Today I raise a simple question: which term, experience" or language, best. expresses the central motivation of pragmatism? Which would you choose?

Similar documents
Pragmatism and Experience in Contemporary Debates

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

What Difference Can Experience Make to Pragmatism?

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Anne Freadman, The Machinery of Talk: Charles Peirce and the Sign Hypothesis (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2004), pp. xxxviii, 310.

Rorty, Dewey, and Incommensurability

Pragmatism and Idealism

PRAGMATIST METAETHICS

Kant, Peirce, Dewey: on the Supremacy of Practice over Theory

James SCOTT JOHNSTON, John Dewey s Earlier Logical Theory

Reply to Stalnaker. Timothy Williamson. In Models and Reality, Robert Stalnaker responds to the tensions discerned in Modal Logic

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

COPYRIGHT 2009 ASSOCIAZIONE PRAGMA

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

RORTY AND BRANDOM: PRAGMATISM AND THE ONTOLOGICAL PRIORITY

BOOK REVIEW: JOHN DEWEY BETWEEN PRAGMATISM RECONSTRUCTING DEMOCRACY, RECONTEXTUALIZING DEWEY: PRAGMATISM AND INTERACTIVE CONSTRUCTIVISM

Swindal, James. Action and Existence: The Case for Agent Causation. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012.

The Self as an Object of Criticism: Richard Rorty s Denial of the Objectivity of Truth. Do Kien Trung, Kobe University, Japan

Categories and Schemata

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Moral Judgment and Emotions

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

On Articulting Reasons of Robert Brandom and His Hegelian Methodology

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Normative Engagement Across Difference: A Pragmatic Social-Practice Based Perspective

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

The identity theory of truth and the realm of reference: where Dodd goes wrong

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Scientific Philosophy

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

4 Embodied Phenomenology and Narratives

On Recanati s Mental Files

The Cognitive Nature of Metonymy and Its Implications for English Vocabulary Teaching

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

Keywords: semiotic; pragmatism; space; embodiment; habit, social practice.

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Current Issues in Pictorial Semiotics

Image and Imagination

In The Meaning of Ought, Matthew Chrisman draws on tools from formal semantics,

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Nature's Perspectives

Logic and Philosophy of Science (LPS)

WILLIAM JAMES STUDIES VOLUME 14 NUMBER 1 SPRING 2018 PP

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

WHY STUDY THE HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY? 1

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Metaphors we live by. Structural metaphors. Orientational metaphors. A personal summary

CRITICAL STUDIES/BOOK REVIEWS

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Natika Newton, Foundations of Understanding. (John Benjamins, 1996). 210 pages, $34.95.

Theories and Activities of Conceptual Artists: An Aesthetic Inquiry

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Practical Intuition and Rhetorical Example. Paul Schollmeier

Herbert Marcuse s Review of John Dewey s Logic: The Theory of Inquiry 1

Twentieth Excursus: Reference Magnets and the Grounds of Intentionality

Thomas Szanto: Bewusstsein, Intentionalität und mentale Repräsentation. Husserl und die analytische Philosophie des Geistes

Virtues o f Authenticity: Essays on Plato and Socrates Republic Symposium Republic Phaedrus Phaedrus), Theaetetus

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

The Body in the Mind: The Bodily Basis of Meaning, Imagination and Reason by Mark Johnson, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1987

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

observation and conceptual interpretation

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Transcription:

Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive David L. Hildebrand, University of Colorado Denver DRAFT: September 9, 2012 To be delivered at First European Pragmatism Conference, Rome, Italy, September 19-21 I. INTRODUCTION Today I raise a simple question: which term, experience" or language, best expresses the central motivation of pragmatism? Which would you choose? Something about the choice matters and perhaps we should choose. But which term and why? What are the stakes? Thirty years ago, Richard Rorty published Consequences of Pragmatism. One consequence has been that the experience vs. language" choice is clearer and starker. Today, one definite approach to pragmatism dare we call it neopragmatism? has chosen language as its focus and motive, and has deemphasized or excluded experience. Still, many others working with pragmatist themes choose to retain experience" as central. This conference provide a unique opportunity to imagine various paths that pragmatism might take in the 21 st century. We re not just here to report on pragmatism, but to persuade one another about our interpretations--interpretations being, after all, practical expressions of our values. I believe that choosing between experience and language is a value choice ingredient to pragmatism s future. To begin, I ll simply state the values I take as central to pragmatism. Pragmatism is the view that philosophy s most important role is to criticize and improve the conditions of human life, broadly considered. Philosophy becomes pragmatic when it foreswears, as marks of success, metaphysical absolutes and epistemological certainties, and nominates the practical as a better way to philosophize about a range of human endeavors: morality, art, religion, learning, politics, etc. Stress upon the practical is an avowal of a starting point; it does not recommend extinguishing or denigrating abstract thought s valuable

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 2/ 13 functions. (After all, without abstraction, pragmatism would have no tools with which improve life.) The central question I m raising, then, is whether pragmatism s mission is more effectively advanced by language-centered" or experience-centered" approaches. While I won t attempt to hide my preference--it s for experience--i want to lay out strengths on both sides. My purpose, then, will not be to prove anything or offer more than a sketch of the various philosophers mentioned but to provide points we can grab on to and debate. First, I ll begin with some common ground between both sides. Second, I ll examine the linguistic side. I discuss Rorty, Brandom, and Price. Third, I ll examine the experience" side. I discuss (mainly) Bernstein, Shusterman, and Margolis. Last, I ll offer a few summary thoughts. II. Common Ground Quite a bit of common ground exists between the two approaches. All repudiate the attempt to know, with certainty and universality, the framework Hilary Putnam labelled metaphysical realism : a reality that is complete, determinate, and radically external to inquiry. All agree, instead, that philosophical inquiries presume a naturalistic conception of reality and deny that beliefs work by representing or corresponding to transcendent entities. (Quine expressed this in Ontological Relativity when he said, With Dewey I hold that knowledge, mind, and meaning are part of the same world that they have to do with, and that they are to be studied in the same empirical spirit that animates natural science. There is no place for a prior philosophy. ) 1 All accept some form of fallibilism, roughly the notion that even highly warranted 1 Quine, W.V.O. Ontological Relativity in Ontological relativity and other essays. New York: Columbia University Press, p. 26.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 3/ 13 beliefs can be revised or replaced. This fallibilism derives from the recognition that a belief s epistemic adequacy depends upon how well it functions relative to specific contexts and purposes, rather than by possessing some mystical correspondence to a static and supra-human reality. The issue of language vs. experience is joined, then, by how best to oppose metaphysical realism how best to accomplish the goals of anti-representationalism and fallibilism. III. Linguistic pragmatists Rorty Rorty s most famous celebration of language as the route to anti-representationalism and fallibilism can be traced to Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature. Targeting traditional epistemology, he called the holism and pragmatism of Sellars s attack on givenness and Quine's attack on necessity were, he wrote, the crucial steps in undermining the possibility of a theory of knowledge because these steps] when extended in a certain way let us see truth as, in James's phrase, what it is better for us to believe, rather than as the accurate representation of reality. 