Introduction to Special Issue: Dedekind and the Philosophy of Mathematics

Similar documents
The Logic in Dedekind s Logicism

7AAN2056: Philosophy of Mathematics Syllabus Academic year 2016/17

Modern Logic Volume 8, Number 1/2 (January 1998 April 2000), pp

STRUCTURES AND STRUCTURALISM IN CONTEMPORARY PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS

Frege s Philosophy. Course Outline and Selected Reading

Philosophy Historical and Philosophical Foundations of Set Theory Syllabus: Autumn:2005

Scientific Philosophy

Frege on Numbers: Beyond the Platonist Picture

A Minimal Construal of Scientific Structuralism Katherine Brading and Elaine Landry

1 Mathematics and its philosophy

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy

Introduction Section 1: Logic. The basic purpose is to learn some elementary logic.

Logical Foundations of Mathematics and Computational Complexity a gentle introduction

GRADUATE SEMINARS

Ontology as a formal one. The language of ontology as the ontology itself: the zero-level language

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Mathematical Representation: playing a role

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

2176 Book Reviews as free open-source software, will serve as a lasting contribution of the translation project even beyond the translation itself. Vo

A Notion of Logical Concept based on Plural Reference

Introduction. Bonnie Gold Monmouth University. 1 The Purpose of This Book

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Philosophy Faculty Reading Lists PART II PAPER 07: MATHEMATICAL LOGIC

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Structure and Categoricity: Determinacy of Reference and Truth-Value in the Philosophy of Mathematics

Dan Nesher, Department of Philosophy University of Haifa, Israel

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

For French and Saatsi (eds.), Continuum Companion to Philosophy of Science

PARSONS AND THE STRUCTURALIST VIEW

KANT S THEORY OF SPACE AND THE NON-EUCLIDEAN GEOMETRIES

History of Analytic Philosophy

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

History of Analytic Philosophy

Formal Concept Analysis

From Kant to Quine: Reading List

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Cultural History of Mathematics

CRITICAL STUDIES/BOOK REVIEWS

Do Not Claim Too Much: Second-order Logic and First-order Logic

doi: /phimat/nkt011 Advance Access publication April 12, 2013

Corcoran, J George Boole. Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 2nd edition. Detroit: Macmillan Reference USA, 2006

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

INTRODUCTION TO AXIOMATIC SET THEORY

E. Roy Weintraub, How Economics Became a Mathematical Science (Duke University Press, Durham and London, 2002).

What is formal logic? Jean-Yves Béziau Federal University of Ceara CNPq/DCR - FUNCAP Brazil

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

attention of anyone with an interest in spherical trigonometry (a topic that finally seems to be making its comeback in college geometry teaching).

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Loss of vision: How mathematics turned blind while it learned to see more clearly

Curry s Formalism as Structuralism

A difficulty in the foundation of Analytic Philosophy

Structural Realism, Scientific Change, and Partial Structures

TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYSIS OF MATHEMATICS: THE TRANSCENDENTAL CONSTRUCTIVISM (PRAGMATISM) AS THE PROGRAM OF FOUNDATION OF MATHEMATICS

Boyd, R., Realism, Underdetermination and a Causal Theory of Evidence, Nous 7 (1973): Braithwaite, R., Scientific Explanation: A Study of the

Mathematical Practice and Conceptual Metaphors: On cognitive studies of historical developments in mathematics

1 in the sense of constructive, not of theoretical content

The Concept of Nature

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

What is formal logic? Jean-Yves Béziau

Axiomatics and Progress in the Light of 20th Century Philosophy of Science and Mathematics

Review of FERREIRÓS, J; LASSALLE CASANAVE, A. El árbol de los números. Editorial Universidad de Sevilla: Sevilla, 2016

Nissim Francez: Proof-theoretic Semantics College Publications, London, 2015, xx+415 pages

