Complexity, Natural Selection, and Cultural Evolution William T. Lynch, Wayne State University

Similar documents
But, if I understood well, Michael Ruse doesn t agree with you. Why?

Objectives: Performance Objective: By the end of this session, the participants will be able to discuss the weaknesses of various theories that suppor


Sidestepping the holes of holism

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

THE EVOLUTION OF RELIGION AND THE EVOLUTION OF CULTURE TAYLOR THIEL DAVIS. B.Sc., The University of Georgia, 2000 M.A., Tufts University, 2011

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Holism, Concept Individuation, and Conceptual Change

Social Mechanisms and Scientific Realism: Discussion of Mechanistic Explanation in Social Contexts Daniel Little, University of Michigan-Dearborn

The Moral Animal. By Robert Wright. Vintage Books, Reviewed by Geoff Gilpin

PHILOSOPHY OF SOCIAL SCIENCE INTS 4522 Spring Jack Donnelly and Martin Rhodes -

Lisa Randall, a professor of physics at Harvard, is the author of "Warped Passages: Unraveling the Mysteries of the Universe's Hidden Dimensions.

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

Philip Kitcher and Gillian Barker, Philosophy of Science: A New Introduction, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014, pp. 192

WHAT S LEFT OF HUMAN NATURE? A POST-ESSENTIALIST, PLURALIST AND INTERACTIVE ACCOUNT OF A CONTESTED CONCEPT. Maria Kronfeldner

KINDS (NATURAL KINDS VS. HUMAN KINDS)

Chudnoff on the Awareness of Abstract Objects 1

Philosophy of Science: The Pragmatic Alternative April 2017 Center for Philosophy of Science University of Pittsburgh ABSTRACTS

Bas C. van Fraassen, Scientific Representation: Paradoxes of Perspective, Oxford University Press, 2008.

MAURICE MANDELBAUM HISTORY, MAN, & REASON A STUDY IN NINETEENTH-CENTURY THOUGHT THE JOHNS HOPKINS PRESS: BALTIMORE AND LONDON

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Darwinian populations and natural selection, by Peter Godfrey-Smith, New York, Oxford University Press, Pp. viii+207.

Kuhn Formalized. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

Significant Differences An Interview with Elizabeth Grosz

8/28/2008. An instance of great change or alteration in affairs or in some particular thing. (1450)

SOCI 421: Social Anthropology

PHILOSOPHY OF BIOLOGY

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

CAROL HUNTS University of Kansas

Boyd, Robert and Richerson, Peter J., The Origin and Evolution of Cultures, Oxford University Press, 2005, 456pp, $35.00 (pbk), ISBN X.

Kuhn s Notion of Scientific Progress. Christian Damböck Institute Vienna Circle University of Vienna

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

Action Theory for Creativity and Process

Review by Răzvan CÎMPEAN

The Psychology of Justice

Are There Two Theories of Goodness in the Republic? A Response to Santas. Rachel Singpurwalla

Philosophical Background to 19 th Century Modernism

ANALYSIS OF THE PREVAILING VIEWS REGARDING THE NATURE OF THEORY- CHANGE IN THE FIELD OF SCIENCE

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

10/24/2016 RESEARCH METHODOLOGY Lecture 4: Research Paradigms Paradigm is E- mail Mobile

observation and conceptual interpretation

These are some notes to give you some idea of the content of the lecture they are not exhaustive, nor always accurate! So read the referenced work.

Published in: International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 29(2) (2015):

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

CRITICAL CONTEXTUAL EMPIRICISM AND ITS IMPLICATIONS

Science and Values: Holism and Radical Environmental Activism

Theory, the Humanities, and the Sciences: Disciplinary and Institutional Settings

The Power of Ideas: Milton Friedman s Empirical Methodology

In Search of Mechanisms, by Carl F. Craver and Lindley Darden, 2013, The University of Chicago Press.