2 Rorty s pragmatism translated older problematics into ones involving language. To know the nature of something, Rorty writes, is not a matter of having it before the mind, of intuiting it, but of being able to utter a large number of true propositions about it. 3 In later years, Rorty highlighted the importance of imagination for human progress, but imagination, too, was framed in terms of language, a Romantic realization that a talent for speaking differently, rather than for arguing well, is the chief instrument of cultural change. 4 Eventually. Rorty attacked not just epistemology but theoretical and systematic 2 Rorty, Richard, Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature, Princeton U.P. 1979, p. 10) 3 Rorty, Richard Contemporary Philosophy of Mind, Synthese, 53(2), pp. 323-48, p. 331. 4 Rorty Contingency, irony, and solidarity, Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 7.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 4/ 13 philosophizing, generally. In 1995 he exclaimed I linguisticize as many pre-linguisticturn philosophers as I can, in order to read them as prophets of the utopia in which all metaphysical problems have been dissolved, and religion and science have yielded their place to poetry. 5 Along the way, Rorty denigrated experience, eliminating the notion from his pragmatism. He viewed reliance on experience by pragmatists like Dewey and James as regrettable; they either lapsed into bad faith (offering substitutes for substance, mind, etc.) or were simply impotent to escape philosophical dead ends because a linguistic strategy was still unavailable. Rorty writes, Dewey s and James s attempts to give a more concrete, more holistic, and less dualism-ridden account of experience would have been unnecessary if they had not tried to make true a predicate of experiences and had instead let it be a predicate of sentences. 6 Progress in pragmatism, then, comes to mean eliminating experience altogether because, in Rorty's view, pragmatist accounts have never succeeded in talking about experience without re-enacting the tradition s pernicious representationalism. (Rorty insisted that Dewey's account of experience implied panpsychism and was inchoate, confused, and disingenuous. ) 7 The linguistic approach, on the other hand, lets us see that The point of language is not to represent either reality or experience accurately, but, once again, to forge more useful tools.... Cutting out the intermediary experience between the causal impact of the environment and 5 Rorty, Reponse to Hartshorne, in Rorty and Pragmatism: The Philosopher Responds to His Critics, edited by Herman J. Saatkamp (Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press, 1995), 35. 6 Rorty, Dewey between Hegel and Darwin, in Truth and Progress: Philosophical Papers, Volume 3, Cambridge University Press, 1998, p. 298 7 Dewey Between Hegel and Darwin, p. 297.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 5/ 13 our linguistic response to the environment is an idea whose time has come. 8 In exchanges with John McDowell, Rorty states that rejection of experience is, more generally, a rejection of what McDowell calls our answerability to the world. By rejecting the demands of answerability, pragmatism reveals its core identity: as an antiauthoritarian philosophy. Brandom Robert Brandom s inferentialism follows Rorty in important ways. Brandom s project is to construct an inferential role semantics derived from pragmatics the normative commitments and entitlements implicit in human discursive practices. In other words, our linguistic and social practices (e.g., of making, challenging, or evaluating assertions) provide the background necessary for explaining why notions like "true" or "refers to are meaningful but not representational. Like Rorty, Brandom eliminates experience from his account. He writes, Rorty and I both think that Sellars critique of the myth of the given shows the notion of experience as simply outmoded. I agree with Rorty] that there is no useful way to rehabilitate the concept of experience. We just need to do without that. 9 Rorty recognizes and celebrates Brandom s turn against experience: Brandom can be read as carrying through on the linguistic turn by restating pragmatism in a form that makes James s and Dewey's talk of experience entirely obsolete.in Making it Explicit] Brandom tells] a story about our knowledge of objects that makes almost no reference to experience. The term experience does not occur in the index to Brandom's 700-page book; 8 Rorty, Afterword: Intellectual Historians and Pragmatism, in Pettigrew, A Pragmatist s Progress, Lanham, Maryland: Rowman and Littlefield Publishers, p. 209. 9 Interview with Robert Brandom, Heine A. Holmen, interviewer, Filosofisk Supplement 1, 2005, p. 5

