WHY IS BEAUTY A ROAD TO THE TRUTH? 1. Introduction

Similar documents
KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Naïve realism without disjunctivism about experience

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

observation and conceptual interpretation

Action, Criticism & Theory for Music Education

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

AN ALTERNATIVE TO KITCHER S THEORY OF CONCEPTUAL PROGRESS AND HIS ACCOUNT OF THE CHANGE OF THE GENE CONCEPT. Ingo Brigandt

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

On The Search for a Perfect Language

In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases as bibliographies become shorter

ENVIRONMENTAL EXPERIENCE: Beyond Aesthetic Subjectivism and Objectivism

Habit, Semeiotic Naturalism, and Unity among the Sciences Aaron Wilson

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

High School Photography 1 Curriculum Essentials Document

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

Image and Imagination

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

On the Analogy between Cognitive Representation and Truth

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Kuhn and coherentist epistemology

Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating Pictures Mind, Vol April 2008 Mind Association 2008

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

The Epistemological Status of Theoretical Simplicity YINETH SANCHEZ

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

The Object Oriented Paradigm

The Reference Book, by John Hawthorne and David Manley. Oxford: Oxford University Press 2012, 280 pages. ISBN

Object Oriented Learning in Art Museums Patterson Williams Roundtable Reports, Vol. 7, No. 2 (1982),

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Review of "The Unexplained Intellect: Complexity, Time, and the Metaphysics of Embodied Thought"


In his essay "Of the Standard of Taste," Hume describes an apparent conflict between two

Moral Judgment and Emotions

Steven E. Kaufman * Key Words: existential mechanics, reality, experience, relation of existence, structure of reality. Overview

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

The Human Intellect: Aristotle s Conception of Νοῦς in his De Anima. Caleb Cohoe

ARISTOTLE AND THE UNITY CONDITION FOR SCIENTIFIC DEFINITIONS ALAN CODE [Discussion of DAVID CHARLES: ARISTOTLE ON MEANING AND ESSENCE]

Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

1/9. The B-Deduction

The Unity of the Manifest and Scientific Image by Self-Representation *

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Université Libre de Bruxelles

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

National Standards for Visual Art The National Standards for Arts Education

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

Credibility and the Continuing Struggle to Find Truth. We consume a great amount of information in our day-to-day lives, whether it is

TERMS & CONCEPTS. The Critical Analytic Vocabulary of the English Language A GLOSSARY OF CRITICAL THINKING

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Building blocks of a legal system. Comments on Summers Preadvies for the Vereniging voor Wijsbegeerte van het Recht

IF MONTY HALL FALLS OR CRAWLS

Music Performance Panel: NICI / MMM Position Statement

SIGNS, SYMBOLS, AND MEANING DANIEL K. STEWMT*

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

K Use kinesthetic awareness, proper use of space and the ability to move safely. use of space (2, 5)

SAMPLE COURSE OUTLINE PHILOSOPHY AND ETHICS GENERAL YEAR 12

VISUAL ART CURRICULUM STANDARDS GRADES Students will understand and apply media, techniques, and processes. Course Level Expectations (CLEs)

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

Aristotle The Master of those who know The Philosopher The Foal

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

Verity Harte Plato on Parts and Wholes Clarendon Press, Oxford 2002

Comparison, Categorization, and Metaphor Comprehension

A Note on Analysis and Circular Definitions

Fig. I.1 The Fields Medal.

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

Chapter 2 Christopher Alexander s Nature of Order

Permutations of the Octagon: An Aesthetic-Mathematical Dialectic

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

The Value of Beauty in Theory Pursuit: Kuhn, Duhem, and Decision Theory

4 Embodied Phenomenology and Narratives

TEST BANK. Chapter 1 Historical Studies: Some Issues

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Seven remarks on artistic research. Per Zetterfalk Moving Image Production, Högskolan Dalarna, Falun, Sweden

Ideological and Political Education Under the Perspective of Receptive Aesthetics Jie Zhang, Weifang Zhong

Communication Studies Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Incommensurability and the Bonfire of the Meta-Theories: Response to Mizrahi Lydia Patton, Virginia Tech

Transcription:

Paul Thagard WHY IS BEAUTY A ROAD TO THE TRUTH? ABSTRACT. This paper discusses Theo Kuipers account of beauty and truth. It challenges Kuipers psychological account of how scientists come to appreciate beautiful theories, as well as his attempt to justify the use of aesthetic criteria on the basis of a meta-induction. I propose an alternative psychological/philosophical account based on emotional coherence. 1. Introduction In a recent article, Theo Kuipers (2002) offers an account of the relation between beauty, empirical success, and truth. Building on his impressive work on the nature of truth approximation (Kuipers 2000), he provides a naturalistic-cum-formal analysis that supports the contention of McAllister (1996) that aesthetic criteria are useful for scientific progress and truth approximation. I agree with this contention, but will challenge Kuipers psychological account of how scientists come to appreciate beautiful theories, as well as his attempt to justify the use of aesthetic criteria on the basis of a meta-induction. I propose an alternative psychological/philosophical account based on emotional coherence (Thagard 2000). 2. Kuipers on Beauty and Truth According to Kuipers, the truth is beautiful in the sense that it has features that we have come to experience as emotionally positive due to the mere-exposure effect. This effect is a robust finding in experimental psychology that an increasing number of presentations of the same item tends to increase the affective appreciation of the item. Kuipers introduces the mere-exposure effect because it suggests that the human mind does a kind of affective induction in addition to the more familiar cognitive kind. Kuipers proposes that scientists do a kind of affective induction that leads them to react with positive emotions to recurring features of science that are not conceptually connected with empirical success, for example simplicity, symmetry, and visualizability. In: R. Festa, A. Aliseda and J. Peijnenburg (eds.), Cognitive Structures in Scientific Inquiry (Pozna Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, vol. 84), pp. 365-370. Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi, 2005.

366 Paul Thagard Assuming that there is indeed a correlation between such features and empirical success, the philosopher of science can then do a cognitive metainduction that justifies scientists affective inductions on the grounds that beauty really does correlate with truth. On this view, scientists acquire the tendency to find beautiful theories that possess features such as simplicity and symmetry on the basis of exposure to previous successful theories that had such features. Moreover, the acquisition is legitimate because, by the cognitive meta-induction, such features really do correlate with experimental success, which is an objective feature of theories. Kuipers not only tries to argue that the empirical success of theories signals their approximation to truth, but also that the correlating non-empirical features directly signal approximation to truth. Hence it is reasonable that scientists let themselves be guided by nonempirical features as well as empirical success. I do not want to challenge Kuipers account of truth approximation, which strikes me as the most sophisticated currently available, but I see several problems with the way he connects beauty and truth. First, note that the mereexposure effect is very different psychologically from affective induction. When mere exposure leads me to like something, the structure of the episode is: exposure to X increased liking of X. In contrast, affective induction has a structure something like: X goes with Y and Y is liked increased liking of X. Affective induction requires exposure to two features, e.g. simplicity and empirical success, whereas the mere-exposure effect does not require any such correlation. Hence the mere-exposure effect is logically and psychologically irrelevant to affective induction. I would not be surprised if human thinking does in fact use something like affective induction, but Kuipers needs to find empirical support for this kind of thinking from experiments other than those that support the existence of the mere-exposure effective. Second, evidence is needed to support the claim that the positive emotional attitude toward simplicity and symmetry that many scientists exhibit is acquired by affective induction. Does scientific education really involve juxtaposition of aesthetic features and empirical success in ways that could lead budding scientists to acquire the emotional appreciation of simplicity and symmetry? In the first place, do scientists have an antecedent positive emotional attitude toward empirical success that would provide the basis of the affective induction that aesthetic features are good? I conjecture that science students acquire the tendency to find some theories beautiful through a partly innate and partly acquired ability to recognize coherence; the next section defends an emotional coherence account of aesthetic judgments in science. If this account is correct, then scientists acquire aesthetic attitudes by means different from affective induction.

