What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Similar documents
By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Argumentation Theory and the Recent Philosophy of Science

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Habermas, Argumentation Theory, and Science Studies: Toward Interdisciplinary Cooperation l

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Idealism and Pragmatism: "Transcendent" Validity Claims in Habermas's Democratic Theory

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Any attempt to revitalize the relationship between rhetoric and ethics is challenged

Logic, Truth and Inquiry (Book Review)

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Discourse analysis is an umbrella term for a range of methodological approaches that

Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Humanities Learning Outcomes

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

A PRIMER TO CRITICAL SYSTEMS HEURISTICS FOR ACTION RESEARCHERS

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

Todd Hedrick

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Capstone Courses

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

Definición: Representation Bennett, Tony; Grossberg, Lawrence & Morris, Meaghan (2005). New Keywords. A Revised Vocabulary of Culture and Society.

Big Questions in Philosophy. What Is Relativism? Paul O Grady 22 nd Jan 2019

Visual Argumentation in Commercials: the Tulip Test 1

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Four Characteristic Research Paradigms

observation and conceptual interpretation

Lisa Randall, a professor of physics at Harvard, is the author of "Warped Passages: Unraveling the Mysteries of the Universe's Hidden Dimensions.

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

Colonnade Program Course Proposal: Explorations Category

foucault s archaeology science and transformation David Webb

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Normative and Positive Economics

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

Grade 8 Fine Arts Guidelines: Dance

COURSE: PHILOSOPHY GRADE(S): NATIONAL STANDARDS: UNIT OBJECTIVES: Students will be able to: STATE STANDARDS:

Master s Thesis. Between Reason and Affect. Frederik Langkjær. The Regulative Hope of Deliberative Politics UNIVERSITY OF COPENHAGEN

Habermas Discourse Ethics as the Foundation of Legitimate Laws

Valuable Particulars

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Theories of memory and a modified approach to discourse ethics: Rick Russo Department of Political Science University of Toronto

National Standards for Visual Art The National Standards for Arts Education

Visual Arts Colorado Sample Graduation Competencies and Evidence Outcomes

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Editorial Policy. 1. Purpose and scope. 2. General submission rules

Preliminary Syllabus. Subject to change. Hours: W &Th 9:00-11:00 Home phone (Milton): (905)

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Kimberly Hutchings Universalism in feminist international ethics: gender and the difficult labour of translation

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

November-December 2009

Université Libre de Bruxelles

BOOK REVIEW: JOHN DEWEY BETWEEN PRAGMATISM RECONSTRUCTING DEMOCRACY, RECONTEXTUALIZING DEWEY: PRAGMATISM AND INTERACTIVE CONSTRUCTIVISM

Holliday Postmodernism

Reviewed by Max Kölbel, ICREA at Universitat de Barcelona

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

Stenberg, Shari J. Composition Studies Through a Feminist Lens. Anderson: Parlor Press, Print. 120 pages.

Hoyningen Symposium Systematicity: The Nature of Science

International Journal of Advancements in Research & Technology, Volume 4, Issue 11, November ISSN

Comments on Bence Nanay, Perceptual Content and the Content of Mental Imagery

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

The Psychology of Justice

Introduction and Overview

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

Developing the Universal Audience

ALIGNING WITH THE GOOD

Theory, the Humanities, and the Sciences: Disciplinary and Institutional Settings

Helena Public Schools. Fine Arts Curriculum. Visual Arts

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)


Moral Geography and Exploration of the Moral Possibility Space

Qualitative Design and Measurement Objectives 1. Describe five approaches to questions posed in qualitative research 2. Describe the relationship betw

Scientific Publication Process and Writing Referee Reports

Challenging the View That Science is Value Free

Feminism, Underdetermination, and Values in Science

Transcription:

Cogent Science in Context: The Science Wars, Argumentation Theory, and Habermas. By William Rehg. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 2009. Pp. 355. Cloth, $40. Paper, $20. Jeffrey Flynn Fordham University Published in International Philosophical Quarterly 51:4 (2011) What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation relative to particular disciplinary contexts? Or are there context-transcending standards of cogency? Answering these questions is important not only for establishing the rationality of science in cases of paradigm shifts and interdisciplinary disputes, but also for being able to critically assess issues at the boundary between science and society. Debates between evolutionary theorists and creationists raise questions about what counts as a scientific argument. And science poses challenges not only to religious beliefs, but also to personal and political interests. We are all constantly bombarded with new scientific findings regarding diet, health, and lifestyle and must decide which claims to take seriously. Policymakers and citizens have to decide whether scientific evidence is strong enough to warrant taking potentially costly measures, for example, in the debate over global warming. In Cogent Science in Context, William Rehg refers to such public controversies as the new, public face of the academic science wars (2) that have been brewing since the 1960s. A significant virtue of this book is that it combines attention to such public debate with rigorous philosophical and sociological analysis of science as an argumentative practice, deploying detailed case studies of actual scientific argumentation (for example, the discovery of the top quark at Fermilab) and sciencebased policy making (for example, expert panels convened by the National Academy of Sciences to study links between diet and health). 1

Before turning to the critical contextualism that Rehg ultimately defends, we need to identify the problem for which it is the solution. That problem is Kuhn s gap : the gap between logical-rational and social-institutional perspectives on science that Thomas Kuhn opened with his critique of logical empiricists, who had largely relied on abstract rules of method and logical inference in analyzing the context of justification. Kuhn shifted attention toward the dynamics operative within the context of discovery and viewing scientific argumentation more as a social practice. The gap thereby opened up is both methodological and disciplinary (53-4). The methodological gap is that between two different perspectives on science: analyzing the cogency of the product of scientific argumentation versus analyzing the social-institutional processes of producing cogent arguments. This tends to support a disciplinary divide that pits philosophers on one side, relying on logical analysis of scientific argumentation, against sociologists on the other, focusing on rhetorical or social-institutional aspects of effective argumentation. Rehg aims to bridge both gaps and thereby foster interdisciplinary cooperation. To do so, Rehg appeals to argumentation theory in viewing scientific inquiry as a socially embodied constellation of argumentative practices (269). Drawing on categories from the study of argumentation product, process, and procedure as components of argumentation, and logic, dialectic, and rhetoric as three traditional modes of evaluation he reconstruct a series of recent debates in science studies, broadly construed to include the history and philosophy of science along with the sociology of scientific knowledge. He identifies a series of failed attempts to bridge the gap between the rational and the social in the wake of Kuhn. Kuhn s own solution was to stress the social-institutional dynamics of science as collectively rational : collectively and in the long run, scientists respond to good reasons (57). But this solution essentially absorbs the logical perspective into the social-historical perspective without looking 2

at the space in between, which includes rhetorical and dialectical perspectives. Rehg explores a range of such approaches (by Marcello Pera, Lawrence Prelli, and Bruno Latour), finds them wanting in various ways, and then turns to Jürgen Habermas s discourse theory as one of the most promising approaches to bridging Kuhn s gap. It is worth considering in more detail what motivates the move toward Habermas. One key point is that Rehg wants to bridge the gap between descriptive and prescriptive approaches within science studies, giving each its proper due. Habermas s combination of philosophical with sociological methodology makes it a good candidate for doing this. A related aim Rehg has is developing a form of critical science studies (CSS) that overcomes some of the relativistic implications of much of the sociology of scientific knowledge (SSK). Habermas s account of the universal pragmatic presuppositions of argumentation what Rehg calls dialogical idealizations certainly provides such a non-relativistic approach. But perhaps the main reason for turning to Habermas is that focusing on the process and not just the products of scientific inquiry suggests that a conception of cogency should include an account of conditions for a sufficiently reasonable process of argumentation. Rehg rightly notes that Habermas has primarily applied such an approach to the domains of morality, law, and politics. So Rehg himself has to do the detailed work of developing a discourse theory of science, which he then critiques and to which he offers an alternative. It is here, the point at which Rehg argues for moving beyond Habermas, that I want to make my first critical point. Rehg notes that the negative status of compromise in Habermas s model (189) presents two problems. First, if SSK theorists are right that compromise and negotiation are common in scientific collaborations (Rehg uses the example of the Fermilab evidence paper on the discovery of the top quark to show how this works in practice), then 3