6 The Analysis of Culture

0:24 Arthur Holmes (AH): Aristotle s ethics 2:18 AH: 2:43 AH: 4:14 AH: 5:34 AH: capacity 7:05 AH:

Introduction to The Handbook of Economic Methodology

THE RELATIONS BETWEEN ETHICS AND ECONOMICS: A COMPARATIVE ANALYSIS BETWEEN AYRES AND WEBER S PERSPECTIVES. By Nuria Toledano and Crispen Karanda

Ithaque : Revue de philosophie de l'université de Montréal

GV958: Theory and Explanation in Political Science, Part I: Philosophy of Science (Han Dorussen)

Part IV Social Science and Network Theory

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

The (Lack of) Evidence for the Kuhnian Image of Science: A Reply to Arnold and Bryant

Is Genetic Epistemology of Any Interest for Semiotics?

Aspects of Western Philosophy Dr. Sreekumar Nellickappilly Department of Humanities and Social Sciences Indian Institute of Technology, Madras

Book Review. John Dewey s Philosophy of Spirit, with the 1897 Lecture on Hegel. Jeff Jackson. 130 Education and Culture 29 (1) (2013):

A Comprehensive Critical Study of Gadamer s Hermeneutics

Durham Research Online

Back to Basics: Appreciating Appreciative Inquiry as Not Normal Science

PROFESSORS: Bonnie B. Bowers (chair), George W. Ledger ASSOCIATE PROFESSORS: Richard L. Michalski (on leave short & spring terms), Tiffany A.

Course Description: Required Texts:

Rational Agency and Normative Concepts by Geoffrey Sayre-McCord UNC/Chapel Hill [for discussion at the Research Triangle Ethics Circle] Introduction

Relativism and the Social Construction of Science: Kuhn, Lakatos, Feyerabend

What do our appreciation of tonal music and tea roses, our acquisition of the concepts

Harris Wiseman, The Myth of the Moral Brain: The Limits of Moral Enhancement (Cambridge, MA and London: The MIT Press, 2016), 340 pp.

David Hull. Peter Godfrey-Smith. Biol Philos (2010) 25: DOI /s y

Incommensurability and Partial Reference

Resemblance Nominalism: A Solution to the Problem of Universals. GONZALO RODRIGUEZ-PEREYRA. Oxford: Clarendon Press, Pp. xii, 238.

What is Character? David Braun. University of Rochester. In "Demonstratives", David Kaplan argues that indexicals and other expressions have a

Normative and Positive Economics

ARISTOTLE S METAPHYSICS. February 5, 2016

Domains of Inquiry (An Instrumental Model) and the Theory of Evolution. American Scientific Affiliation, 21 July, 2012

George Levine, Darwin the Writer, Oxford University Press, Oxford 2011, 272 pp.

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at

English/Philosophy Department ENG/PHL 100 Level Course Descriptions and Learning Outcomes

Guide to the Republic as it sets up Plato s discussion of education in the Allegory of the Cave.

The Concept of Nature

The Nature of Time. Humberto R. Maturana. November 27, 1995.

Dabney Townsend. Hume s Aesthetic Theory: Taste and Sentiment Timothy M. Costelloe Hume Studies Volume XXVIII, Number 1 (April, 2002)

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Narrative Case Study Research

On Ba Theory Masayuki Ohtsuka (Waseda University)

Mind, Thinking and Creativity

Course Description: looks into the from a range dedicated too. Course Goals: Requirements: each), a 6-8. page writing. assignment. grade.

