Cybernetics, Virtue Ethics and Design

Similar documents
The ethics of ethics and the ethics of architecture Sweeting, Ben

Kent Academic Repository

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis


UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

II. Aristotle or Nietzsche? III. MacIntyre s History, In Brief. IV. MacIntyre s Three-Stage Account of Virtue

Normative and Positive Economics

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Matching Bricolage and Hermeneutics: A theoretical patchwork in progress

Architecture is epistemologically

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Can Art for Art s Sake Imply Ethics? Henry James and David Jones

Assistant Professor in Philosophy, Cornell University (reappointed in 1969 to second 3-year term, resigned in 1970).

Capstone Design Project Sample

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Values, Virtue, and the Ethical Sportsman by Gregory Gauthier

MacIntyre, Virtue, and Liberalism: a Response to Schneewind. A thesis presented to. the faculty of

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Aristotle on the Human Good

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

A (Cybernetic) Musing: Design and Cybernetics. Ranulph Glanville

1) Three summaries (2-3 pages; pick three out of the following four): due: 9/9 5% due: 9/16 5% due: 9/23 5% due: 9/30 5%

Valuable Particulars

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

The Doctrine of the Mean

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Foucault's Archaeological method

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

My thesis is that not only the written symbols and spoken sounds are different, but also the affections of the soul (as Aristotle called them).

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

The Cybernetics of Value and the Value of Cybernetics. The Art of Invariance and the Invariance of Art. Et Cetera

Watcharabon Buddharaksa. The University of York. RCAPS Working Paper No January 2011

observation and conceptual interpretation

Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order

An essay on Alasdair MacIntyre s Relativism. Power and Philosophy

Creative Arts Education: Rationale and Description

GRADUATE SEMINARS

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

Hoyningen Symposium Systematicity: The Nature of Science

History Admissions Assessment Specimen Paper Section 1: explained answers

Loughborough University Institutional Repository. This item was submitted to Loughborough University's Institutional Repository by the/an author.

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Gender, the Family and 'The German Ideology'

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Thai Architecture in Anthropological Perspective

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

Song Wei, Qin Mingli. Dalian University of Technology

Philosophical foundations for a zigzag theory structure

Integration, Ambivalence, and Mental Conflict

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

The study of design problem in design thinking

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Moral Judgment and Emotions

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Dream - Writing. StarShip WordSmith Supporting Narrative Text for the Companion Video

UPHEAVALS OF THOUGHT The Intelligence of Emotions

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

MAIN THEORETICAL PERSPECTIVES IN CONTEMPORARY SOCIOLOGY

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

0:24 Arthur Holmes (AH): Aristotle s ethics 2:18 AH: 2:43 AH: 4:14 AH: 5:34 AH: capacity 7:05 AH:

Charles Taylor s Langue/Parole and Alasdair MacIntyre s Networks of Giving and Receiving as a Foundation for a Positive Anti-Atomist Political Theory

African Fractals Ron Eglash

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

Anna Carabelli. Anna Carabelli. Università del Piemonte Orientale, Italy 1

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Critical interpretive synthesis: what it is and why it is needed. Mary Dixon-Woods Department of Health Sciences University of Leicester

Ed. Carroll Moulton. Vol. 1. New York: Charles Scribner's Sons, p COPYRIGHT 1998 Charles Scribner's Sons, COPYRIGHT 2007 Gale

Transcription:

Cybernetics, Virtue Ethics and Design Working Paper Ben Sweeting Senior Lecturer University of Brighton Introduction In this paper I speak directly to the subject matter of this conference: to its theme of flourishing, and to the subject areas of systems thinking and design that this conference series as a whole seeks to bring together. The conference theme of flourishing is a direct reference to ethics, and in particular the Nicomachean Ethics of Aristotle. There has been a revival of interest in this in recent decades under the heading of virtue ethics. Aristotle defined the good as that at which all things aim, and so in terms of goals and purpose. He described the goal of human life in terms eudemonia, which is usually translated as either human flourishing or the good life. There is a clear connection between this conception of ethics in terms of purpose and both design and systems. Design is an explicitly purposeful activity, which can be understood as the attempt to devise courses of action aimed at changing existing situations into preferred ones (Simon, 1969/1996, p. 111). Purpose is of central concern for how we understand systems, most explicitly in cybernetics. The aim of this paper is to make explicit some of the deep interconnections between these three areas in terms of the theme of purpose, and to suggest areas of common concern where they might lend support to each other. In order to do this within the scope of this paper, I focus on a specific point of reference in each of the three areas: to Alasdair MacIntyre s (1981/1985) After Virtue, Dalibor Vesely s (1985, 2004, 2010) account of architecture, and to the debate around Rosenblueth, Wiener and Bigelow s (1943) protocybernetic paper. The failure of the enlightenment project of rationally justifying morality MacIntyre begins After Virtue with a metaphoric account of a world in which science has suffered a cataclysm: 1

Imagine that the natural sciences were to suffer the effects of a catastrophe. A series of environmental disasters are blamed by the general public on the scientists. Widespread riots occur, laboritaries are burnt down, physicists are lynched, books and instruments are destroyed. Finally a Know-Nothing political movement takes power and successfully abolishes science teaching in schools and universities, imprisoning and executing the remaining scientists. Later still there is a reaction against this destructive movement and enlightened people seek to revive science, although they have largely forgotten what it was. But all they posess are fragments: a knowledge of experiments detached from any knowledge of the theoretical context which gave them significance; parts of theories unrelated either to the other bits and pieces of theory which they possess or to experiment; instruments whose use has been forgotten; half-chapters from books, single pages from articles Adults argue with each other about the respective merits of relativity theory, evolutionary theory and phlogiston theory, although they possess only a very partial knowledge of each. Children learn by heart the surviving portions of the periodic table and recite as incantations some of the theorems of Euclid. (MacIntyre, 1981/1985, p. 1) According to MacIntyre, something like this has happened in ethics over the last centuries. The enlightenment attempt to provide a rational basis for morality has resulted in the bifurcation of the social world into the realm of organization, in which ends are taken as given and not available for scrutiny, and the realm of the personal, in which debates over values are central but there is no available social resolution. We have fragments of theories but these are drawn from different cultures and there is no coherence as to how they relate. Debates remain unresolvable and our moral reasoning tends to take the form of assertion and counter assertion. For MacIntyre, the failure of the enlightenment project to rationally justify morality was inevitable, not because ethics necessarily involves arbitrariness but because of the specific culture in which this project was carried out, and its conception of what would count as rational. This involved both the adoption of scientific forms of language, which were descriptive and excluded notions of purpose, and the simultaneous fragmentation of religious and scholastic traditions. This process has left us with an incomplete moral scheme. We have an analysis of ourselves as we are now, and various moral precepts and rules, but without any idea of our goal or telos eudemonia, the good life, or human flourishing. Architecture and the end of the cosmological tradition There are parallels between the enlightenment s legacy in ethics, as described by MacIntyre, and its affect on the design discipline of architecture, as described by Dalibor Vesely. The enlightenment saw the dissiptation of architecture s cosmological tradition, and attempts to design architecture rationally in various ways, such as the use of history as a reference point: The transformation of cosmological into astronomical thinking, where the unity of celestial and terrestrial phenomena was reduced to a narrow domain of celestial mechanics (astrophysics), lost its ability to serve as a reference for the phenomena on earth, where architecture itself is situated. The loss of cosmological reference was gradually replaced by 2

