as a way to counteract recent empirical methods in literary criticism that tend to problematize vagueness. Keywords: philosophy / pragmatism / linguistic turn / realism Vagueness is surely an apt description for many readers encounters with modernist literature, and Megan Quigley embraces the term as a fundamental aspect of the period and its debates about language. Modernist Fiction and Vagueness reveals a historical moment when the vagueness of language presented itself as a crisis for philosophers who tried to clarify philosophical language with logical precision. Quigley argues that the experimental styles of Henry James, Virginia Woolf, and James Joyce developed as a critique of such logical precision and the authorities philosophical and social that enforce it. Luke Mueller (luke.mueller@tufts.edu) is a PhD candidate in the English department at Tufts University. His dissertation examines the aesthetics and politics of lying in modernist literature and philosophy, from Oscar Wilde and Friedrich Nietzsche to Samuel Beckett and Theodor W. Adorno. Journal of Modern Literature

191 She contends that while literary movements since New Criticism have sought aesthetic order in the chaos of modernist literature (and deconstruction has, conversely, sought chaos in aesthetic order), criticism should attend to vagueness as the best way to understand language and the world it describes. For Quigley, vagueness is not a problematic lack of order or a barrier to communication. At the heart of her argument is an insistence that modernists are realists whose close attention to the vagueness of concepts and objects aims to faithfully represent the world. Thus, Quigley s book is a timely history and polemic that pushes recent object-oriented criticism and empirically descriptive criticism back to the inevitably hazy philosophical and phenomenological questions of how subjects perceive and make sense of the real world. Modernist Fiction and Vagueness provides an excellent historical background of intellectual connections between Anglo-American philosophy and experimental literature in the early twentieth century. Despite what she claims are vague connections between literature and philosophy, Quigley provides convincing textual evidence for seeing experimental modernists working toward the same conclusions as pragmatic philosophers. Her book follows recent studies such as Lisi Schoenbach s Pragmatic Modernism and Liesl Olson s Modernism and the Ordinary that sought to recast modernists engagement with habit and ordinary life. Arguing against conceptions of modernists formal order and elitist detachment from the world, Quigley shows that modernist fiction writers, like pragmatists, made vague language and vague concepts the foundations of their experimentation. Quigley argues that Henry James, Woolf, and Joyce reflect William James s pragmatic solution to the problem of vague language. To make William James s version of pragmatism clear, she lays out philosophical responses to vagueness that center on a classical philosophical thought experiment called the sorites paradox, or the heap paradox. According to Quigley, this paradox, first proposed by Eubulides of Miletus in fourth century BCE Greece, asks us to consider how many grains of sand make a heap. Is one grain of sand a heap? Two? Three? If we keep adding grains of sand, how do we know at what point the sand constitutes a heap? Approached with mathematical logic, there seems to be no distinction between a heap of sand and a few grains. How, then, can we precisely define what a heap is? Quigley describes how the vagueness of words like heap proved problematic for many Western philosophers. On the one hand, logicians such as Gottlob Frege and Bertrand Russell tried to eliminate vague definitions by creating ideal forms of language. On the other hand, pragmatists such as Charles S. Peirce and William James recognized vagueness as a valuable tool for understanding language and discovering truth. But while Peirce thought that recognizing the vagueness of language would eventually lead to a clearer picture of precise objects, James maintained that because objects themselves were vague, vague language was perfectly suited to scientific investigations. Ludwig Wittgenstein takes both positions at different points in his career. His early Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus can be seen as an extension of the work of Frege and Russell in defining an ideal logical language, while his later work, especially the