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Lecture 3 Kuhn s Methodology

Psychology PSY 312 BRAIN AND BEHAVIOR. (3)

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Realism, Conventionalism, and Causal Decomposition in Units of Selection: Reflections on Samir Okasha s Evolution and the Levels of Selection

An Alternative to Kitcher s Theory of Conceptual Progress and His Account of the Change of the Gene Concept

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Architecture is epistemologically

Anthro 1401, University of Utah Evolution of Human Nature Study Guide. Alan Rogers

Natural Genetic Engineering and Natural Genome Editing, Salzburg, July

Transcription:

Complexity, Natural Selection, and Cultural Evolution William T. Lynch, Wayne State University Peter Taylor begins his reply to me by objecting to Steve Fuller s intelligent design-based critique of the intelligibility of science which is the object of my criticism. 1 He argues that Fuller's own point of view does not make sense and that intelligent design should lead one to lack motivation to study nature since God can just change the rules at any point. That, of course, depends upon what God is taken to choose to do. In any event, I certainly cannot be expected to make a case for Fuller's argument that is stronger than the one he presents. Fuller is certainly right that belief in the book of nature as authored by God motivated early scientists to engage in scientific inquiry to fulfill their religious aims. That is a truism in the history of science. My argument against Fuller s view is that the pursuit of science is no more stymied by a transition away from theological motivations for conducting science than ethics or purpose in life are blocked by a move away from religious belief. Despite registering a lack of sympathy and understanding of Fuller s project, Taylor shares with him the belief that the scientific consensus behind evolution by natural selection is flawed and that it would be better to abandon Darwin s account and begin anew. It was precisely this kind of extreme anomaly mongering that I criticized in Fuller. It is evident in Taylor s stated desire to push the Lewontin-Gould critique of adaptationism beyond a rejection of just-so stories to denial of natural selection as a mechanism at all. 2 Despite telling us Intelligent design exponents be warned not all science studies critics of Darwinism play into your hands, that s exactly what Taylor s critique does. 3 The Political Consequences of Natural Selection He abandons Darwinian explanations for more contextual ones by claiming that complexity cannot be tamed by Darwin s simple metaphor. In doing so, he goes further than a call to incorporate developmental or sociological complexity within evolutionary accounts as endorsed by defenders of an extended evolutionary synthesis and as I have done in my article. 4 I take on board much of the critique of adaptationism that has been driven by the criticism of human sociobiology. I accept that simple, biological explanations of complex human behaviors are unlikely to be effective. Indeed, the key error of sociobiological accounts of human behavior and culture that I identify is that they miss that our biological adaptations have made possible another level of Darwinian selection entirely, which means groups will differ from each other as the result of cultural, not genetic, evolution. Moreover, reading to the end of Taylor s 1 Peter J. Taylor 2016, 85. 2 Taylor 2001. 3 Taylor 2016, 86. 4 Massimo Pigliucci and Gerd B. Müller 2010; Eva Jablonka and Marion J. Lamb 2006. 64

challenge to the metaphor of selection, it is clear that he has also reified the political critique of sociobiology into a requirement that scientific findings never threaten to bring about negative social stereotyping. 5 Thus, while Taylor notes that E.O. Wilson does, in fact, present a positive valuation of homosexuals, suggesting that they evolved as they are in order to assist their kin in raising children, such a positive valuation would collapse if they stopped assisting their kin in the modern world. It is, however, not clear, why an explanation of how our genes evolved by natural selection requires us to only value that mechanism itself and conform our behavior to its desiderata. In fact, it is urgent that the political case for basic human rights for gays and lesbians, as well as women and minorities denigrated by questionable sociobiological accounts, be made separately from any empirical account of their traits or provenance. The political critique of sociobiology s methods has been a useful exercise in that it revealed the bad assumptions and methods behind a reductive approach towards explaining human complexity. That critique should never be turned into a fetish and it is by no means clear that rejecting speculative scientific hypotheses for their perceived social consequences is either justified or, ultimately, consistent. 6 Artificial and Natural Selection Taylor s main objection to my own account of Darwinism is that my treatment of artificial and natural selection distorts Darwin s views and ignores the fact that natural selection is a metaphor. Here, he seriously misunderstands my discussion of natural and artificial selection. No one doubts that artificial selection was used to motivate an understanding of natural selection by analogy. Indeed, I explicitly argue that the growing prevalence of selective breeding provided the analogical basis for Darwin s theory. 7 I take it that all scientific explanations depend upon a metaphorical structure that is then exploited by the modeler. So to say that natural selection is a metaphor is not to say much. More to the point, it is simply not the case that artificial selection is utterly different from natural selection just because there is an explicit selector in artificial selection (a selector created by evolution by natural selection!). That is why I discussed Darwin's argument that pigeons don't revert to wild types, as well as modern niche construction theory, according to which animals help select the traits of other organisms by shaping the environment in similar ways to what humans do in shaping the selection environment of domestic animals. 8 Darwin recognized the conscious and unconscious effect of human behavior on selection as a continuum, with explicit, conscious human selection one extreme of a range of 5 Taylor 1998. 6 Alice Dregger 2015; William T. Lynch 1994. 7 Lynch 2016, 33. 8 Lynch 2016, 32. 65