reference to history, focused primarily on the question of origins (from Solomon s temple to the primitive hut). The foundational role of classical orders was replaced by historical precedents, genealogies, character and finally by style. (Fischer von Erlach, Boffrand, J.F. Blondel, et al.) The reference to history was inevitably more relative than cosmology. This led to the well known historical arbitrariness of the 19c and as a result to a search for a new objectivity of architectural principles and order. (Vesely, 2010, p. 4) Vesely describes this as leading to what he characterizes as our age of divided representation (Vesely, 2004), a split between technical rationality on the one hand and personal visions on the other, much as in MacIntyre s account. This split between the rational/ objective and the aesthetic/ subjective runs deep in our culture. Yet, as Vesely points out, these two poles are not in opposition, as we often assume, but part of the same problematic settlement: Science, technology and aesthetics belong together. The development of scientific objectivity depends, as we have already seen, on the role of the subject responsible for the project of science. In other words, the more objective reality becomes, the more subjective must be the position of man, because in modern science he encounters by definition, as it were, only his own projection of reality. In conclusion, it is possible to say that objectivity in science is in fact the product of the subjectivity of man. (Vesely, 1985, p. 26) Vesely and others, such as Christian Norberg-Schulz (1971, 1980) whose name is on the door of the room in which I am speaking, have attempted to heal this divide using phenomenology to recover an understanding of the cosmological structure of space in a way that is accessible in the present. This position, however, has been in retreat in recent years within architectural discourse. Cybernetics and the reintroduction of purpose into scientific discourse MacIntyre and Vesely describe similar historical processes: the attempt to replace traditional forms of enquiry with rational justification; the failure of this to provide a stable point of reference; and a resulting split between the rational and personal. In each of their accounts we might see the development of modern science as the villain of the piece, with its rejection of final causes in favour of a linear and mechanistic account of causality. It was this linear causality that risked obfuscating what was special about design in the design methods movement (Gedenryd, 1998). Yet, this linear causality can be understood as also limiting the scope of science. It is in conflict with many contemporary developments, such as the study of complexity or emergence and the convergence between science and design that has taken place in recent decades (Jonas, 2014). 3

Cybernetics is notable for reintroducing purpose as a subject within scientific discourse, most notably in the proto-cybernetic paper of Arturo Rosenblueth, Norbert Wiener and Julian Bigelow (1943). Heinz von Foerster has summarised cybernetics in explicitly Aristotelian terms: we are all cyberneticians (whether or not we call ourselves such) whenever we justify our actions without using the words because of, or à cause de, but with the phrase in English in order to, which in French is much more Aristotelian, à fin de (von Foerster, 1990/2003, p. 298) Cybernetics bypasses problems with final causes occurring after the events they cause through its circular understanding of causality (Stewart, 1959/2000) and emphasises rather than hides the agency and purposes of the scientific observer. Internal and external goals As Rosenblueth et al. (1943) showed, the circularity of a cybernetic system allows a purpose to be pursued. Rosenblueth et al. defined purpose as follows: The term purposeful is meant to denote that the act or behaviour may be interpreted as directed to the attainment of a goal i.e., to a final condition in which the behaving object reaches a definite correlation in time or in space with respect to another object or event. (Rosenblueth, et al., 1943, p. 18) The eponymous example of cybernetics is steering a ship, a clearly goal directed activity. The goal, however, is not necessarily best understood as the port towards which the ship is heading. As Richard Taylor (1950) argues, Rosenblueth et al. s conception of purpose as striving towards a definite final condition does not account for vague or unsuccessful activities that are still goal-directed although no goal exists, such as a man groping about in the dark for matches which are not there, but which he erroneously believes to be near at hand or how the alchemist can seek the philosopher s stone, the knight can seek the Holy Grail (p. 329). In these cases, and also in the case of the ship, we do not have to identify the goal of the system in terms of something external to it, such as the port. We can instead understand the goal as an internal quality of the system, that of being on course for the port as a set of relations between steersman, sea, rudder and the direction in which the port is believed to lie. This removes the problem of the end goal being ambiguous, unknown or absent, such as in the examples Taylor cites. It also removes the risk that cybernetics understanding of teleology is interpreted in a deterministic way the maintenance of the internal goal of being on course allows the steersman not just to continue his or her journey to a port but also to change course and to explore as yet unknown destinations. This is the sense in which Gordon Pask speaks of machines with underspecified goals (Bateson, 1972/2005); in which design is a cybernetic activity, oriented towards the new (Glanville, 2007; Sweeting, 2016a); and in which Andrew Pickering (2010) characterises cybernetics as a form of forward looking search. It follows that homeostasis, the process of 4

