Introduction: From Practice to Results in Mathematics and Logic

Similar documents
RETHINKING SCIENCE AFTER THE PRACTICE TURN

PHIL/HPS Philosophy of Science Fall 2014


Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

Mathematical Practice and Naturalist Epistemology: Structures with Potential for Interaction

Cultural History of Mathematics

IS SCIENCE PROGRESSIVE?

Constructive mathematics and philosophy of mathematics

VISUALISATION AND PROOF: A BRIEF SURVEY

Envisioning Transformations The Practice of Topology

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

CRITIQUE OF PARSONS AND MERTON

INTUITION IN SCIENCE AND MATHEMATICS

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

PHILOSOPH ICAL PERSPECTI VES ON PROOF IN MATHEMATI CS EDUCATION

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

Modern Logic Volume 8, Number 1/2 (January 1998 April 2000), pp

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Relativism and the Social Construction of Science: Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

observation and conceptual interpretation

Proof in Mathematics Education

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

COMPUTER ENGINEERING SERIES

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

Normal Science and Normal Kuhn.

INTRODUCTION TO AXIOMATIC SET THEORY

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

EPISTEMOLOGY, METHODOLOGY, AND THE SOCIAL SCIENCES

The contribution of material culture studies to design

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Chapter 1 Overview of Music Theories

Arnold I. Davidson, Frédéric Gros (eds.), Foucault, Wittgenstein: de possibles rencontres (Éditions Kimé, 2011), ISBN:

Is There Anything Wrong with Thomas Kuhn? Markus Arnold, University of Klagenfurt

Mathematical Principles of Fuzzy Logic

Breger and myself, Carlo Cellucci, Donald Gillies, Penelope Maddy, Paolo Mancosu, François De Gandt, Jaakko Hintikka, Madeline Muntersbjorn, Carl

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order

Thomas Kuhn s Concept of Incommensurability and the Stegmüller/Sneed Program as a Formal Approach to that Concept

INTERNATIONAL CONFERENCE ON ENGINEERING DESIGN ICED 05 MELBOURNE, AUGUST 15-18, 2005 GENERAL DESIGN THEORY AND GENETIC EPISTEMOLOGY

Aaron Preston (ed.) Analytic Philosophy: An Interpretive History [Book review]

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Giuliana Garzone and Peter Mead

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

The Barrier View: Rejecting Part of Kuhn s Work to Further It. Thomas S. Kuhn s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, published in 1962, spawned

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Hoyningen Symposium Systematicity: The Nature of Science

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Citation Analysis in Research Evaluation

Poznań, July Magdalena Zabielska

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Introduction: Mills today

Capstone Design Project Sample

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Review of Krzysztof Brzechczyn, Idealization XIII: Modeling in History

SYNTAX AND MEANING Luis Radford Université Laurentienne, Ontario, Canada

The Influence of Chinese and Western Culture on English-Chinese Translation

Advanced Placement English Language and Composition

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

Book Review of Rosenhouse, The Monty Hall Problem. Leslie Burkholder 1

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Mitchell ABOULAFIA, Transcendence. On selfdetermination

The Debate on Research in the Arts

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

French theories in IS research : An exploratory study on ICIS, AMCIS and MISQ

Building blocks of a legal system. Comments on Summers Preadvies for the Vereniging voor Wijsbegeerte van het Recht

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases as bibliographies become shorter

BOOK REVIEW. William W. Davis

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

*** At the end of his (2012), Solomon Feferman commits himself to a formalisability thesis about mathematical proofs that he characterises as follows:

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Managing cognitive aspects of conceptual modeling and design in the arrow diagram logic framework: A mathematician s view 1

Journey through Mathematics

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

Methods, Topics, and Trends in Recent Business History Scholarship

Visualisation and proof: a brief survey of philosophical perspectives

Publications des Archives Henri-Poincaré Publications of the Henri Poincaré Archives

Problem Books in Mathematics

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Philosophy of Economics

The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Philosophy of Development

Normative and Positive Economics

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

Critical Spatial Practice Jane Rendell

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

Transcription:

Philosophia Scientiæ Travaux d'histoire et de philosophie des sciences 16-1 2012 From Practice to Results in Logic and Mathematics Introduction: From Practice to Results in Mathematics and Logic Valeria Giardino, Amirouche Moktefi, Sandra Mols and Jean Paul Van Bendegem Publisher Editions Kimé Electronic version URL: http:// philosophiascientiae.revues.org/706 DOI: 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.706 ISSN: 1775-4283 Printed version Date of publication: 1 avril 2012 Number of pages: 5-11 ISBN: 978-2-84174-581-4 ISSN: 1281-2463 Electronic reference Valeria Giardino, Amirouche Moktefi, Sandra Mols and Jean Paul Van Bendegem, «Introduction: From Practice to Results in Mathematics and Logic», Philosophia Scientiæ [Online], 16-1 2012, Online since 01 April 2015, connection on 05 October 2016. URL : http://philosophiascientiae.revues.org/706 ; DOI : 10.4000/philosophiascientiae.706 The text is a facsimile of the print edition. Tous droits réservés

Introduction: From Practice to Results in Mathematics and Logic Valeria Giardino Institut Jean Nicod (CNRS EHESS-ENS), Paris (France) & Universidad de Sevilla (Spain) Amirouche Moktefi IRIST (EA 3424), Université de Strasbourg & LHSP Archives H. Poincaré (UMR 7117), CNRS Université de Lorraine (France) Sandra Mols LHSP Archives H. Poincaré (UMR 7117), CNRS Université de Lorraine (France) Jean Paul Van Bendegem CLWF, Center for Logic and Philosophy of Science, Vrije Universiteit Brussel (Belgium) 1 Mathematical practice: a short overview This volume is a collection of essays that discuss the relationships between the practices deployed by logicians and mathematicians, either as individuals or as members of research communities, and the results from their research. We are interested in exploring the concept of practices in the formal sciences. Though common in the history, philosophy and sociology of science, this concept has surprisingly thus far been little reflected upon in logic and mathematics. Yet, such practice-based approach would be most crucial for a critical study of these fields. Indeed, in their daily work, mathematicians and logicians do deploy sets of practices, some intimately tied to mathematics and logic as such and others relating rather to material, theoretical, intellectual and social issues in their Philosophia Scientiæ, 16 (1), 2012, 5 11.

6 Valeria Giardino et al. environments. For these reasons, this volume pertains to the interdisciplinary trend that has gained more and more interest in recent years, and which is known as the philosophy of mathematical practice. To give an all too short account of this recent approach, one might look for its roots in Imre Lakatos s 1976 seminal Proofs and Refutations [Lakatos 1976], a work that was in part inspired by Georg Polya s How to Solve It [Polya 1945] which discusses heuristics and problem-solving techniques in an educational setting. Later on, Philip Kitcher proposed in his book The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge [Kitcher 1985] a more or less formal model of how mathematics as an activity can be described. Several authors embraced that trend, as is shown in subsequent volumes that made connections between philosophy and history of mathematics, as did Thomas Tymoczko s New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics [Tymoczko 1986] and, later and more explicitly, Bill Aspray and Philip Kitcher s History and Philosophy of Modern Mathematics [Aspray & Kitcher 1988]. It must be said here that historians of mathematics have long paid attention to practices and produced significant studies with often implicit, but also sometimes explicit, claims about their philosophical relevance. The above description may suggest a rather uniform approach to the study of mathematical practice, but such is not the case. In the introduction to The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice [Mancosu 2008], Paolo Mancosu identifies two main traditions. The first is the maverick tradition which remains close to the Lakatosian approach, while the second settles itself within the modern analytical tradition, namely the naturalizing programme that started with Williard Van Orman Quine, and where Penelope Maddy has played and still plays an important role. This is not yet the end of the story however. Independently of these developments in the philosophy of mathematics, but also partially inspired by Lakatos as well as Thomas Kuhn s The Structure of Scientific Revolutions [Kuhn 1962], some researchers developed a sociology of mathematics, where one of the major focuses was mathematical practice as a group or community phenomenon. Two works should be mentioned in this line: David Bloor s Knowledge and Social Imagery [Bloor 1976] and Sal Restivo s The Social Relations of Physics, Mysticism, and Mathematics [Restivo 1985]. In contrast with history and philosophy of mathematics, the sociological approach did not merge easily with the mentioned traditions, although some brave attempts in this direction should be noticed [Restivo, Van Bendegem, & Fischer 1993], [Rosental 2008], [Löwe & Müller 2010]. Plenty of reasons can be listed but surely one of the corner elements is the internal-external debate: does mathematics develop according to laws or patterns that are internal to mathematics, or do external elements contribute? One outcome of these discussions has been to draw the attention to other, so far neglected, areas where mathematics is involved, prominently mathe-