Meaning, Use, and Diagrams

WHITEHEAD'S PHILOSOPHY OF SCIENCE AND METAPHYSICS

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

On Recanati s Mental Files

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

The Philosophy of Language. Frege s Sense/Reference Distinction

Subjective Universality in Kant s Aesthetics Wilson

From Pythagoras to the Digital Computer: The Intellectual Roots of Symbolic Artificial Intelligence

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Pensées Canadiennes. Canadian Undergraduate Journal of Philosophy. Revue de philosophie des étudiants au baccalauréat du Canada VOLUME 10, 2012

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Philosophical Foundations of Mathematical Universe Hypothesis Using Immanuel Kant

"History of Modern Economic Thought"

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

Constructive mathematics and philosophy of mathematics

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

On the imaginative constructivist nature of design: a theoretical approach

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Haskell Brooks Curry was born on 12 September 1900 at Millis, Massachusetts and died on 1 September 1982 at

AN INTRODUCTION TO CLASSICAL REAL ANALYSIS KARL R. STROMBERG. AMS CHELSEA PUBLISHING American Mathematical Society Providence, Rhode Island

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

SENSE AND OBJECTIVITY IN FREGE'S LOGIC

On The Search for a Perfect Language

a n a l i t i c a comitato scientifico Mauro Mariani, Carlo Marletti Enrico Moriconi

THE FACT OF MODERN MATHEMATICS: GEOMETRY, LOGIC, AND CONCEPT FORMATION IN KANT AND CASSIRER. Jeremy Heis. B.A., Michigan State University, 1999

Immanuel Kant, the author of the Copernican revolution in philosophy,

The Debate on Research in the Arts

1 Exceptions to this include Friedman 1992, 34-5 and Ferrari 2009, who allude to Cassirer s emphasis on

Journal for the History of Analytical Philosophy

GOTTLOB FREGE: SOME FORMS OF INFLUENCE

Cambridge Introductions to Philosophy new textbooks from cambridge

Library Assignment #2: Periodical Literature

Edward Winters. Aesthetics and Architecture. London: Continuum, 2007, 179 pp. ISBN

Why are Aristotle and Euclid so Modernistic?

Transcription:

287 291 10.1093/philmat/nkx021 Philosophia Mathematica Advance Access Publication on August 7, 2017 Introduction to Special Issue: Dedekind and the Philosophy of Mathematics Richard Dedekind (1831 1916) was a contemporary of Bernhard Riemann, Georg Cantor, and Gottlob Frege, among others. Together, they revolutionized mathematics and logic in the second half of the nineteenth century. Dedekind had an especially strong influence on David Hilbert, Ernst Zermelo, Emmy Noether, and Nicolas Bourbaki, who completed that revolution in the twentieth century. With respect to mainstream mathematics, he is best known for his contributions to algebra and number theory (his theory of ideals, the notions of algebraic number, field, module, etc.). With respect to logic and the foundations of mathematics, many of his technical results his conceptualization of the natural and real numbers (the Dedekind-Peano axioms, Dedekind cuts, etc.), his analysis of proofs by mathematical induction and definitions by recursion (extended to the transfinite by Zermelo, John von Neumann, etc.), his definition of infinity for sets (Dedekind-infinite), etc. have been built into the very fabric of twentieth- and twenty-first-century set theory, model theory, and recursion theory. And with some of his methodological innovations he even pointed towards category theory. (Cf. [Ferreirós, 1999; Corry, 2004; Reck, 2016] also for further references.) No philosopher of mathematics today can afford to be ignorant of Dedekind s technical results. His more philosophical views, as well as other philosophical aspects of his mathematical style, have received much less attention, however, at least until recently. To some degree, this is due to the fact that he did not elaborate much on these views and aspects, especially compared to figures such as Cantor, Frege, Bertrand Russell, or Henri Poincaré. Partly it also results from early philosophical criticisms by Frege and Russell, later re-emphasized by Michael Dummett, George Boolos, and others [Reck, 2013b]. Besides Russell s antinomy, which applied to Dedekind s logical framework as much as to Frege s, it was mainly the charge of psychologism that appeared to disqualify Philosophia Mathematica (III) Vol. 25 No. 3 c The Author [2017]. Published by Oxford University Press. All rights reserved. For permissions, please e-mail: journals.permissions@oup.com 287