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 6/ 13 it is simply not one of his words. 10 Thus, the lesson of the linguistic turn as Brandom understands it is that philosophy does not need to describe, analyze, or theorize about experience at all because, as he puts it, pragmatists who have made the linguistic turn take it that the most important feature of the natural history of creatures like us is that we have come to engage in distinctively linguistic practices and to exercise linguistic abilities. 11 Price s Linguistic Paradigm The linguistic paradigm also informs the work of Huw Price who, like Rorty, wants to dismiss the metaphysical puzzles that arise whenever philosophy tries to place notions like truth and mind in the world depicted by science. Pragmatists, Price writes, favor more practical questions about the roles and functions of the matters in question in human life. Note, please, that by the matters in question Price explicitly means the words, concepts, and thoughts in terms of which we talk and think about such things and properties.pragmatism thus has a second-order, or linguistic' focus. 12 Note also that Price s pragmatism has not only a linguistic focus but a linguistic beginning or starting point. He writes, P]ragmatism begins with phenomena concerning the use of certain terms and concepts, rather than with things or properties of a non-linguistic nature. 13 This emphasis and starting point allows pragmatism to operate, Price says, without feeling the pull of the metaphysical questions without wanting to ask what we are talking about. Price in Misak book: 97] This approach, he thinks, is the only way to avoid what 10 Rorty, Robert Brandon on Social Practices and Representations, in Truth and Progress, p. 122. 11 Brandom From German Idealism to American Pragmatism, and Back text for lecture given at Cambridge, UK, May 31-June 1, 2012. p. 26. Document file downloaded from http://www.pitt.edu/~brandom/index.html 12 Price, Huw, Truth as Convenient Friction. In Robert Talisse and Scott Aikin, eds. The Pragmatism Reader (Princeton University Press), p. 94. 13 Price, Truth as Convenient Friction, p.95, emphasis on begins is mine.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 7/ 13 he calls our predecessors mistake of following a representationalist path into the culde-sac of metaphysics. 14 Pragmatism, he says, is a no-metaphysics view. 15 We see, then, in these three figures several advantages of the linguistic turn: language requires no transcendental referents (antirepresentational); the homogeneity of language removes unjustified hierarchies between, for example, science and art; finally, the supposed clarity of a linguistic medium displaces the confusion and metaphysical baggage of experience. III. Experience pragmatists Turning to experience, I ll now highlight several figures who find advantages in experience-based pragmatism. Pragmatists stressing the centrality of experience typically agree that pragmatism finds it s raison d être in meliorism in improving the conditions of life. Connecting with life requires embracing an approach to philosophy that avoids starting with theoreticallyloaded (or aprioristic ) starting points. As Dewey put it, We must go behind the refinements and elaborations of reflective experience to the gross and compulsory things of our doings, enjoyments and sufferings 16. This proposal, common to classical pragmatists, was not a theory about what experience is really like, as Rorty worried, but a proposal for how to make practice primary without setting philosophy against theory itself. Bernstein and Misak: Epistemic Check of Experience, Wider Range of Philosophical Subject Matter Richard Bernstein argues that when it comes to inquiry, redescription, no matter how 14 Price, Truth as Convenient Friction, p. 97. 15 Price, Truth as Convenient Friction, p.98. 16 Dewey, John. Experience and Nature. Vol. 1 of John Dewey: The Later Works, edited by Jo Ann Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, p. 74, pp. 375-76.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 8/ 13 imaginative, is not enough. 17 We learn what works and what doesn t by paying attention to what frustrates our words and deeds. This is experience, but it s neither a Raw Given nor a thin echo of self-enclosed subjectivity. Peirce taught us, Bernstein writes, that Experience involves bruteness, constraint, over-and-againstness. Experience is our great teacher. And experience takes place by a series of surprises. 18 Without this element, Bernstein argues, there is no friction to our experiments: Acknowledgement of this bruteness the way in which experience says no! is required to make sense of the self-corrective character of inquiry and experimentation. Experiments must always finally be checked by experience. Peirce would have been horrified by Rorty's claim that the the only constraints upon us are conversational constraints. To speak in this manner is to ignore the facticity, the surprise, shock, and brute constraint of our experiential encounters. 19 Dewey made this Peircean point in his Logic by pointing out how language becomes senseless when disconnected from a situation: Linguistic d]istinctions and relations, he wrote, are instituted within a situation; they are recurrent and repeatable in different situations. Discourse that is not controlled by reference to a situation is not discourse, but a meaningless jumble. 20 Cheryl Misak is another pragmatist who cites the constraint of experience as an indispensable epistemic value, especially for moral inquiry. She writes, "Clearly, if we want true beliefs, we should expose them to experience and 17 Bernstein, Richard, 2010, The Pragmatic Turn. Polity, p. 214. 18 Bernstein, Pragmatic Turn, p. 132. 19 Bernstein, Pragmatic Turn, p. 134. 20 Dewey, John. Logic: The Theory of Inquiry. Vol. 12 of John Dewey: The Later Works, edited by Jo Ann Boydston. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, p. 74.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 9/ 13 argument that might overturn them.those engaged in moral or political deliberation who denigrate or ignore the experiences of those with a certain skin color, gender, or religion are also adopting a method unlikely to reach the truth. 21 In Misak and Bernstein we see a concise articulation of the connection between experience" and meliorism. Life is improved by inquiry, and inquiry relies on the check of experience. That check is one advantage of experience. Experience also provides another, more general, advantage for Bernstein the diversity of philosophical subject matters. Linguistic pragmatism shrinks "what we consider to be a legitimate topic for philosophical investigation. 