Why Is Beauty a Road to the Truth? 367 Third, I am less confident than Kuipers about the connection between empirical success and truth. Even if there is a legitimate meta-induction connecting beauty and empirical success, it remains to be shown that there is a connection between empirical success and truth. On Kuipers view, the connection is direct, by virtue of the definition of approximate truth and the theorem that if Y is closer to the truth than X, then Y is at least as empirically successful as X. I agree that in general empirical success is a sign of truth, but it is hard to make the connection directly, since we have no independent way of establishing truth. This is concealed in Kuipers framework because he identifies the truth as the strongest true theory rather than as how the world really is. In order to conclude that empirical success is a guide to how the world really is, we need to bring in other aspects of science such as its technological applicability, the substantial degree of agreement among scientists, and the largely cumulative nature of scientific development (Thagard 1988, ch. 8). In the past few hundred years, we have learned that empirical success is a much better guide to truth than other determinants of belief such as a priori reflection and divine inspiration, but it might have been otherwise. Hence the connection between empirical success and truth is just as much in need of argument as the connection between beauty and truth. The argument cannot be a cognitive meta-induction, because we have no way of identifying what is true. Rather, the form of argument is theoretical: we can infer that science acquires true theories because that is the best explanation of its technological success and largely cumulative development. 3. Beauty as Emotional Coherence I will now sketch a different picture of the role of beauty in scientific inference. My most recent book develops a theory of emotional coherence that is used to explain how judgments of beauty arise (Thagard 2000, ch. 6). The theory extends a general theory of coherence as constraint satisfaction: when people make inferences, they do so in a way that maximizes coherence by maximizing the satisfaction of multiple positive and negative constraints among representations. The kind of inference most relevant to scientific thinking is explanatory coherence, in which the representations are of evidence and hypotheses, the positive constraints are based on explanation relations between hypotheses and evidence, and the negative constraints are based on relations of contradiction or competition between hypotheses. When scientists choose between competing theories, they do so by accepting those hypotheses that are part of the maximally coherent account. Various algorithms are

368 Paul Thagard available for maximizing coherence, including psychologically plausible algorithms using artificial neural networks. The theory of emotional coherence postulates that human thinking is a process that involves affective as well as cognitive constraints and that both kinds of constraint satisfaction are intimately related. Representations acquire valences, which constitute their emotional content, in addition to their degrees of acceptability. For example, your concept of beer involves in part a valence that represents whether or not you like beer. Propositional representations such as Beer is good for you also have a valence, as is evident in the different emotional reactions that might be given to this proposition from avid beer drinkers as opposed to those of teetotalers. From the perspective of emotional coherence theory, beauty is not a property of individual representations, but is a metacoherence property that arises as the result of a general assessment of coherence. A feeling of happiness emerges when most constraints are satisfied in a person s unconscious processing of cognitive and affective constraints, whereas feelings of sadness and anxiety can emerge when constraints are not satisfied. In particular, scientists find a theory beautiful when it is highly coherent with the evidence and with their other beliefs. Such coherence is largely a matter of empirical success, in that many of the constraints on a theory concern the data which it is intended to explain. But simplicity is intrinsically part of the coherence calculation, since the constraints that tie hypotheses with evidence are stronger if the explanations involve fewer hypotheses (see Thagard 1992, for a full exposition). Moreover, symmetry, which is another one of the aesthetic factors mentioned by Kuipers, is also a matter of coherence, of an analogical sort. Symmetry is a matter of having multiple parts of a theory or other set of representations that are analogous to each other (Thagard 2000, p. 203). For example, a face is symmetrical to the extent that the left side is analogous to the right side. Like explanatory inference, analogical thinking can be thought of in terms of satisfaction of multiple constraints (Holyoak and Thagard 1995). In contrast to Kuipers, who views simplicity, symmetry, and analogy as problematic because they are nonempirical, I see them as an integral part of the coherence-based inferences about whether to accept or reject a theory. Beauty is the feeling that emerges to consciousness when a theory is very strongly coherent with respect to explaining the evidence and being consistent with other beliefs and possessing simplicity, symmetry, and other kinds of analogies. Psychologically, the beauty of a theory does not arise from affective inductions connecting aesthetic features with empirical success, but rather from the coherence of the theory that intrinsically includes those features.