288 Reck him as a first-rate philosopher, particularly among Fregeans. But the structuralist aspect of his position was also received unsympathetically for a while (with exceptions, cf. [Cassirer, 1907; 1910]). In contrast, three recent developments have started to bring him back to the attention of philosophers of mathematics: the revival of structuralist conceptions of mathematical objects (Benacerraf, Resnik, Shapiro, Hellman, Parsons, etc.), frequently claimed to be in line with, or at least in the spirit of, Dedekind; increased interest in the philosophy of mathematical practice, including in what is sometimes called methodological structuralism [Reck and Price, 2000]; and the reconsideration of logicism, both from a historical point of view, with Dedekind being recognized as an early proponent [Reck, 2013a], and from a systematic perspective, including the use of abstraction principles [Linnebo and Pettigrew, 2014]. This special issue of Philosophia Mathematica is meant to reflect, as well as to reinforce, the revival of Dedekind s views and Dedekindian themes in the philosophy of mathematics. It consists of four new papers (previously available only in online-first versions). Two of them focus on mathematical practice and methodology, as seen from a philosophical perspective (those by Sieg and Schlimm and by Ferreirós). The other two concern more traditional philosophical themes, namely logicism and the objectivity of mathematics (Klev and Yap, respectively). As the following summaries will make evident, there are various interconnections between these pieces. DEDEKIND, METHODOLOGICAL STRUCTURALISM, AND THE NOTION OF MAPPING In their co-written paper, Dedekind s abstract concepts: Models and mappings, Wilfried Sieg and Dirk Schlimm develop a distinctive, historically grounded, and philosophically rich account of the sense in which Dedekind s writings embodied an original and revolutionary structuralist methodology. (The paper is a continuation of [Sieg and Schlimm, 2005].) The lens through which they see him is the axiomatic standpoint, as developed further by Hilbert and Noether later, and involving three aspects especially: abstract concepts (continuity, simple infinity, field, etc.), models (subfields of the complex numbers, models of the Dedekind-Peano Axioms), and mappings (the successor function, algebraic morphisms). Particular attention is paid to the emergence of the notion of structure-preserving mapping, from a few germs in Dedekind s predecessors, especially Gauss and Dirichlet, to their blossoming in his own work. In the latter, this development went through several forms or stages, from Dedekind s early work in group theory (during the 1850s) through his celebrated work in algebraic number theory and initial drafts of his foundational writings (1860s 70s) to his mature writings (from the mid-1880s on). There is a related shift in Dedekind s terminology (from substitutions through permutations and correspondences to mappings ), traced carefully by Sieg and Schlimm as well. The focus in Sieg s and Schlimm s paper is on the emergence of structuralist mathematics in Dedekind s writings up to the 1880s. In José Ferreirós s paper, Dedekind s map-theoretic period, that emergence is acknowledged too, but