22 He writes, A linguistic pragmatism' that doesn t incorporate serious reflection about the role of experience in human life not only] loses] contact with the everyday life world of human beings and fails to do justice to the ways in which experience (Secondness) constrains us b]ut even more seriously it severely limits the range of human experience (historical, religious, moral, political, and aesthetic experience) that should be central to philosophical reflection. 23 The Aesthetics of Experience: Alexander and Shusterman Let s turn, now, to aesthetic experience. Both Richard Shusterman and Thomas Alexander cite encounters with music and art as vivid illustrations of why experience can be neither eliminated nor reduced to linguistic formulae. Both chafe at Sellars assertion that all awareness is a linguistic affair insofar as that has exempted philosophy from dealing with 21 Misak, Cheryl. Making Disagreement Matter: Pragmatism and Deliberative Democracy, in Robert Talisse and Scott Aikin, eds. The Pragmatism Reader (Princeton University Press), p. 476. 22 Bernstein, Pragmatic Turn, p. 141. 23 Bernstein, Pragmatic Turn, p. 152.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 10/ 13 the nondiscursive. 24 Neglect of nondiscursive experience indicates to Shusterman philosophy s preoccupation with justificational epistemology but such an assumption, he writes, is neither self-evident nor argued for." 25 In Dewey, both find a contrary approach urging that philosophical attention be paid to nondiscursive (or primary) experience. Such experience comprises the living and meaningful world from which symbols and arguments derive purpose and sense. Primary experience is our living starting point; by remaining humbly mindful of it, we gain what Dewey called a doctrine of direction insofar as it tells us to open the eyes and ears of the mind, to be sensitive to all the varied phases of life and history. 26 It is, in Alexander s words, a method for aesthetic receptivity and openness 27 that attempts to make us fully aware of the world beyond our ideas of it.it] is meant to contextualize the cognitive interests of philosophy within the noncognitive scope of life and so it] aims at reminding philosophy] of its origins in a prereflective world as well as of its obligations to make life more meaningful and value-rich. 28 Shusterman uses Dewey s account of nondiscursive experience to broaden the domain of what we might call art while pushing philosophy to engage with the body: Dewey] always insisted that our most intense and vivid values are those of on-the-pulse experienced quality and affect, not the abstractions of discursive 24 Paraphrased from Shusterman, Richard, Dewey on Experience: Foundation or Reconstruction, Philosophical Forum 26, no. 2 (Winter 1994), p. 140. 25 Shusterman, Dewey on Experience, p. 140. 26 Alexander, Thomas, Dewey s Denotative-Empirical Method: A Thread Through the Labyrinth. Journal of Speculative Philosophy, Vol. 18, No. 3, 2004, p. 251. 27 Alexander, Thomas, Dewey s Denotative, p. 251. 28 Alexander, Thomas, Dewey s Denotative, p. 254.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 11/ 13 truth." 29 By "affirming and enhancing the continuity between soma and psyche, between nondiscursive experience and conscious thought Dewey thought philosophy could enrich and harmonize how we live. 30 Shusterman proposes extending Dewey's insight by critically examining popular] body practices and their attendant ideologies and even integrating] bodily disciplines into the very practice of philosophy. In this way, they will be seeing philosophy not simply as a discursive genre but as search for truth and wisdom pursued not only through texts but also acute attention to the body and its nonverbal messages so as to heighten somatic awareness and transform how one feels and functions 31 The Continuity Thesis: Margolis and Johnson One last advantage provided by experience is found in recent work by Joseph Margolis and Mark Johnson. Linguistic pragmatists, Margolis argues, have provided no evidence for their assumption that language deserves primacy at the exclusion of experience. Margolis asks, "Why must we suppose, even if judgments, beliefs, reasons, and intentions are, paradigmatically, verbal, that there are no evolutionarily plausible animal analogues of any and all such cognitive elements, inferable from the behavior of nonlinguistic creatures? 32 Indeed, Margolis asks, why must concepts be specifically linguistic? Pragmatist accounts of experience can facilitate explanations of learning among higher animals and language acquisition among infants. One can tell a naturalistic story of an experiential continuum that does not imply panpsychism! 33 29 Shusterman, Dewey on Experience, p. 135-36. 30 Shusterman, Dewey on Experience, p. 139. 31 Shusterman, Dewey on Experience, p. 143-44. 32 Margolis, Joseph, Dewey s and Rorty's Opposed Pragmatisms. Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society, Vol. 38, No. 1, p. 124. 33 See Margolis, Present doldrums, pleasant prospects : Philosophy early in the new century.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 12/ 13 Work by Mark Johnson and Daniel Stern explores this further. Linguistic "meaningmaking" has a natural genesis in "patterns of experience" which begin in youth and continue throughout life. There are, Johnson writes, pervasive patterns of feeling that make up an infant s emerging sense of self and world. Human experience has a feeling of flow, and differences of pattern in this flow are the basis for different felt qualities of situations. 34 What psychiatrist] Stern identifies as being at the heart of an infant s sense of itself and the meaning of its prelinguistic] experience also lies at the heart of meaning in an adult s experience.we never abandon or transcend our early meaning-making ways; we only extend and build upon them. 35 IV. CONCLUSION In conclusion, my objective hasn t been to prove whether language or experience should be the central motive for pragmatism; instead, I have sketched various motives important to linguistic and experiential pragmatists. Let me make three tentative observations: First, the linguistic approach always seems to push us beyond language. As Bjørn Ramberg noted, any philosophical characterization of a vocabulary...will embody a proposal for conceiving of our interests in a certain way, a plea for seeing them that way and for assigning them a certain weight." 36 Philosophy Social Criticism 2007 33: 15, p. 21. 34 Johnson, Mark. The meaning of the body: aesthetics of human understanding. University of Chicago Press, 2007, p. 43. 35 Johnson, Meaning of the Body, p. 44. 36 Ramberg, Bjørn T., "Language, Mind, and Naturalism in Analytic Philosophy," in A Companion to Pragmatism, Blackwell, 2007, p. 222.

