Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory

Similar documents
Idealism and Pragmatism: "Transcendent" Validity Claims in Habermas's Democratic Theory

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

This is an electronic reprint of the original article. This reprint may differ from the original in pagination and typographic detail.

3. The knower s perspective is essential in the pursuit of knowledge. To what extent do you agree?

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

observation and conceptual interpretation

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

Environmental Ethics: From Theory to Practice

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Lia Mela. Democritus University of Thrace. Keywords: modernity, reason, tradition, good, Frankfurt School, MacIntyre, Taylor

Categories and Schemata

Habermas and the Project of Immanent Critique Titus Stahl

INTRODUCTION TO THE POLITICS OF SOCIAL THEORY

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

The Observer Story: Heinz von Foerster s Heritage. Siegfried J. Schmidt 1. Copyright (c) Imprint Academic 2011

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Heideggerian Ontology: A Philosophic Base for Arts and Humanties Education

KONSTANTINOS KAVOULAKOS. University of Crete

Master s Thesis. Between Reason and Affect. Frederik Langkjær. The Regulative Hope of Deliberative Politics UNIVERSITY OF COPENHAGEN

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Semiotics of culture. Some general considerations

Interdepartmental Learning Outcomes

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theory and Society.

An Intense Defence of Gadamer s Significance for Aesthetics

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions


SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

TROUBLING QUALITATIVE INQUIRY: ACCOUNTS AS DATA, AND AS PRODUCTS

Ralph K. Hawkins Bethel College Mishawaka, Indiana

Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

Qeauty and the Books: A Response to Lewis s Quantum Sleeping Beauty Problem

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

INTRODUCTION TO NONREPRESENTATION, THOMAS KUHN, AND LARRY LAUDAN

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Mixed Methods: In Search of a Paradigm

Rorty, Dewey, and Incommensurability

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

Logic and argumentation techniques. Dialogue types, rules

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

TRAGIC THOUGHTS AT THE END OF PHILOSOPHY

CONRAD AND IMPRESSIONISM JOHN G. PETERS

Université Libre de Bruxelles

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Habermas Discourse Ethics as the Foundation of Legitimate Laws

Normative and Positive Economics

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Notes on Gadamer, The Relevance of the Beautiful

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Credibility and the Continuing Struggle to Find Truth. We consume a great amount of information in our day-to-day lives, whether it is

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

Department of Philosophy Florida State University

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

On Recanati s Mental Files

Moral Relativism in Context

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

Theories of memory and a modified approach to discourse ethics: Rick Russo Department of Political Science University of Toronto

Towards a Rational Critique of Violence: Beyond Habermas Semantic Genealogy and Girard s Mimetic Anthropology

Perceptions and Hallucinations

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Situated actions. Plans are represetitntiom of nction. Plans are representations of action

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

Towards a Conflict Theory of Recognition: On the Constitution of Relations of Recognition in Conflict

Internal Realism. Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Abstract Several accounts of the nature of fiction have been proposed that draw on speech act

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

A Copernican Revolution in IS: Using Kant's Critique of Pure Reason for Describing Epistemological Trends in IS

Aalborg Universitet. Learning and Communicative Rationality The Contribution of Jürgen Habermas Rasmussen, Palle. Publication date: 2007

Scientific Philosophy

Reading/Study Guide: Lyotard. The Postmodern Condition

CARROLL ON THE MOVING IMAGE

M. Chirimuuta s Adverbialism About Color. Anil Gupta University of Pittsburgh. I. Color Adverbialism

Society for the Study of Symbolic Interaction SSSI/ASA 2002 Conference, Chicago

PHD THESIS SUMMARY: Phenomenology and economics PETR ŠPECIÁN

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

Theory or Theories? Based on: R.T. Craig (1999), Communication Theory as a field, Communication Theory, n. 2, May,

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

John R. Edlund THE FIVE KEY TERMS OF KENNETH BURKE S DRAMATISM: IMPORTANT CONCEPTS FROM A GRAMMAR OF MOTIVES*

Transcription:

Res Cogitans Volume 4 Issue 1 Article 14 6-19-2013 Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory Richard Van Barriger Portland State University Follow this and additional works at: http://commons.pacificu.edu/rescogitans Part of the Philosophy Commons Recommended Citation Van Barriger, Richard (2013) "Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory," Res Cogitans: Vol. 4: Iss. 1, Article 14. http://dx.doi.org/10.7710/2155-4838.1085 This Article is brought to you for free and open access by CommonKnowledge. It has been accepted for inclusion in Res Cogitans by an authorized administrator of CommonKnowledge. For more information, please contact CommonKnowledge@pacificu.edu.