Introduction 7 matics education and ethnomathematics. In 2002, a conference was organized in Brussels where the organizers, Jean Paul Van Bendegem and Bart Van Kerkhove, tried to realize their ambition in bringing representatives of all these disciplines together. This conference has led to the 2007 Perspectives on Mathematical Practices, with the overambitious subtitle Bringing Together Philosophy of Mathematics, Sociology of Mathematics, and Mathematics Education [Van Kerkhove & Van Bendegem 2007]. Another important outcome from all these developments, overall, has been the confirmation of the rather heterogeneous character of this field, as can be seen in the recently founded Association for the Philosophy of Mathematical Practice (APMP) (see the website of the association at http://institucional.us.es/apmp/), wherein both of Mancosu s traditions are clearly present and at times happily interacting. More generally, so as to draw a complete picture of the philosophy of mathematical practice, it has to be noted that all of the above would have to be looked at from a wider perspective, in order to see how these developments relate to the whole domain of the philosophy of mathematics, including its mainstream sub-domain, the foundational studies of mathematics. In a sense this is a tension within the internal approach: even if one accepts that mathematics is subjected to something like an internal development, it will remain to find out how this development is best characterized. Such a complete picture will not be drawn here but will need to be clarified in the future. 2 Themes and issues in the philosophy of mathematical practice In the light of what has been said, how does the problem agenda of the philosophy of mathematical practice look like? The main focus will be on exploring the internal issues, while indicating along the way connections with external issues and themes. An elegant way to obtain some coherence in such an agenda is to look at the various levels where the practices are situated: macro-, mesoand micro-level, as a first rough classification. At the macro-level, the discussion is about the global development of mathematics. One specific question that arises is whether or not revolutions take place and, if so, of what kind. On this issue, the standard volume remains Donald Gillies s Revolutions in Mathematics [Gillies 1992]. Are there Kuhnian parallels to be drawn or does a philosophy of mathematical practice approach also confirm the special status of mathematics vis-à-vis the sciences? As has happened in post-kuhn philosophy of science, the sociological elements enter into the picture, as one asks why particular mathematical developments took place in their place and time. Rephrased, the issue is that of how well math-

8 Valeria Giardino et al. ematics is or is not closed off from the rest of society. The relevance of the educational and ethnomathematical dimensions is obvious at this level. At the meso-level, the concern is to deal with research programmes (traditions, styles, etc.). Are there such research programmes? How do they guide research, motivate people, and so forth? The educational dimension is present here as well but on a more internal level: how is the next generation of mathematicians initiated in a particular research programme? A lot of work has been done on this level and addressed features include the issues of being deemed, interesting, fruitful, provider of explanation, promising solutions, or indicative of heuristics. These are all features that are usually neglected in foundational studies. At the micro-level, the core theme is the nature of mathematical proof. Besides the notion of proof itself and its inner difficulties, there is a wealth of related themes to explore. A first group includes issues related to presentation concerning the (non-)formalized character of a proof, its (in-)formality, the use of diagrams and their status, and accessibility who is able to grasp the proof? and, perhaps most importantly, why is a proof convincing? A second group of themes concerns what accompanies proofs. Mathematicians perform experiments, but are such quotation marks necessary? Why (not)?; they crunch numbers in the hope of finding interesting patterns, performing inductive reasoning; they support their proofs by arguments, leading to the questions whether proofs themselves can be seen as a particular type of argument, and whether, fascinatingly, a rhetorics of mathematical texts is possible. Quite interestingly, at this latter micro-level, other fields and disciplines than history, philosophy and sociology, also contribute to the picture. Such is the case with cognitive psychology, crucial to understand reasoning processes as they take place in the human (social?) brain. Such is the case too with evolutionary biology and psychology, necessary to establish the roots and origins of mankind s number sense, if any. It is to be noted too that, at this micro-level, the impact of the particular tradition, whether maverick or naturalized, is not overwhelmingly present, making a close collaboration perfectly possible. More generally, there is one issue that is for sure: there is no shortage of themes to explore and problems to be solved when looking at the philosophy of mathematics from the standpoint of practices. The list of subjects that we presented above is not exhaustive and additional questions the use of computers in mathematics certainly being one of them are expected to be addressed by the (hopefully) growing and striving community of philosophers interested in this practice-based approach.