Hildebrand, Rome 2012 Experience or Language? Choosing Pragmatism's Central Motive 13/ 13 Those pleas, I take it, are about how to live and that is distinct from how to talk. Second, despite all the attendant problems, our need to appeal to experience (or some cognate term) is not going away. As Bernstein puts it, there is something about this signifier that gives it a power, a lure, an intensity that makes it irresistible....we cannot escape appealing to experience...in our irrepressible attempts to make sense of our being-in-theworld. 37 Third, and finally, the language-experience tension might be relieved by rejecting the dichotomy altogether. Bernstein might be right when he suggests that a forced choice between language and experience is obfuscating and sterile and that a pragmatic orientation demands a thoughtful and nuanced understanding of the meaning and significance of experience while also seeking to integrate the linguistic turn with a subtle appreciation of the role and varieties of experience. 38 Again, I m interested in your thoughts. I believe that discussing the experience or language" issue enriches a healthy dialogue about which purposes and priorities are best for the future of pragmatism. THANK YOU FOR LISTENING David L. Hildebrand Philosophy Department University of Colorado Denver READING COUNT: 3019 = 22 minutes, approximately. 37 Bernstein, Richard. 2006. "The Ineluctable Lure and Risks of Experience." History and Theory 45:261 75, p. 275. 38 Bernstein, Pragmatic Turn, p. 128-29.