Res Cogitans (2013) 4:107-115 Idealism and Pragmatism: Transcendent Validity Claims in Habermas s Democratic Theory Richard Van Barriger Portland State University Published online: 19 June 2013 Richard Van Barriger 2013 Abstract In her recent article Realism and Idealism: Was Habermas s Communicative Turn a Move in the Wrong Direction? Maeve Cooke examines the evolution of Jürgen Habermas s thought over the past five decades. According to Cooke, Habermas s so-called communicative turn was a necessary step in his philosophy s systematic attempt to derive a universal norm from the immanent context of human practices and institutions. In her opinion, however, Habermas is unable to uphold his pragmatically-based claim to transcendence from within without encountering problems of epistemic justification when it comes to his theory s treatment of normative validity claims. Cooke believes that despite Habermas exhaustive efforts, any political theory that discredits the possibility of metaphysical truth inevitably relinquishes the context-transcending moment that his idea of validity is meant to capture. In this essay, I examine how Habermasian philosophy attempts to assimilate such criticisms by deriving its normative ideals from the Theory of Communicative Action. In conclusion, I seek to characterize the dilemma thusly: the epistemic criticism raised by Cooke places her in the unenviable position of defending metaphysically-justified validity claims a pitfall that Habermas theory is designed to avoid. Introduction In her recent article Realism and Idealism: Was Habermas s Communicative Turn a Move in the Wrong Direction? Maeve Cooke examines the evolution of Jürgen Habermas s thought over the past five decades. According to Cooke, Habermas s socalled communicative turn was a necessary step in his philosophy s systematic attempt to derive a universal norm from the immanent context of human practices and institutions. In her opinion, however, Habermas s theory is unable to achieve such transcendence from within due to the inherent problem of justification in his theory s treatment of normative validity claims. Cooke believes that despite Habermas s exhaustive efforts to provide a communication-based model for an ideal theory of law, any political theory that discredits the possibility of metaphysical truth inevitably relinquishes the context-transcending moment that his idea of validity is meant to capture.

Res Cogitans (2013) 4 Van Barriger 108 I examine how Habermas derives the normative ideals of validity in democratic willformation from the Theory of Communicative Action, and compare this with the approach proposed by Cooke. In conclusion, I characterize their respective methods as mutually exclusive in terms of their assessment of the epistemic condition of modernity. Immanence and transcendence in critical theory: Habermas and the new realists Cooke is largely sympathetic towards Habermas s overall approach to critical theory, and shares his aspirations for a deliberative democracy that emphasizes reason-based communication between citizens. In fact, most of her piece is devoted to defending Habermas s position against more recent critical theorists such as Axel Honneth and Albena Azmanova, whom she refers to as the new realists. Their contention with Habermas revolves around the notion that his theory places insufficient emphasis on empirical subjects in the real world. In their view, a viable critical theory can instead be formed through a method of normative reconstruction based on political judgments that recognize the inherent subjectivity encountered in a complex pluralistic society (Cooke, 2012, p. 815). As Cooke points out, however, these theorists attempt to provide a historicallycontextualized account of social freedom and ethical life without resorting to so-called ideal theory is anything but new. Rather, (the) concern to avoid abstract normative theorizing and to investigate the actual experiences of historically situated agents is as old as the Frankfurt School tradition of critical theory itself (Cooke, 2012, p. 813). Interestingly, Habermas himself began his career by employing a similar method of normative reconstruction, and, as Cooke notes, his reasons for abandoning it in favor of rational reconstruction continue to haunt the efforts of the new realists. Cooke traces three distinct phases of thought in Habermas s writing that comprise (respectively) three distinct efforts at a normative justification for democracy: 1) a Marxist-Hegelian approach that attempts to situate democratic norms within the material conditions encountered in the world, 2) an epistemological approach that seeks to grant epistemic privilege to the concept of human benefit, and finally 3) the language-based theory of communicative rationality that Habermas has defended since the late 1970 s. Cooke believes that the new realists are too simple in their critique of Habermas, and fail to realize the extent to which their own theories lack a rational basis for normative claims. Here she believes Habermas is correct in confronting this problem and that he is right to look to human communicative practices in order to find an answer (Cooke, 2012, pp. 816-817).