situations where human behavior shapes the environment driving plant and animal evolution. 9 The context of this whole discussion is Fuller's claim that Darwin did not believe that humans could significantly modify nature, a kind of failure of nerve on his part. I think I showed that this was not the case. Darwin believed that artificial selection imposed fewer constraints on the human capacity to mold nature than his contemporaries believed. Moreover, domestication itself has now been demonstrated to have started with selfselection for tameness by the future animal domesticates, as they adapted to proximity to human habitations. Darwin had identified commonalities in the domesticated phenotype and these have now been shown to be the byproduct of selected changes in aggression and fear, as demonstrated in the famous Belyaev fox experiments. 10 Such changes exploit cryptic genetic variation without phenotypical effects, changes that accumulated during evolution prior to human intervention, which are then exposed to selection by the human role in the animal s environment. 11 Humans driving away or killing aggressive animals while tolerating tame ones in their vicinity acts just like any other animal behavior in the environment that can shape natural selection, favoring the emergence of new ecological niches. 12 Moreover, scientists are now coming to realize that selection for domesticated varieties of grains occurred through a process that is closer to natural selection than conscious breeding. Domestication as a model for natural selection has received a new lease on life by research that suggests that domestication is not as directed by human choice or as rapid as originally believed. In looking at the domestication of grains, Purugganan and Fuller argue that [t]he domestication process appears driven largely by unconscious selection pressures and is in principle simply natural selection in the novel environments established by human agriculture. 13 Even where researchers like Hillman and Davies posit a rapid transition to domesticated varieties of grains, based in part on the experimental study of the cultivation of surviving wild varieties, they conclude that this rapid evolution could occur without any conscious selection. 14 So in that sense, the first stage of domestication just is natural selection rather than something humans have imposed on nature by directly controlling breeding. When humans do take greater charge in directing animal or plant breeding, the resulting artificial selection does not somehow escape the mechanism of natural selection, as directed breeding must abide by the constraints of survival and reproduction, even given human management of the environment, as worries about inbreeding among domesticated animals bred to type demonstrate. 15 9 Lynch 2016, 32. 10 L.N. Trut et al. 2007. 11 Richard C. Francis 2015, 16. 12 Stephen Budiansky 1999; Darcy F. Morey 2010. 13 Michael D. Purugganan and Dorian Q. Fuller 2010, 181. 14 Gordon C. Hillman and M. Stuart Davies 1990, 157. 15 Donna J. Haraway 2007, ch. 4. 66