Why Is Beauty a Road to the Truth? 369 4. Assessment I have offered an alternative to Kuipers psychological and philosophical explanations of why beauty is a road to the truth. Whose explanations are more plausible? First consider the competing psychological explanations of how scientists come to experience some theories as beautiful because of aesthetic features such as simplicity and symmetry. Kuipers: Scientists come to like such aesthetic features because of a psychological mechanism of aesthetic induction akin to the mere exposure effect. Thagard: Scientists find theories with such features beautiful because of their contribution to coherence which is inherently pleasurable. There is currently little experimental evidence to enable us to discriminate directly between these two explanations; I have already argued that aesthetic induction is a very different process from the mere-exposure effect, so the considerable psychological evidence for the latter does not support the general plausibility of the former. My main reason for preferring the emotional-coherence explanation of the pleasurable nature of simplicity and symmetry is that it derives scientific beauty from the same kind of psychological mechanism that produces intellectual pleasure in other domains, such as art, music, and mathematics. Aesthetic theorists such as Collingwood and Hutcheson, as well as mathematicians such as Hardy, have described beauty as deriving from unity, harmony, and coherence. Emotional coherence provides a unified (i.e. more beautiful!) explanation of scientific judgments of beauty, because it describes the same mechanism at work in science as in art and mathematics. Kuipers could well maintain that aesthetic induction on particular features operates in these other domains as well, which might serve to explain emotional preferences for particular kinds of art or mathematics. But aesthetic induction does not explain the general appreciation of beauty deriving from an overall appreciation of a work of art, a mathematical construction, or a scientific theory. In contrast, the theory of emotional coherence provides a specific computational mechanism by which positive feelings can emerge from global judgments of coherence, including ones that incorporate simplicity and symmetry. I also think that the emotional-coherence account provides a better basis for the philosophical issue of justifying scientists use of aesthetic judgments than Kuipers inductive account. Here are the two positions:

370 Paul Thagard Kuipers: Scientists use of aesthetic criteria such as simplicity and symmetry is justified by the cognitive meta-induction that these features correlate with empirical success and truth. Thagard: Scientists use of aesthetic criteria is justified more indirectly by the fact that they are integral to the coherence assessments that promote the largely cumulative development of theories, many of which are technologically successful. I prefer the indirect strategy because it does not require the accumulation, by practicing scientists or by philosophers combing the history of science, of a large body of instances of correlations between aesthetic features and truth. It is also immune to the likely existence of counterexamples in the form of cases where theories that turned out to be false were initially adopted in part on the basis of aesthetic criteria. Judgments of scientific beauty, like all inductive reasoning, are highly fallible. My indirect method of justifying explanatory coherence assessment as scientific method does not assume that it always or even usually works, as meta-induction requires. Scientific reasoning, based on explanatory coherence and including judgments of beauty, is justified because it is sometimes successful and there is no other method that is anywhere near as successful in finding out how the world really is. Beauty is a road to truth, but the road can be a winding one. In conclusion, I applaud Theo Kuipers for his development of elegant and plausible accounts of scientific reasoning and approximation to truth, and for his noble attempt to extend these accounts to explain the role of aesthetic judgments in science. But I have argued that the role of beauty in science is more fruitfully understood from the non-inductive perspective of emotional coherence. University of Waterloo Philosophy Department Waterloo, Ontario ON N2L 3G1 Canada REFERENCES Holyoak, K.J. and P. Thagard (1995). Mental Leaps: Analogy in Creative Thought. Cambridge,MA: The MIT Press/Bradford Books. Kuipers, T. (2000/ICR). From Instrumentalism to Constructive Realism. Dordrecht: Kluwer. Kuipers, T. (2002). Beauty, a Road to the Truth. Synthese 131 (3), 291-328. McAllister, J. W. (1996). Beauty and Revolution in Science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Thagard, P. (1988). Computational Philosophy of Science. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press/BradfordBooks. Thagard, P. (1992). Conceptual Revolutions. Princeton: Princeton University Press. Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in Thought and Action. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