Res Cogitans (2013) 4 Van Barriger 109 Communication and ideals: The limits of rational reconstruction Cooke s own disagreement with Habermas, on the other hand, engages his theory at the epistemological level of justification. She maintains that while his theory contains many valuable elements for political critique, it also falls short of its universalistic goal. As Cooke (2012) puts it Habermas has confronted but not yet solved the problem of how to defend his theory s context-transcending claims to validity (p. 818). Cooke s (2012) claim is that communicative reason ultimately fails to invoke universal ideals or guidelines, and should instead find its place within an intersubjective, pragmatically-comparative approach that includes the interplay of reason and affect:..the ultimate reference points for normative theorizing (transcendent objects such as truth and justice) are radically context transcending and as such inaccessible in their entirety to human beings; thus I posit an insurmountable gap between truth, justice and other transcendent reference points and the knowledge of them that is available by way of communicative reasoning. (p.819) Here the question arises: why, in Cooke s view, are these reference points inaccessible? What are the implications of this claim for Habermas s theory? To address this, I will briefly outline the Theory of Communicative Action in order to examine Habermas s formulation of normative validity. In conclusion, I will return to Cooke s argument against such a conception of validity and examine the implications of her own epistemic position. Communicative Action: The search for validity Habermas has always been interested in examining 1) the structural evolution of sociopolitical and economic systems in the twentieth century and 2) how the conceptions of knowledge and truth have undergone paradigmatic changes in the philosophy of science. Habermas seeks to place the justification for his democratic model in postmetaphysical terms that can accommodate what he sees as a coevolution of law and morality in political society, and so eschews both theological and ideological claims pertaining to human nature and well-being. His project consists of a comprehensive analysis of the social functions of language, drawing from other theorists such as G.H. Mead and J.L. Austin who explored the rational nature of language and attempted to define its modes and structures in communication. Habermas s (1987) goal in this seems to be his concern with a formal-pragmatic description that can be expressed in terms of a modern understanding of the world

Res Cogitans (2013) 4 Van Barriger 110 (p. 70). His contribution to political theory, then, is a model designed to avoid ideological claims while still retaining the ability to critique and diagnose the problems of modernity. For the purposes of the present discussion, we are concerned with how Habermas s theory develops the vitally-important concept of context-transcending validity claims, that can appeal to universal norms from within the the perspective of an existence situated in the world [emphasis original] (Habermas, 1993b, p.107). Habermas (1987) begins with examining the nature of communicative speech acts and their functional role in social activity. Here his goal is to establish a communication concept of rationality (p.13) that can avoid the limitations imposed upon the validity of intuition or introspection in the twentieth century- by logical positivism on one side and behaviorism on the other (p. 11). Rather than become embroiled in this subjectobject debate, Habermas (1987) borrows from George Mead s theory of communication that analyzes linguistic acts in exclusively social terms. The latter s concept of communicative action provides him with a functional, nonreductionist concept of language that can avoid scientific modernity s assault upon the so-called inner phase of individual experience (p.12). Mead identifies three phases in the evolutionary development of language that will play heavily in Habermas s own analysis of language: 1) Gesture mediated actions, illustrated by animal behavior, naturally form an ontological starting point from which to study communication and language. Here the key concept of meaning is found to be embedded in the functional circuit of behavior- that is, a gesture and response relation between organisms results in a field of meaning for its participants. This relation, according to Habermas (1987), forms the objective basis of the meaning that the gesture of one participant assumes for the other [emphasis original] (pp. 16-17). 2) Symbolically-oriented, or signal-language, refers to the intermediate stage of language development. According to Habermas, this phase includes three vital transformations: a) The replacement of gestures with symbols that carry the same meaning for both participants. b) The emergence of communicative intent from the causal cycle of stimulusresponse-stimulus. c) A shift in the structure of interaction wherein participants encounter the necessary distinction between acts of reaching understanding and acts of reaching success. (This will underwrite Habermas own typification of actionoriented speech as dependent upon mutual understanding, as will be shown below).