Evaluating Theories of Evolutionary Change Besides objecting to the metaphorical basis of natural selection, Taylor also argues that the mere existence of transitional forms does not mean that natural selection obtains, as evolution could have proceeded by other means that would also predict transitional forms. I would argue that we ought to approach this point historically, as it is not terribly meaningful to object to a successful scientific theory on the purely hypothetical grounds that some alternative theory with Duhem-Quine equivalence could be constructed. Indeed, that, again, is the key point that Taylor shares with Fuller if alternative hypotheses cannot be ruled out as potential explanations of the available facts, they both presume that these alternatives should be treated as equally credible. However, as Lakatos pointed out, we typically judge which programs are worth pursuing by their fruitfulness at generating predictions that are corroborated over time. While no crucial experiments can be expected to decide the issue, it does not follow that explanations that simply exploit the predictions made by another theory, adjusting its theoretical structure accordingly, should carry the same weight as a theory that is actually guiding new, productive work. Scientific theories are judged by their fruitfulness in guiding inquiry. The evolutionary view available to Darwin as a competitor theory and most familiar to his contemporaries was Robert Chambers anonymously published Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation. 16 Chambers' theory did not predict properly transitional forms, according to Darwin, let alone forms that are responsive to changes in environment. Instead, living forms advance along a predetermined path of change rather than adapt their characteristics to local environments. At the time, Asa Gray drew the inference from Darwin's theory that human transitional forms should be found, which was later corroborated, as I discuss. 17 Consequently, the basic Lakatosian track record (which Fuller himself uses as a criterion) is progressive, notwithstanding hypothetical Duhem-Quine equivalences. Nor would I think that Taylor s own alternative account of evolution would be able to predict the Tiktaalik fish I mention in the paper. 18 Indeed, I m not sure that isn t the point of Taylor s account of unruly complexity all determinate models ought to be rejected because there are always interactions with the environment and other processes. 19 In open systems, this is always the case in science, which is why experimental isolation of causes is sought, where possible, to supplement field observations that are subject to complex interactions with other causes. 20 Understood in terms of my article s appeal to recent work on cultural evolution, Darwin s significance is to uncover the basic mechanisms that lead to an evolutionary process: variation, inheritance, and differential survival. The theory predicts that whenever you can uncover such mechanisms, one should find selection-driven evolution. The modern 16 Robert Chambers 1844. 17 Gray 1860; Lynch 2016, 29 n. 4. 18 Lynch 2016, 29. 19 Taylor 2005. 20 Roy Bhaskar 1975. 67

evolutionary synthesis worked out one particular evolutionary system, but there are others that show that Darwin s project continues to be fruitful. It also shows that an understanding of complexity ought to begin by identifying evolutionary systems that can then be studied for their interaction with the environment and other processes. Contextual Explanations in Science Studies Taylor takes a similar skeptical approach towards understanding the complexity of the institution of science itself. He is skeptical that there is a singular institution called science. 21 Science, like evolution, certainly produces results that are radically dependent upon circumstance and no single set of traits characterizes life, or science, in general. However, it is just an unquestioned dogma of science studies today that science should be understood as any representation of nature by any society whatever and not an institution whose emergence was historically contingent. In opposing the political errors of Eurocentrism, we have adopted the dogmatic view that there are just different episode(s) of systematic knowledge-making that should all be explained piecemeal by contextual factors. 22 Just as tearing down Darwinian natural selection so sociobiologists can t make an uncongenial home there is counterproductive, so, too, is adopting contextualism as a global strategy for avoiding any hint of Eurocentrism in accounting for the emergence of modern science. In fact, one of the problems with Fuller s view is that he presumes that Abrahamic religions have an intimate and permanent connection to the heart of science as an institution it is aggressively Eurocentric in that sense (allowing for a somewhat broader view by including Islam). The best response, however, is not to argue that each and every picture of nature held by any human group is the same kind of thing as modern science (or all are completely different from each other, which amounts to the same thing), but to see that historical contingency of the Gould type exists in the history of modern science. Modern science did emerge, fitfully, in particular times and places. Path dependency means that we can as easily be misled by the Islamo-Christian metaphysical assumptions connected to this emergence, as Fuller is in writing them into the essence of science. My view is that science is historically contingent, in Gould s terms. It is an exaptation of our evolved biological characteristics, subject to further evolution at the cultural level. The paper's long discussion about the origins of agriculture and the development of religion and science are included to make this point. Just as with the critique of adaptationism in biology, a critique of essentialism in science is necessary. However, just as we shouldn t throw out selection with the adaptationist water, so too, should we not reject Fuller s views only by endorsing an unfocused contextualism that fails to explain anything general at all. 21 Taylor 2016, 85. 22 Taylor 2016, 85. 68