Theo A. F. Kuipers AESTHETIC INDUCTION VERSUS COHERENCE REPLY TO PAUL THAGARD Paul Thagard s brief contribution deserves a long reply, but I confine myself here to some basic issues. I start with some concessions relative to SiS regarding simplicity and analogy, followed by rebutting Thagard s general and specific reserves about my recent naturalistic-cum-formal inductive account of the relation between beauty and truth. Finally, I raise some doubts about the exhaustiveness of his coherence account of that relation and its supposed incompatibility with my account. Aesthetic Induction, Empirical Success, and Truth Approximation Let me start by reporting some new considerations that are relevant to Thagard s contribution. In SiS I went as far as to claim that simplicity should only play a role in case of equal success (SiS, p. 238, and Section 11.2) and for analogy I saw no role at all (SiS, p. 297). Contrary to my previous beliefs, at the time of completion of SiS, very much stimulated by reading McAllister (1996), I was beginning to understand that there might be a relation between truth and simplicity, and, more recently, stimulated by a discussion with Thagard when he visited Groningen on the occasion of Alexander van den Bosch s promotion, even one between truth and analogy. Hence, in the light of my recent article on beauty and truth (Kuipers 2002), I have to qualify these claims in SiS. Since simplicity figures, at least in certain periods of certain disciplines, in the prevailing aesthetic canon, to use McAllister s nice phrase, it has cognitive merits related to empirical success and even to truth approximation, which scientists favoring the dominant theory may value more than some empirical successes of a new theory that are failures of the old one. Repairs may well come to grips with these failures. Similarly, as McAllister (1996) also illustrates and my article implicitly justifies, analogy may also be seen In: R. Festa, A. Aliseda and J. Peijnenburg (eds.), Cognitive Structures in Scientific Inquiry (Pozna Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, vol. 84), pp. 371-374. Amsterdam/New York, NY: Rodopi, 2005.

372 Theo A. F. Kuipers as a nonempirical feature of certain theories that may play a cognitively justified role. Certainly, the relative weight assigned to such features should take into account that these features are based on meta-induction, that is, induction of a recurring nonempirical feature correlating with empirical success, whereas general empirical successes are based on object-induction, induction of a regularity about (the behavior of) a certain kind of objects. Although object-inductions are not very trustworthy, they are certainly more trustworthy than meta-inductions. To be sure, the uniform notion of being empirically more successful, as presented in ICR and SiS, leaving no room for empirical failures compensated by more impressive empirical successes, can be extended to the more general notion of more successful, taking also nonemprical successes and failures uniformly into account. However, as explained in Section 6 of my article on beauty and truth, the interesting cases of nonempirical considerations come into the picture when they point in another direction than the empirical considerations. This would require a combined definition of more successfulness taking relative weights of different kinds of considerations into account. Depending on one s weights, to use an example suggested to me by Thagard, one may then value the phlogiston theory or even the oxygen theory as less successful than the classical theory, according to which there are only four substances, viz., air, earth, fire, and water, because this theory is much simpler than the two famous competing theories. I am happy to agree with Thagard s claim that my view of the relation between beauty and empirical success needs new experimental and historical evidence, although I would not say that the well established mere-exposure effect is irrelevant. In the article I argue that the aesthetic induction may be a variant of the mere-exposure effect, more precisely, a concretization, provisionally called a qualified-exposure effect. In line with its naturalized approach, I suggest at the end a number of experiments with normal and toy pieces of art and with scientific examples to establish the conditions and limitations of the effect. Moreover, further evidence for the varying character of the aesthetic canon when different phases or different research programs of the same discipline or of different disciplines are compared would strengthen the basic ideas around aesthetic induction as such and its diagnosis as a variant of the mere-exposure effect. Finally, as I also stress in my reply to Miller, in the companion volume, my refined claim about aesthetic induction can be falsified: determine a nonempirical feature which happens to accompany all increasingly successful theories in a certain area from a certain stage on and which is not generally considered beautiful by the relevant scientists. To be sure, the common interesting point of our diverging views is, of course, that both suggest (comparative) experiments and possible pieces of historical