Res Cogitans (2013) 4 Van Barriger 111 3) Propositionally differentiated speech acts, according to Mead, represent the final stage of linguistic evolution. Habermas, however, believes that the theory becomes mired in the categorically-problematic concept of taking the attitude of the other, and disagrees with Mead s highly-complex formulation of how this particular transition occurs. His own proposal is to utilize two concepts already contained in Mead s theory as a functional differentiation in language use: action and understanding: This problem can be dealt with if we distinguish, more clearly than did Mead himself, between language as a medium for reaching understanding and language as a medium for coordinating action and socializing individuals [emphasis mine]. (Habermas, 1987, p.31) Habermas goal here is to establish this two-track ontology as the basis from which to analyze the nature of propositional language. Where Mead tried to continue from the bottom up in terms of his causal-historical account of language, Habermas (1987) is convinced that the former s genetic analysis of meaning between actors provides the conceptual tools to tackle propositional language from the top down, so to speak. His theory of language borrows from Austin, who distinguishes two components inherent in speech acts: propositional and illocutionary (p. 75). Illocutionary Speech: The emergence of normative validity An illocutionary speech act is some statement that is action-oriented- in the words of J.C. Farnum (2001) established as a promise, command, avowal, etc (p.33). This form of speech, according to Habermas, is what carries the crucial concepts of meaning and communicative intent developed in Mead s theory. Other forms of language such as describing the state of affairs in the world (i.e. locutionary) or attempting to influence others (i.e. perlocutionary) depend upon the twofold presuppositions of mutual understanding and action-orientation. 1 Thus illocutionary speech acts are presupposed by other modes of speech, and so possess an inherent precedence in communication. As Habermas (1996) puts it: Communicative action, then depends upon the use of language oriented to mutual understanding (p. 18) Here we arrive at the heart of the matter pertaining to Habermas conception of validity: a universalizing ideal in language that rests on two inherent possibilities in communicative action: consensus and rationality. Habermas (1993a) will define these as mutually-interdependent features of any speech act directed towards action in the world: We are intuitively aware that we cannot rationally convince anyone, not even ourselves, of something if we do not accept as our common point of departure that all voices that are at all relevant should be heard, that the best arguments

Res Cogitans (2013) 4 Van Barriger 112 available given the current state of our knowledge should be expressed, and that only the unforced force of the better argument should determine the yes and no responses of the participants. (p. 107) In other words, validity is that which conforms to the universal norms that are presupposed by the act of entering into communication. What Habermas hopes to accomplish with this definition is a dissolution of the tension between his concept of linguistic universality and the context of a historical-material world that it supposed to transcend. A communication-based concept of validity is meant to provide the tools to address both levels of this dilemma, and consequently provide a normative ideal for political critique: validity claims are Janus-faced: as universal, they outstrip every given context; at the same time, they must be raised and gain acceptance here and now if they are to sustain an agreement capable of coordinating action. (Habermas, 1993b, p.108) Knowledge, validity, and metaphysics: the epistemology of communicative reason In Habermas s framework, although validity-claims are analogous to truth-claims, only validity-claims retain the power of contextual transcendence and can appeal to the (idealized) universal norms of discourse. While there is much more to say about the distinction between truth and validity, I hope to have provided a minimally sufficient sense of the latter concept to enable a further examination of Cooke s critique. What does she mean when she says that truth and justice are transcendent reference points beyond the reach of communicative reasoning, and does she provide an alternative basis for such vital concepts? Habermas s primary mistake, in Cooke s view, has been an overreliance on rational reconstruction and excessive confidence in the firmness of the footing on which formal pragmatics places critical theory. The basis for this claim seems to arise not only from concerns over justification, but also from Cooke s own viewpoint of human nature as it pertains to communication. 2 As she sees it, reason-based argumentation forms but a part of individual shifts in perception from which political and moral convictions are formed, and the force of the better argument only partially captures the elusive concept of validity (Cooke, 2006, p. 111). There seems to be an inescapable dilemma contained within the parameters of this discussion when it comes to the role of religion in the public sphere. In the case of Cooke, the implications of her critique could not be starker: metaphysically grounded truth-claims, such as those based in religious belief, cannot in principle be excluded from the public process of argumentation. Whereas Habermas s secular concept of reason necessitates this exclusion, Cooke believes that this is both a necessary and