Models and Complexity Models by their very nature fail to capture the complexity of the world. Their value comes from their ability to guide inquiry in a way that can allow us to slowly build up a better, general account of a complex reality, even though there will always be elements exogenous to the modeled system. Generally speaking, scientists are aware that they are simplifying things, though sometimes they are unaware of exactly how they are doing so or where they go awry in adopting particular kinds of simplifying assumptions rather than others. Consider, for example, the new mathematical game theoretical accounts of evolution. Obviously these are models extended metaphors that treat natural selection as if it was a game with strategies. Early findings showed that tit for tat was an especially successful strategy that led to differential success in modeled environments. Is this a finding or a mistake? It is an early finding, since science works by dialectically engaging its past findings to generate new findings. The institutional generation of repeated novelty distinguishes modern science from other social representations of nature. 23 As such, the simplified assumptions underlying early game theoretic accounts can be challenged by incorporating more complex, but still mathematically tractable, assumptions into new models with the hope that the results will shed light on more complex evolutionary strategies. Just this kind of effort has illuminated new aspects of evolution, from a better understanding of specific ecological interactions to an understanding of how cooperation emerges, making possible new levels of evolutionary selection. 24 Is an emphasis on unruly untamable complexity better? Only in a very ad hoc sense, in that one can always appeal to aspects of the modeled reality that are not captured by the model. In this limited view, a non-model model always wins but only once all the facts are in and the components of construction are given one by one without any further discussion of how they interact and what this says about other cases (beyond that they are complex, too ). One can, in short, be a critic, after-the-fact, of any model that cannot be definitively matched to the facts. But it does not help you guide the further investigation of new cases it is not progressive in Lakatos sense. When this kind of extreme skepticism is wedded to ideological correctness, the critique can go awry in the long run, even if its methodological use in the short run is salutary. Why do Darwinian explanations need impossible standards of proof but any story of complexity in science or science studies is considered superior especially when they provide no guidance in actually carrying out any further investigations? Taylor routinely conflates the issue of whether a proposed explanation can explain a particular phenomenon and whether we can know it to be true given the limited tools at our disposal 23 Randall Collins 1998. 24 Martin A. Nowak 2011. 69

that can trace the timing and function of proposed adaptations. 25 An emphasis on complexity that just eliminates theoretical perspectives judged either too simple to match reality or too difficult to prove is not helpful. Conclusion Taylor s own contribution to the anti-adaptationist critique of human behavioral explanations initiated by Lewontin and Gould is important, epistemologically and politically. But the solution to the spread of reductionism is not to blow up all explanations, something that seems to be a permanent temptation in STS. 26 If you explain everything by a process of construction that proceeds by innumerable, one-off components of context, then you will explain nothing at all (and, in fact, smuggle in all kinds of unrecognized explanatory assumptions). Taken to its extreme, this represents not a critique of science, but a rejection of it. Science, on this view, is a conceit where you assume falsely that you can eliminate complexity. Only explaining every possible concrete event or outcome by contextual and contingent factors would be allowed no generalizing across contexts and certainly no comparisons with nonhuman animals, which might allow ideologues to justify contemporary inequalities. 27 Instead, I believe Lakatos (and Feyerabend) had it right in thinking about the theoretical context of science as dialectical, related, on the one hand, to overcoming the theoretical inadequacies of prior perspectives by pushing the programs until they break down, and, on the other hand, looking to see how new perspectives make possible more fruitful programs of research. 28 This is why the paper looks at how the limitations of certain versions of Darwinism were overcome in a way that put in place new models for dealing with complexity. It neither throws its hand up in defeat nor does it just reduce everything to contextual complexity without remainder. Contact details: William.Lynch@wayne.edu References Bhaskar, Roy. A Realist Theory of Science. York: Leeds Books, 1975. Budiansky, Stephen. The Covenant of the Wild: Why Animals Chose Domestication. New Haven: Yale University Press, 1999. Chambers, Robert. Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation. London: John Churchill, 1844. Collins, Randall. The Sociology of Philosophies: A Global Theory of Intellectual Change. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 1998. 25 Taylor 1998, 22-23. 26 e.g. Bruno Latour 1988, 1996; Michael Lynch 1993. 27 Taylor 1998, 28-29. 28 Imre Lakatos and Paul Feverabend 1999; John Kadvany 2001. 70