192 posthumously published Philosophical Investigations, turns toward a pragmatic view of language that accepts vague conceptual boundaries. In Wittgenstein s later thought, vagueness is not a problem for philosophy at all; vague language can be used to convey definite understanding. Quigley shows the heap paradox at work in many forms throughout modernist philosophy and literature. For Russell, a smudged photograph is an imperfect likeness because it might equally represent Brown or Jones or Robinson (qtd. in Quigley 72), while Wittgenstein praises the blur and insists that the command, stand roughly there is fully comprehensible despite its vagueness (17). For William James, the stream of consciousness exemplifies the watery indivisibility of experience, where consciousness flows and thoughts cannot be clearly distinguished from memory and sensation. Images of water and waves proliferate in modernist literature, too: Woolf s The Waves (translated into French as Les Vagues), blurs boundaries between its characters, and when Joyce s Stephen Dedalus meets a prostitute, Stephen relives the fall of the mythical Icarus, becoming a fallen man, and dropping into water metaphors that begin to blur the solidity of his world. More fundamentally, metaphor itself offers a structure for vagueness because it constantly defers contact with solid things-in-themselves. Quigley s examples include metaphors such as the beast in Henry James s The Beast in the Jungle, a metaphor for the vague dread of catastrophe, and trees in Woolf s work, which might stand for solid objects if they weren t growing, collapsing and killing people, and transforming into chests of drawers and books. For Quigley s modernists, objectivity finds itself in a curious state of flux. Each chapter builds on personal connections between modernist writers and language philosophers. The opening chapter provides the strongest personal connection: that of brothers Henry and William James and their friend Peirce. By connecting Henry s aesthetic practice with his brother s pragmatism, Quigley challenges conceptions of Henry as an aesthete who resists modernity (24). Instead, she depicts him as an enthusiastic proponent of William s emphasis on vagueness, rejecting the latent idealism in the ostensibly practical concerns of Peirce and Gustave Flaubert. Quigley proposes that Henry s first novel, Watch and Ward (which the author later disowned as his first novel), is an aesthetic failure for the author because it is not vague enough. Instead of distancing themes of incest and pedophilia from its romantic content, Watch and Ward leaves these secret themes open from the beginning, thus it fails aesthetically. Quigley follows James s oeuvre as it grows steadily more vague. In The Beast in the Jungle, for example, she finds vagueness maintained to the end, as John Marcher s sense of foreboding can only be expressed in terms of the metaphor of the beast. Quigley claims that Marcher s character is strikingly similar to Charles S. Peirce, whose own beast, his vague ambition of promoting pragmaticism, caused his wife to leave him. While Quigley s desire to read certain biographical details of Peirce in James s story are novel, the importance of this vague resemblance is unclear. Still, her readings of James s stylistic and metaphorical affinities with his brother William provide strong evidence for seeing The Master in a more pragmatic light.

193 The second chapter traces the social connections between Virginia Woolf and Anglo-American language philosophers, arguing that Woolf s vague language rejects the precision and masculinity of Bertrand Russell s logical positivism. Quigley takes a comprehensive look at Woolf s oeuvre by analyzing her published fiction, manuscripts, diaries, essays, and even her 1937 BBC radio broadcast, Craftsmanship, in which Woolf advocates the multiplicity of linguistic meaning in opposition to Russell s attempts to refine it. These sources construct a Woolf whose vague, philosophical texts critique dominant patriarchal structures. Recognizing that critics have read Woolf as both realist and idealist, Quigley contends that Woolf s use of vague language allows her to be both: Woolf rejects idealist Truth while accepting a multiplicity of experienced truths reflected in language. Thus, Quigley emphasizes the affinities of Virginia Woolf s stylistic projects with those other opponents of Russell: Henry and William James. Yet, Quigley reaches an unsatisfying conclusion when she claims that The Waves, Woolf s vaguest novel, approaches solipsism by collapsing the distinctions between facts and subjective experiences. Such solipsism feels out of tune both with the political Woolf, who sees vagueness as a strength of language rather than a problem, and with the pragmatic Wittgenstein of Philosophical Investigations, who ardently refutes skepticism. In the third chapter, Quigley aims to contextualize James Joyce in the era s debates about language philosophy, rather than consigning him to the position of late-classicist or early-postmodernist. She tracks Joyce s developing anti-theological view of language throughout his work in the diminishing role of Stephen Dedalus s Aristotelian worldview, which holds that God s real name was God (qtd. in Quigley 134). Stephen s logical order gives way as he learns how language constructs different conceptions of God, the nation, and morality. Quigley aligns the Aristotelian worldview with Wittgenstein s early picture theory of language, and shows how Wittgenstein s later theory of language games and Joyce s dense wordplay express similar understandings of the function and possibilities of language. Although Joyce and Wittgenstein never met, Quigley connects them historically through C.K. Ogden. Ogden translated Wittgenstein s Tractatus into English and put its precise logic into practice by developing Basic English, a simplified language containing only 850 words. Later, Joyce invited Ogden to translate into Basic English the Anna Livia Plurabelle section of Finnegans Wake. The Wake, according to Quigley, is the culmination of Joyce s project to destabilize linguistic idealism by pushing vague language to its limits. Its celebration of vagueness makes it perhaps the most unlikely text to translate into Basic English, a language invented to eliminate vagueness, and Quigley intriguingly suggests that Joyce may have intended the translation to be an over-simplification, a foil for the complexity of language captured in his last work. The book concludes with a history of literary criticism and vagueness that centers on T.S. Eliot. While Eliot is often considered the coldly formalist and logically precise father of New Criticism, Quigley aims to reanimate (149) his work by showing a picture of his changing oeuvre and his complicated mixture of admiration and distaste for Russell s philosophy. She contends that Eliot saw