Res Cogitans (2013) 4 Van Barriger 113 unwanted feature of his theory s attempt at postmetaphysical justification. Cooke has admitted that her position places her at odds with much of the last two centuries of epistemology, 3 but is convinced that postmetaphysical thinking can never justify the concept of immanent transcendence (Habermas s communicative reason notwithstanding). Here one must at least credit Cooke (2012) for her forthrightness: I make the normativity of truth and justice partly dependent on a realm of value that is not the result of human behavior (p. 819). Cooke concludes her article with two speculative theses that conform neither with Habermas nor the new realists. The first is the aforementioned insurmountable gap between any transcendent reference point and the knowledge gained through communicative reason. The second is that communicative reasoning retains some usefulness to critical theory in that it can narrow the gap between immanent facts and transcendent norms. Given that Cooke rejects postmetaphysical justification as a method, it is not surprising that she flatly characterizes her views as speculative and context-specific. As she sees it, any bottom-up, postmetaphysical theory is inherently incomplete when formulated and justified solely as such, and the onus is on those who dispense with metaphysics to maintain this context-transcending moment without it (Cooke, 2012, p. 819). Conclusion In this essay I have sought to summarize the problem of postmetaphysical justification as conceived by Habermas and Cooke, and examine their disagreement over whether Habermas s concept of validity succeeds as a strategy for solving the paradox of immanent transcendence. While there is much more to be said for each theorist s views on truth and justification, their respective differences of approach seem fundamentally incompatible, if not mutually exclusive. I find Cooke s critique at once appealing and troubling. Her pragmatic concern over the interplay of religious and nonreligious reasoning in public dialogue is (as Cooke notes) shared by Habermas, as shown by his own recent work. However, the source of their disagreement, as we have seen, rests in their treatment of justification in the face of modernity: universality, on Cooke s account, is unjustifiable for any postmetaphysical theory, communicative or otherwise. In this it seems that Cooke struggles not only against Habermas s model, but also the epistemic condition of modernity itself. With an eye towards praxis, I see this as a potentially fatal problem for any normative political theory. For this reason, Habermas remains unwilling to place his theory in such a speculative position. He sees modernity as an irreversible condition, and so would rather utilize than resist its conceptual tools. That is, where Cooke sees an insurmountable gap

Res Cogitans (2013) 4 Van Barriger 114 between communicative reason and transcendent ideals, Habermas (1993b) instead sees communicative reason as the sole opportunity for a new concept of transcendence: The historicism of paradigms and world-pictures, now rife, is a second-level empiricism which undermines the serious task of confronting a subject who takes up a positive or negative stance towards validity-claims... But now it is argumentative reason itself which reveals, in the deeper layers of its own pragmatic presuppositions, the conditions for laying claim to an unconditional meaning. It thereby holds open the dimension of validity-claims which transcend social space and historical time... Without this, normality would close herself hermetically against any experience of a solidarity and justice that is lacking. (p.134) Whether or not Habermas s approach is effective as a normative political theory, and to what degree, will be a subject of debate for years to come. While I see Cooke s defense of metaphysically-justified validity claims as unrealizable in practice, her relatively novel line of critique does serve to illustrate the limited number of epistemic options available for modern political theory in general. References Cooke, Maeve. Re-presenting the Good Society. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2006. Cooke, Maeve. Violating Neutrality? Religious Validity Claims and Democratic Legitimacy. Center for Global Ethics and Politics at the Ralph Bunche Institute, CUNY Graduate Center, 25 Oct. 2011. Web. 27 Dec. 2012. Cooke, Maeve. Realism and Idealism: Was Habermas s Communicative Turn a Move in the Wrong Direction? Political Theory 40.6 (2012): 811-21. http://ptx.sagepub.com. Dec. 2012. Web. Dec. 2012. Farnum, John C. Habermas and the American Context: Toward a Theory of Substantive Democracy. Diss. Florida State University, 2001. 2001. Web. 25 Nov. 2012. Habermas, Jürgen. Between Facts and Norms: Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1996. Habermas, Jürgen. Justification and Application. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1993a.

Res Cogitans (2013) 4 Van Barriger 115 Habermas, Jürgen. Moral Consciousness and Communicative Action. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1990. Habermas, Jürgen. Religion and Rationality. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 1993b. Habermas, Jürgen. The Theory of Communicative Action, Vol. 2. Boston: Beacon, 1987. 1 As Farnum (2001) puts it, processes of communication rely on an ideal understanding of language-use that reveals the ever-present possibility of coordinating action via an uncoerced, intersubjective mode of social agreement. (p.35). 2 Elsewhere, Cooke has leveled several internal critiques of Habermas s justificatory framework that invite further examination, but I cannot address them here. 3 See the Q&A section to Cooke s presentation of her forthcoming paper Violating Neutrality? Religious Validity Claims and Democratic Legitimacy (Discussion with Maeve Cooke. Center for Global Ethics and Politics at the Ralph Bunche Institute, CUNY Graduate Center, 25 Oct. 2011. Web. 27 Dec. 2012).