Dregger, Alice. Galileo's Middle Finger: Heretics, Activists, and the Search for Justice in Science. New York: Penguin Press, 2015. Francis, Richard C. Domesticated: Evolution in a Man-Made World. New York: W. W. Norton, 2015. Gray, Asa. Darwin on the Origin of Species. The Atlantic, 1860, http://www.theatlantic.com/magazine/archive/1860/07/darwin-on-the-origin-ofspecies/304152/. Haraway, Donna J. When Species Meet. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2007. Hillman, Gordon C. and M. Stuart Davies. Measured Domestication Rates in Wild Wheats and Barley under Primitive Cultivation, and Their Archaeological Implications. Journal of World Prehistory 4, no. 2 (1990): 157-222. Jablonka, Eva, and Marion J. Lamb. Evolution in Four Dimensions: Genetic, Epigenetic, Behavioral, and Symbolic Variation in the History of Life. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2005. Kadvany, John. Imre Lakatos and the Guises of Reason. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2001. Lakatos, Imre, and Paul Feyerabend. For and against Method: Including Lakatos' Lectures on Scientific Method and the Lakatos-Feyerabend Correspondence, Matteo Motterlini, ed. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1999. Latour, Bruno. The Politics of Explanation: An Alternative. In Knowledge and Reflexivity, Steve Woolgar (ed.), 155-76. Newbury Park, Cal.: Sage, 1988. Latour, Bruno. Aramis, or the Love of Technology. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1996. Lynch, Michael. Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action: Ethnomethodology and Social Studies of Science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993. Lynch, William T. Ideology and the Sociology of Scientific Knowledge. Social Studies of Science 24, no. 2 (1994): 197-227. Lynch, William T. Darwinian Social Epistemology: Science and Religion as Evolutionary Byproducts Subject to Cultural Evolution. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 5, no. 2 (2016): 26-68. Morey, Darcy F. Dogs: Domestication and the Development of a Social Bond. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2010. Nowak, Martin A. Supercooperators: Altruism, Evolution, and Why We Need Each Other to Succeed. New York: Free Press, 2011. Pigliucci, Massimo, and Gerd B. Müller (eds.). Evolution: The Extended Synthesis. Cambridge: MIT Press, 2010. Purugganan, Michael D., and Dorian Q. Fuller. Archaeological Data Reveal Slow Rates of Evolution During Plant Domestication. Evolution 65, no. 1 (2011): 171-83. Taylor, Peter. Natural Selection: A Heavy Hand in Biological and Social Thought. Science as Culture 7, no. 1 (1998): 5-32. Taylor, Peter. The Challenge of Integrating Ecological Dynamics into Evolutionary Theory. In Thinking About Evolution: Historical, Philosophical, and Political Perspectives, edited by Rama S. Singh, Costas B. Krimbas, Diane B. Paul and John Beatty, 377-93. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001. 71

Taylor, Peter. Unruly Complexity: Ecology, Interpretation, Engagement. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005. Taylor, Peter J. Questioning the Darwinism that Lynch Presents as a Viable Basis for Humans to Pursue Science. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective 5, no. 2 (2016): 85-87. Trut, L. N., A. L. Markel, P. M. Borodin, S. V. Argutinskaya, I. K. Zakharov, and V. K. Shumny. To the 90th Anniversary of Academician Dmitry Konstantinovich Belyaev (1917 1985). Russian Journal of Genetics 43, no. 7 (2007): 717-20. 72