194 Russell s logical approach to language as an antidote to abstractions and vagueness in his era s literary criticism vagueness that Eliot associated primarily with the descent of Romanticism. Such concreteness accounts for Eliot s scientific metaphors (for example, the poet as a chemical catalyst in Tradition and the Individual Talent ) and his term objective correlative can be understood like a concept in a picture theory of language in which words align precisely with emotions and things. But while Eliot, like Russell, recognized as early as the 1920s that language resists scientific precision, Quigley emphasizes how in his later essays he transitions to a more pragmatic view that the wobbliness of words is not something to be deplored (qtd. in Quigley 157). Quigley argues that Eliot s early attempts to find reassuring order amid the chaos of modernity contribute to popular acceptance of modernist literature, even if his later criticism points more accurately to the favorability of literary vagueness. Quigley concludes with a plea for the use of Jeffrey Perl s concept Fuzzy Studies in literary criticism, taking vagueness as an object and method of inquiry rather than an epistemological problem to be overcome. While the New Critics eliminate vagueness to unify meaning and the poststructuralists see meaning as always already out of reach (169), Quigley advocates William James s pragmatic dictum that vague methods are ideally suited for investigating vague objects. She insists that analyzing language s vagueness can help readers to get somewhere (160). She criticizes recent social-scientific and cognitive approaches to literature and follows Perl in thinking that humanists should not subordinate their methods to those of scientists. (Ironically, she supports her argument for Fuzzy Studies in the humanities with evidence of the success of Fuzzy Studies in the sciences). Quigley suggests that prioritizing scientific methods in literary criticism risks ignoring the importance of context and all its difficulties. This discussion of Fuzzy Studies is intriguing, but may leave readers with many questions. If literary criticism is to get us somewhere, where would that be? What pragmatic results follow from realistic representation? How could these results be pragmatic but not utilitarian? Quigley does not answer these questions. It is somewhat troubling that she finds it necessary to take sides against precision a tool with its own pragmatic applications, and one that Quigley would admit Eliot employed successfully. The power of Fuzzy Studies in hard sciences seems proof that vagueness and precision are not mutually exclusive. Recently, Heather Love has provocatively suggested that literature might benefit from including both empirical and interpretive methods, which she calls thin description and thick description, following anthropologist Clifford Geertz (Love 430). Such a catholic view opens critical possibilities that include attention to vagueness without problematizing precision. Quigley maintains the ethical commitments to reality and complexity that her focal modernist writers and philosophers practiced, noting that Woolf saw patriarchal domination in Russell s logical precision and Joyce may have seen in Basic English the demands of global commerce and the domination of British culture. But these authors certainly retained commitments to accurate description and historical detail. In the end,

195 Quigley successfully posits vagueness as a crucial question for modernist criticism, challenging her readers to read textual openness and multiplicity as an extension of the real world rather than an epistemological problem. Love, Heather. Close Reading and Thin Description. Public Culture 25.3 71 (2013): 401 434. Web. 16 June 2015.