Habermas s model is descriptively inaccurate. Second, if for a variety of reasons and under certain circumstances, compromise might be preferable to the kind of consensus based on the same reasons that Habermas privileges, then his model would be prescriptive in the wrong way. My first point is simply that if we take a cue from Habermas s application of discourse theory to law and politics in Between Facts and Norms (1996), we see that compromise does not have such a negative status and that Habermas was in fact realistic about the significant role of compromise and negotiation in politics. But he maintained that the framework for making such compromises must be justifiable and so constrained by more idealized notions of, for example, fairness. The same point, with suitable modifications could presumably be made with regard to justifiable or reasonable compromise among scientific collaborators too. Rehg seems to acknowledge this (193), but seems to me also to over-stress the extent to which this aspect of Habermas s theory represents an obstacle. Before turning to my second critical point, I should explain the basic idea of Rehg s own position, critical contextualism. The key move is a shift away from Habermas s general philosophical theory of cogency to a more context-sensitive approach that relies on participants judgments what scientists perceive as cogent in the specific context at issue (209). To do this, Rehg introduces a three-dimensional framework for assessing the cogency of scientific arguments according to their content merits (evaluating the argument s content), transactional merits (evaluating the quality of the locally situated transactions among scientists that produced the argument), and public merits (evaluating the ability of the argument to appeal beyond particular transactional domains within a broader public sphere that is itself well-structured to sustain collective reasonableness). This puts the stress less on a set of independent logical, dialectical, or rhetorical standards and more on the different levels of context in which the 4

meaning and relevance of such standards are concretely realized (271). The critical side of critical contextualism draws on the critical perspective of participants themselves, from scientists to a lay public who as Rehg shows with his analysis of the scientific and public reception of reports by NAS advisory committees already critically engage scientific arguments in terms of these three types of merits. Thus, the critical contextualist framework is not externally imposed, but is more of a heuristic for argumentation theorists to enter the discussion as one critical participant among others. In this way, it also aims to bridge the disciplinary divide between critical anti-relativistic approaches and more relativistic contextualist approaches. My second point is about the weight that Rehg places on interdisciplinary cooperation: fostering it is one of his primary aims in overcoming Kuhn s gap, and the extent to which Habermas s model would hinder it is one of his main criticisms of Habermas. But I am not sure I see how important it is. If the aim of SSK theorists is primarily descriptive, I can see why a CSS theorist might want to draw on some of their work to inform his or her analysis. But why would a deeply relativistic SSK theorist want to draw on CSS work at all? Moreover, how much of an obstacle would Habermas s approach actually pose to such cooperation? Rehg makes an excellent point about how Habermasians should not view pragmatic presuppositions like laws that automatically have jurisdiction over any and all arguments, but that their relevance must be demonstrated for the locale and context in question (241). In this way, process idealizations central to discourse theory can be made more context-sensitive by viewing them as enduring sites of contest and reflection in social life (229). But if such dialogical idealizations can indeed be contextualized in a variety of ways, then the extent to which a theory that posits them is an obstacle to interdisciplinary cooperation seems to decrease. 5

It also seems to me that Rehg is ultimately pulled in two different directions. The goal of interdisciplinary cooperation with SSK theorists, including those committed to some version of relativism, pulls in one direction (toward a more thorough-going contextualism), while the goal of having a theory that bridges the science-society interface pulls in another (toward the need for a more context-transcending theory of argumentation that can be applied within and across scientific and deliberative democratic contexts). Something has to give here. Since Rehg does not want to be pulled too far in the direction of relativism, I would argue that the Habermasian approach has more to offer, in particular once we get to really addressing the thorny questions raised at the end of the book about competing visions of the relation between science and society. I certainly have not done justice to all of the arguments in Rehg s comprehensive and meticulously well-argued book. Although I have focused my critical remarks primarily on Rehg s engagement with Habermas, that has more to do with my own interests than with the overall focus of the book. Rehg s book is no mere application of Habermas s discourse theory to science. It does provide a detailed account of what a Habermasian discourse theory of science would look like, and does so quite well. This is not surprising since Rehg had already written one of the best books on Habermas s theory of practical discourse (Insight and Solidarity: The Discourse Ethics of Jürgen Habermas [University of California, 1994]). But the book also provides a lucid and compelling reconstruction of debates within science studies over the last century using the resources of argumentation theory, and a bold defense of critical contextualism as an interdisciplinary framework for addressing significant tensions within science studies and a critical framework for assessing the cogency of scientific arguments. 6