maintaining a goal state, does not necessarily imply the status quo. The maintenance of the internal goals of a system is a requirement for it being able to change its external goals. Internal goals (or goods) are central to the positive part of MacIntyre s account, where he tries to recover something of the Aristotelian conception of ethics: Consider the example of a highly intelligent seven-year-old child whom I wish to teach to play chess, although the child has no particular desire to learn the game. The child does however have a very strong desire for candy and little chance of obtaining it. I therefore tell the child that if the child will play chess with me once a week I will give the child 50 cents worth of candy; moreover I tell the child that will always play in such a way that it will be difficult, but not impossible, for the child to win and that, if the child wins, the child will receive an extra 50 cents worth of candy. Thus motivated the child plays and plays to win. Notice however that, so long as it is the candy alone which provides the child with a good reason for playing chess, the child has no reason not to cheat and every reason to cheat, provided he or she can do so successfully. But, so we may hope, there will come a time when the child will find in those goods specific to chess, in the achievement of a certain highly particular kind of analytical skill, strategic imagination and competitive intensity, a new set of reasons, reasons now not just for winning on a particular occasion, but for trying to excel in whatever way the game of chess demands. (MacIntyre, 1981/1985, p. 188) The contrast between external and internal goods is not an either/ or choice, and external goods can follow from the pursuit of internal ones. However, it is a problem when external goals dominate internal ones. If our actions are motivated only by goods external to them, potentially any means can be justified. This includes such obvious external goals as wealth, success or fame but also apparently benevolent goals where these are seen as external to the practice of seeking them, such as in consequentialist ethical frameworks. MacIntyre s (1981/1985) project is to reconstruct the idea of the good life or human flourishing as a goal internal to our lives, drawing on social roles and practices that have internal goods. He describes the good life as a form of quest (p. 219) and goes on to define it self-referentially: the good life for man is the life spent in seeking the good life for man (p. 219). The pursuit of internal goals is also central to design. Staying with the example of architecture, there is a significant difference between those buildings that have been designed and constructed with care for their qualities as pieces of architecture, such as their spatiality or craftsmanship, and those that have been built with a focus on external goals, such as profit. Moreover, designers cannot simply pursue fixed external goals when they are designing because they cannot exhaustively analyse the situation at the outset (Rittel & Webber, 1973). Rather, designers nurture the internal goals of design activity, revising the criteria and goals of the project as they do so. In this they are much like the steersman, adjusting his or her course to suit changes in the environment or to explore new possibilities not seen at the start of the journey. 5

Conclusion Cybernetics, design and virtue ethics are each concerned with similar questions regarding purpose and the relation of goals to the actions that pursue them. If we hold with the historical account I have sketched, drawing on MacIntyre and Vesely, then we might even say they are concerned with the same questions. There are several ways in which these areas might usefully support or critique each other. For instance: MacIntyre's discussion of social practices, which is a central but underdeveloped part of his (1981/1985) account, may benefit from cybernetic discussions of internal and external goals (Sweeting, 2015). Although he does not frame it in these terms, Ranulph Glanville s (2004) account of cybernetics and ethics takes the form of a series of virtues that enable and cultivate cybernetic forms of practice, such as design. MacIntyre s (1981/1985) self-referential definition of the good life may find support in cybernetic understanding of circularity, recursion and reflexivity and in the ethical reflections of second-order cybernetics, where cybernetics is applied to itself (e.g. Glanville, 2004; Mead, 1968; Poerksen, 2011; Sweeting, 2016b; von Foerster, 1990/2003). Virtue ethics seems compatible with design (Jonas, 2006) in a way that consequentialism and deontology are not, given their dependence on forms of reasoning (such as predefined rules and optimisation) that clash with what is special about design. Cybernetics may be one way to develop this connection. Developing these points of connection can help us understand how flourishing may be put forward as a goal, as has been proposed by many participants during this conference. For instance, whenever we speak about flourishing we must take care that we do not advocate it merely as an external goal as something to be maximized by whatever means available. Reference List Bateson, M. C. (2005). Our own metaphor: A personal account of a conference on the effects of conscious purpose on human adaptation. Cresskill, NJ: Hampton Press. (Original work published: 1972). Gedenryd, H. (1998). How designers work: Making sense of authentic cognitive activities. Lund University Cognitive Studies, 75. Retrieved from http://lup.lub.lu.se/record/18828/file/1484253.pdf Glanville, R. (2004). Desirable Ethics. Cybernetics and Human Knowing, 11(2), 77-88. Retrieved from http://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/imp/chk/2004/00000011/00000002/art00007 Glanville, R. (2007). Try again. Fail again. Fail better: The cybernetics in design and the design in cybernetics. Kybernetes, 36(9/10), 1173-1206. doi: 10.1108/03684920710827238 Jonas, W. (2006). A special moral code for design? Design Philosophy Papers, 4(2), 117-132. doi: 10.2752/144871306X13966268131596 Jonas, W. (2014). The strengths / limits of systems thinking denote the strengths / limits of practicebased design research. FORMakademisk, 7(4). doi: 10.7577/formakademisk.789 MacIntyre, A. (1985). After virtue: A study in moral theory (2nd corrected ed.). London: Duckworth. (Original work published: 1981). 6