Introduction 9 3 The essays in this volume The essays in this volume are contributions to the philosophy of mathematical practice. Two kinds of papers are to be found. The first set of essays is more conceptual and theoretical, with authors discussing the notion of practice and its connections with concepts, understanding and representations. The second set of essays contains rather detailed analyses and discussions of case studies. In the first group of essays, first, as a general discussion, Mark Smith defends a conception of mathematical practice and mathematical subject matter that puts together inferential pluralism and a form of concept-realism. The second essay by Danielle Macbeth is a close examination of the relation between the practice of proving and understanding. Fully formalized mathematical proofs usually do not advance our mathematical understanding: does this mean that form does not correspond to content? In her view, to avoid such an opposition, it is necessary to develop a different notion of (formal) proof, and eighteenth-century algebraic proofs can provide an example of fully rigorous and fully content-filled mathematical proofs. The third essay, by Jessica Carter, is an analysis of the role of representations in mathematical proofs, illustrated by an example from contemporary mathematical practice where the value of an expression is found by gradually breaking it down into simpler parts. More generally, and referring to the Peircean terminology, she also discusses the role of icons and indices in such a practice. Finally, the fourth essay by Catarina Dutilh Novaes delineates a practice-based philosophy of logic and illustrates it by focusing on the role played by formal languages in logic. In her view, formal languages have an operative role; paper-and-pencil and hands-on technology trigger specific cognitive processes, which psychology discloses. In the second group of essays, the first three are analyses of case studies exploring specific mathematical practices. First, Daniele Molinini focuses on the explanatory character of Euler s proof of his Theorem, which, according to the author, is not recognized by Steiner s approach to mathematical explanation. Secondly, Irina Starikova shows how the representation of groups through graphs leads to a new conceptual perspective on the geometry of groups. Thirdly, Baptiste Mélès defends the thesis that the concepts of paradigm and thematization used by Jean Cavaillès find an illustration and a formalization in category theory and a precedent in the Hegelian dialectic. In the fourth and last essay, Vincent Ardourel explores possible interactions between mathematics and physics, by focusing on instances of practices of mathematical research that consist in reformulating constructively physical theories. All in all, the essays in this volume give an idea of how many different routes can be taken by the investigation on the mathematical and logical practices. Although one might wish the opposite, the general impression is that it is not likely that a far-reaching integration of the internal and external viewpoints may occur in the very near future. Nevertheless, and following the

10 Valeria Giardino et al. recent creation of the APMP, one may hope that, at the very least, historians and philosophers of mathematics and logic may have found one another, not that it would mean that the heterogeneity of this field of research may not be an issue to be dealt with. Acknowledgments We want to thank the PratiScienS group and the MSH-Lorraine staff for their help for the organisation of the conference that has inspired this volume. Thanks are also due to the authors, the reviewers and the proof-readers who helped us all along the preparation of this volume. Lastly, we also warmly thank Sandrine Avril and Manuel Rebuschi for their help and support. Bibliography Aspray, William & Kitcher, Philip (eds.) 1988 History and Philosophy of Modern Mathematics, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. Bloor, David 1976 Knowledge and Social Imagery, London: Routledge & K. Paul. Gillies, Donald (ed.) 1992 Revolutions in Mathematics, Oxford: Clarendon Press. Kitcher, Philip 1985 The Nature of Mathematical Knowledge, New York: Oxford University Press. Kuhn, Thomas 1962 The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Lakatos, Imre 1976 Proofs and Refutations, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Löwe, Benedikt & Müller, Thomas (eds.) 2010 Philosophy of Mathematics: Sociological Aspects and Mathematical Practice, London: College Publications. Mancosu, Paolo (ed.) 2008 The Philosophy of Mathematical Practice, Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press. Polya, Georg 1945 How to Solve It: A New Aspect of Mathematical Method, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Introduction 11 Restivo, Sal 1985 The Social Relations of Physics, Mysticism, and Mathematics, Dordrecht, Boston: D. Reidel. Restivo, Sal, Van Bendegem, Jean Paul & Fischer, Roland (eds.) 1993 Math Worlds: Philosophical and Social Studies of Mathematics and Mathematics Education, Albany: SUNY Press. Rosental, Claude 2008 Weaving Self-Evidence: A sociology of logic, Princeton: Princeton University Press. Tymoczko, Thomas (ed.) 1986 New Directions in the Philosophy of Mathematics, Boston: Birkhäuser. Van Kerkhove, Bart & Van Bendegem, Jean Paul (eds.) 2007 Perspectives on Mathematical Practices: Bringing Together Philosophy of Mathematics, Sociology of Mathematics, and Mathematics Education, Dordrecht: Springer.