Introduction 289 then an original twist is added. Ferreirós argues that there is a subtle, gradual shift in Dedekind s writings, from a primarily set-theoretic orientation, from 1858 to 1887, to a more map-theoretic focus, most prominently in his writings from 1887 to 1894. Like Sieg and Schlimm, Ferreirós discusses Dedekind s foundational writings in this connection, especially Was sind und was sollen die Zahlen? (an 1887 draft of it, as well as the final version from 1888). But two less familiar contributions receive careful attention as well: Dedekind s strikingly modern treatment of Galois theory, integrated into his algebraic number theory, in which the notion of structure-preserving mapping is placed at the very center (transforming Galois theory from the investigations of equations and their solutions to the study of field extensions and corresponding automorphisms); and his introduction of a radically new, distinctively map-theoretic, version of the continuum in an unfinished fragment from 1891 (pointing towards Baire space). The paper concludes with a discussion of how this gradual shift in Dedekind s orientation fits with his logicism. DEDEKIND, PHILOSOPHY OF MATHEMATICS, AND THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY In the secondary literature, Dedekind is sometimes mentioned as a major early logicist, besides Frege and Russell. Indeed, Dedekind himself talks about his goal of establishing that arithmetic is a part of logic, or of providing a purely logical construction for the natural and real numbers, especially in the Preface to his 1888 essay. However, he is much less explicit than Frege or Russell about the logical framework assumed in the background. Moreover, there are some open questions about his basic concepts, especially those of set and function, and their logical nature. In Ansten Klev s paper, Dedekind s Logicism, such issues are addressed directly. (In some respects, this paper is a continuation of [Klev, 2011].) After some initial clarifications concerning the notion of logicism operative in Dedekind s writings, developed with reference to Rudolf Carnap s influential characterization of it, Klev focuses on Dedekind s claim that functional thinking is indispensible for human thought. His core suggestion is to conceive of that claim along Kantian lines, and more specifically, to see the ability to think functionally as intrinsically tied to the understanding in Kant s sense. Implicitly Dedekind s use of logic is thus put in the context of transcendental logic, as opposed to more recent alternatives, e.g., Frege s and Alfred Tarski s, that are also considered briefly. Finally, there is Audrey Yap s paper, Dedekind and Cassirer on mathematical concept formation. In it, Dedekind s logicism, his alleged psychologism, and connections to Kant are addressed once again, but in a different way, namely by connecting them to the neo-kantian philosopher Ernst Cassirer. While Cassirer s sympathetic reception of Dedekind s philosophical views has been noted more generally (cf. [Friedman, 2000; Heis, 2010; Reck, 2013b], Yap focuses specifically on the accounts of subjectivity and objectivity with respect to mathematical concept formation in Cassirer s book Substance and Function. She suggests that Cassirer s function-based perspective on mathematics, together with his juxtaposition of two kinds of abstraction, provides a helpful

290 Reck framework for re-evaluating Dedekind s position. More particularly, it allows for the rejection of a naïve psychologistic reading of him, as presented prominently in Dummett s work; and it does so in a more nuanced way than earlier defenses of Dedekind by W.W. Tait and David McCarty. As a result, we can take his language of mental creation seriously after all, namely along the lines of the transcendental psychology specific to Cassirer s Neo-Kantianism. These suggestions are used, moreover, to reinforce a reading of Dedekind s position as logical structuralism (cf. [Yap, 2009a;b; Reck, 2003]). CONCLUDING REMARKS Comparing all four papers, the following related suggestions concerning Dedekind s philosophical views are perhaps most noteworthy. First, it is not just the notion of set that was crucial for Dedekind s logicism, thus for his revolutionary rethinking of the pure mathematics of his time, but also, and perhaps more, the notion of mapping or function. Second, with respect to mathematical practice it is Dedekind s substantive and self-conscious use of structure-preserving mappings (morphisms, including homomorphisms and isomorphisms) that constitutes his most important contribution. Third, Dedekind s emphasis on functional thinking allows for some illuminating comparisons to Kantian ideas, including Kant s transcendental logic, but also, perhaps more appropriately in the end, the Neo-Kantianism of Ernst Cassirer. And fourth, such comparisons shed new light on the notion of logic involved in Dedekind s writings. It is not to be expected that the articles in this special issue are the last word on Dedekind s philosophical views, not even on those aspects directly addressed in them: his structuralism, his logicism, and his more general methodology. In fact, an ongoing debate in the literature about how exactly to understand Dedekind s structuralism should be mentioned here, one that forms the background for some of the present papers (cf. the interpretation in [Sieg and Schlimm, 2005], their paper in this issue, as well as [Sieg and Morris, forthcoming], on the one hand, and the works by Reck and Yap already mentioned, on the other hand). There is also an emerging debate about Dedekind s logicism, including a recent challenge to categorizing Dedekind that way at all, given some important differences to Frege s and Russell s versions of it (cf. the suggestions in [Benis-Sinaceur et al., 2015] versus the pieces by Ferreirós, Klev, and Reck in the references below). Finally, much more can, and should, be said about philosophically relevant aspects of Dedekind s methodology (compare, e.g., [Avigad, 2006; Detlefsen, 2011; Haffner, 2014]). Then again, each of the four articles included here contributes to the corresponding debates in novel and substantive ways, thus helping to raise the level of philosophical discussions about Dedekind significantly. Erich Reck May 31, 2017 Department of Philosophy, University of California, Riverside, California 92521-0201, U.S.A. E-mail: erich.reck@ucr.edu