Mead, M. (1968). The cybernetics of cybernetics. In H. von Foerster, J. D. White, L. J. Peterson & J. K. Russell (Eds.), Purposive Systems (pp. 1-11). New York, NY: Spartan Books. Norberg-Schulz, C. (1971). Existence, space and architecture. London: Studio Vista. Norberg-Schulz, C. (1980). Genius loci: Towards a phenomenology of architecture. London: Academy Editions. Pickering, A. (2010). The cybernetic brain: Sketches of another future. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press. Poerksen, B. (2011). Ethics of enabling ethics. Cybernetics & Human Knowing, 18(3-4), 143-149. Retrieved from http://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/imp/chk/2011/00000018/f0020003/art00013 Rittel, H., & Webber, M. (1973). Dilemmas in a general theory of planning. Policy Sciences, 4, 155-169. Rosenblueth, A., Wiener, N., & Bigelow, J. (1943). Behavior, purpose and teleology. Philosophy of Science, 10(1), 18-24. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/184878 Simon, H. A. (1996). The sciences of the artificial (3rd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Retrieved from http://m.friendfeed-media.com/092e5a73c91e0838eeb11e0fe90edaf9e9afc065 (Original work published: 1969). Stewart, D. J. (2000). An essay on the origins of cybernetics. [Originally part of PhD thesis, University of Bristol, Bristol, 1959]. Retrieved from http://www.hfr.org.uk/cyberneticspages/origins.htm Sweeting, B. (2015). Cybernetics of practice. Kybernetes, 44(8/9), 1397-1405. doi: 10.1108/K-11-2014-0239 Sweeting, B. (2016a). Design research as a variety of second-order cybernetic practice. Constructivist Foundations, 11(3), 572-579. Retrieved from http://www.univie.ac.at/constructivism/journal/11/3/572.sweeting Sweeting, B. (2016b). The ethics of ethics and the ethics of architecture. In P. Jones (Ed.), Proceedings of Relating Systems Thinking and Design (RSD5) 2016 Symposium. 13-15 October. Taylor, R. (1950). Purposeful and non-purposeful behavior: A rejoinder. Philosophy of Science, 17(4), 327-332. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/185932 Vesely, D. (1985). Architecture and the conlfict of representation. AA Files, 8, 21-38. Retrieved from http://www.jstor.org/stable/29543434 Vesely, D. (2004). Architecture in the age of divided representation: The question of creativity in the shadow of production. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Vesely, D. (2010, June). The latent ground of the natural world: Introduction to the communicative role of architecture. Paper presented at The Communicative Role of Architecture, Leicester School of Architecture, De Montfort University, Leicester, UK. von Foerster, H. (2003). Ethics and second-order cybernetics. In Understanding understanding: Essays on cybernetics and cognition (pp. 287-304). New York, NY: Springer-Verlag. 7