Reply to Paul Thagard 373 evidence (see below), a rare but welcome aspect of primarily philosophical theories. Apparently I did not convince Thagard by arguing in ICR (p. 162) that there is a direct connection between empirical success and truth, and that we do not need his detour, as I explained in SiS (p. 298). The crucial point seems to be that I identify the truth as the strongest true theory (given a domain and a vocabulary) rather than as how the world really is. Here Thagard is transgressing the boundaries of my kind of constructive realism and enters some kind of essentialist realism. In the introductory chapter to this volume I summarize my direct argument for a relation between truth and empirical success. In my reply to Hans Mooij in the other volume I try to specify my metaphysical position in some more detail. Since Thagard s truth does not exist in my view, his detour argument, that empirical success is a sign of truth, essentially pertains to my non-essentialist kind of truth(s), like my direct argument. Emotional Coherence Let me now turn to Thagard s theory of beauty as an aspect of emotional coherence. According to him, scientists find a theory beautiful when it is highly coherent with the evidence and with their other beliefs, where simplicity, symmetry and analogy (of which symmetry is a special case) are intrinsically part of the coherence calculation. In SiS (Section 11.2), I argue in general against Thagard s unstratified theory of explanatory coherence (and its implementation in the ECHO program), in favor of the stratified priority of explanatory superiority (implemented by the evaluation matrix EM), by using a meta-application of simplicity considerations. I show that both are equally successful in accounting for all historical choices provided and prepared by Thagard himself, whereas ECHO is much more complicated than EM. (See my reply to Vreeswijk.) In other words, Thagard s coherence theory asks for historical cases in which explanatory superiority is sacrificed to simplicity, which would go against the stratified view. Thagard associates the beauty of theories with all kinds of coherence. Hence, incoherent aspects of theories should be seen as ugly. Thagard (2000, pp. 199-200) argues in general that symmetry is aesthetically appreciated for its contribution to coherence, and asymmetry is ugly due to its incoherence. He mentions the symmetry of (most) human faces, as opposed to the asymmetry of a misshapen face. This type of example is interesting for two reasons. First, after habituation to a misshapen face, e.g. of a movie star, we may come to find it very beautiful. Second, we are used to pictures of the arrangement of

374 Theo A. F. Kuipers organs in the human body, including all kinds of asymmetries, and many of us will find the composition very beautiful, not least for these asymmetries. Hence, an overall coherence account of beauty is difficult to combine with the fact that at least certain people appreciate incoherencies, including scientists. The biologist Stephen Gould, for example, stresses in an interview (Kayzer 2000) that he, in contrast to the physicist Steven Weinberg, counts diversity, unrepeatable contingencies and irregularities among the sources of his ultimate aesthetic satisfaction. Gould mentions as examples of great aesthetic satisfaction the diversity of a certain species of land snails, called cerions (p. 32), and the incoherencies in the revolutions of earth and moon, which make it impossible to design a coherent calendar (p. 29). Ironically enough, Weinberg (Kayzer 2000, p. 78; see also Weinberg 1993, p. 119) mentions the gravedigger scene in Shakespeare s Hamlet as a surprising intermezzo in a logical sequence of events, which, according to Weinberg, illustrates the fact that in the arts there are even higher aesthetic phenomena than in science. Hence, Gould s claim and examples seem to be incompatible with an overall coherence view of beauty in science, and Weinberg s example at least suggests that coherence cannot be the only source of aesthetic appreciation in the arts, which makes it difficult to understand why there would be no experiences of beautiful incoherencies in science. In the last part of his contribution Thagard gives a very clear statement of our diverging psychological and philosophical explanations of why beauty is a road to the truth. However, from the above it will be clear that I am not yet converted to his view. But I would also like to stress that they may be less incompatible than Thagard suggests. First, as to the psychological side, overall coherence might well be a feature that in certain disciplines and at certain stages can belong to the aesthetic canon as the result of aesthetic induction. Second, as to the philosophical side, I have already indicated that Thagard s supposed indirect connection between beauty and the essentialist truth, that is, the truth about how the world really is, boils down to a connection between beauty and constructive truths, for which connection there is a direct argument which, as a matter of fact, has not been disputed by Thagard. REFERENCES Kayzer, W. (2000). Het Boek over de Schoonheid en de Troost. Amsterdam: Contact. Kuipers, T. (2002). Beauty, a Road to The Truth. Synthese 131 (3), 291-328. McAllister, J. (1996). Beauty and Revolution in Science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in Thought and Action. Cambridge, MA: The MIT press. Weinberg, S. (1993). Dreams of a Final Theory. London: Vintage.