Introduction 291 REFERENCES Avigad, Jeremy [2006]: Methodology and metaphysics in the development of Dedekind s theory of ideals, in J. Ferreirós and J. Gray, eds, The Architecture of Modern Mathematics, pp. 159 186. Oxford University Press. Benis-Sinaceur, H., M. Panza, and G. Sandu [2015]: Functions and Generality of Logic: Reflections on Dedekind s and Frege s Logicisms. Springer. Cassirer, Ernst [1907]: Kant und die moderne Mathematik, Kant Studien 12, 1 49. [1910]: Substanzbegriff und Funktionsbegriff. Berlin: Bruno Cassirer. English trans., Substance and Function. Chicago: Open Court, 1923. Corry, Leo [2004]: Modern Algebra and the Rise of Mathematical Structures. 2nd ed. Basel: Birkhäuser. Detlefsen, Michael [2011]: Dedekind against intuition: Rigor, scope and the motives for his logicism, in C. Cellucci, E.R. Grosholz, and E. Ippolti, eds, Logic and Knowledge, pp. 205 217. Newcastle-upon-Tyne: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. Ferreirós, José [1999]: Labyrinth of Thought: A History of Set Theory and its Role in Modern Mathematics. 2nd ed. Basel: Birkhäuser. [forthcoming]: On Dedekind s logicism, in A. Arana and C. Alvarez, eds, Analytic Philosophy and the Foundations of Mathematics. London: Palgrave. Friedman, Michael [2000]: A Parting of the Ways: Carnap, Cassirer, Heidegger. Chicago: Open Court. Haffner, Emmylou [2014]: D un point de vue rigoureux et parfaitement général: Pratique des mathématiques rigoureuses chez Richard Dedekind, Philosophia Scientiae 18, 131 156. Heis, Jeremy [2010]: Ernst Cassirer s neo-kantian philosophy of geometry, British Journal of the History of Philosophy 19, 759 794. Klev, Ansten [2011]: Dedekind and Hilbert on the foundations of the exact sciences, The Review of Symbolic Logic 4, 645 681. Linnebo, Ø., and R. Pettigrew [2014]: Two types of abstraction for structuralism, The Philosophical Quarterly 64, 267 283. Reck, Erich [2003]: Dedekind s structuralism: An interpretation and partial defense, Synthese 137, 369 419. [2013a]: Frege, Dedekind, and the origins of logicism, History and Philosophy of Logic 34, 242 265. [2013b]: Frege or Dedekind? Towards a reevaluation of their legacies, in E. Reck, ed., The Historical Turn in Analytic Philosophy, pp. 139 170. London: Palgrave. [2016]: Dedekind s contributions to the foundations of mathematics, in The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Edward N. Zalta, ed.) https://plato. stanford.edu/archives/win2016/entries/dedekind-foundations/, accessed July 2017. Reck, E., and M. Price [2000]: Structures and structuralism in contemporary philosophy of mathematics, Synthese 125, 341 383. Sieg, W., and R. Morris [forthcoming]: Dedekind s structuralism: Creating concepts and deriving theorems, in E. Reck, ed., Logic, Philosophy of Mathematics, and their History. London: College Publications. Sieg, W., and D. Schlimm [2005]: Dedekind s analysis of number: Systems and axioms, Synthese 147, 121 170. Yap, Audrey [2009a]: Logical structuralism and Benacerraf s problem, Synthese 171, 157 173. [2009b]: Predicativity and structuralism in Dedekind s construction of the reals, Erkenntnis 71, 151 173.