Page109. Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions

Similar documents
Creative Actualization: A Meliorist Theory of Values

The Critical Turn in Education: From Marxist Critique to Poststructuralist Feminism to Critical Theories of Race

African Philosophy. Polycarp Ikuenobe A N I NTRODUCTION

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

observation and conceptual interpretation

Copyright is owned by the Author of the thesis. Permission is given for a copy to be downloaded by an individual for the purpose of research and

INTERVIEW: ONTOFORMAT Classical Paradigms and Theoretical Foundations in Contemporary Research in Formal and Material Ontology.

By Rahel Jaeggi Suhrkamp, 2014, pbk 20, ISBN , 451pp. by Hans Arentshorst

(as methodology) are not always distinguished by Steward: he says,

Vol. 5 No. 1 January June, 2016

HEGEL, ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY AND THE RETURN OF METAPHYISCS Simon Lumsden

AP English Literature and Composition 2004 Scoring Guidelines Form B

Program General Structure

Phenomenology and Non-Conceptual Content

AP English Literature and Composition

Research Topic Analysis. Arts Academic Language and Learning Unit 2013

Karen Hutzel The Ohio State University, Columbus, Ohio REFERENCE BOOK REVIEW 327

Mabel Moraña Washington University in St. Louis

What counts as a convincing scientific argument? Are the standards for such evaluation

Module A: Chinese Language Studies. Course Description

scholars have imagined and dealt with religious people s imaginings and dealings

AP English Literature 1999 Scoring Guidelines

CUA. National Catholic School of Social Service Washington, DC Fax

Post Structuralism, Deconstruction and Post Modernism

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

Always More Than One Art: Jean-Luc Nancy's <em>the Muses</em>

Presented as part of the Colloquium Sponsored by the Lonergan Project at Marquette University on Lonergan s Philosophy and Theology

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

UNIT SPECIFICATION FOR EXCHANGE AND STUDY ABROAD

PHILOSOPHY. Grade: E D C B A. Mark range: The range and suitability of the work submitted

Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

Postmodernism. thus one must review the central tenants of Enlightenment philosophy

Media as practice. a brief exchange. Nick Couldry and Mark Hobart. Published as Chapter 3. Theorising Media and Practice

PHI 3240: Philosophy of Art

The phenomenological tradition conceptualizes

IGU International Geographical Union Union Géographique Internationale UGI

Philosophic Sagacity: Aims and Functions 1

Università della Svizzera italiana. Faculty of Communication Sciences. Master of Arts in Philosophy 2017/18

Should Intercultural Philosophy take over from Anthropology in study of culture? Boele Van Hensbroek, Pieter

Introduction to Postmodernism

Undercutting the Realism-Irrealism Debate: John Dewey and the Neo-Pragmatists

A Process of the Fusion of Horizons in the Text Interpretation

Mixing Metaphors. Mark G. Lee and John A. Barnden

Internal Realism. Manuel Bremer University Lecturer, Philosophy Department, University of Düsseldorf, Germany

THE DIFFERENT LANGUAGES OF QUALITATIVE RESEARCH

Rachel G.K. Singpurwalla

Brandom s Reconstructive Rationality. Some Pragmatist Themes

HISTORIOGRAPHY IN THE TWENTIETH CENTURY: FROM SCIENTIFIC OBJECTIVITY TO THE POSTMODERN CHALLENGE. Introduction

SUMMARY BOETHIUS AND THE PROBLEM OF UNIVERSALS

Caught in the Middle. Philosophy of Science Between the Historical Turn and Formal Philosophy as Illustrated by the Program of Kuhn Sneedified

REFERENCES. 2004), that much of the recent literature in institutional theory adopts a realist position, pos-

Development of Philosophy of History

The Shimer School Core Curriculum

Post 2 1 April 2015 The Prison-house of Postmodernism On Fredric Jameson s The Aesthetics of Singularity

Film. Overview. Choice of topic

Credibility and the Continuing Struggle to Find Truth. We consume a great amount of information in our day-to-day lives, whether it is

Culture and Art Criticism

Interpretive and Critical Research Traditions

Wincharles Coker (PhD Candidate) Department of Humanities. Michigan Technological University, USA

Content or Discontent? Dealing with Your Academic Ancestors

Rorty, Dewey, and Incommensurability

Methodology in a Pluralist Environment. Sheila C Dow. Published in Journal of Economic Methodology, 8(1): 33-40, Abstract

BOOK REVIEWS. University of Southern California. The Philosophical Review, XCI, No. 2 (April 1982)

In basic science the percentage of authoritative references decreases as bibliographies become shorter

Comparative Literature: Theory, Method, Application Steven Totosy de Zepetnek (Rodopi:

A Letter from Louis Althusser on Gramsci s Thought

A STEP-BY-STEP PROCESS FOR READING AND WRITING CRITICALLY. James Bartell

NORCO COLLEGE SLO to PLO MATRIX

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Truth and Method in Unification Thought: A Preparatory Analysis

Usability of Computer Music Interfaces for Simulation of Alternate Musical Systems

Capstone Design Project Sample

Introduction: Mills today

MODULE 4. Is Philosophy Research? Music Education Philosophy Journals and Symposia

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

Objectivity and Diversity: Another Logic of Scientific Research Sandra Harding University of Chicago Press, pp.

By Maximus Monaheng Sefotho (PhD). 16 th June, 2015

12th Grade Language Arts Pacing Guide SLEs in red are the 2007 ELA Framework Revisions.

Goals and Rationales

Aesthetics and meaning

Student Performance Q&A:

Revisiting the African-Africana philosophy of education debate: implications for university teaching

OUP UNCORRECTED PROOF. the oxford handbook of WORLD PHILOSOPHY. GARFIELD-Halftitle2-Page Proof 1 August 10, :24 PM

Review by Răzvan CÎMPEAN

Hypatia, Volume 21, Number 3, Summer 2006, pp (Review) DOI: /hyp For additional information about this article

PART II METHODOLOGY: PROBABILITY AND UTILITY

Mind Association. Oxford University Press and Mind Association are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Mind.

Penultimate draft of a review which will appear in History and Philosophy of. $ ISBN: (hardback); ISBN:

Sidestepping the holes of holism

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

HEGEL S CONCEPT OF ACTION

Giving Reasons, A Contribution to Argumentation Theory

Critical Political Economy of Communication and the Problem of Method

The Polish Peasant in Europe and America. W. I. Thomas and Florian Znaniecki

The Role of Imagination in Kant's Theory of Reflective Judgment. Johannes Haag

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

Humanities Learning Outcomes

Writing an Honors Preface

Transcription:

Page109 Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions

Vol. 6. No. 1. January-June, 2017 BOOK REVIEW: AFRICAN PHILOSOPHY IN THE SEARCH OF AUTHENTICITY AND THE CONDITION OF UNIVERSALITY DOI: https://dx.doi.org/10.4314/ft.v6i1.6 Author: Pius Maija Mosima. Title: Philosophic Sagacity and Intercultural Philosophy: Beyond Henry Odera Oruka. Publisher: African Studies Centre, Leiden, The Netherlands. Pages: 187. Year of Publication: 2016. Reviewer: Ada AGADA, Ph.D Page110 Mosima s excellent work on Henry Odera Oruka and interculturality, Philosophic Sagacity and Intercultural Philosophy: Beyond Henry Odera Oruka, succinctly captures the dilemma of a philosophical tradition in the search for particularist authenticity and universal solidarity all at once. The philosophical tradition under study is, of course, African philosophy. Mosima commences his discourse with a three-fold classification of the various tendencies and schools in African philosophy for the sake of simplification: traditionalism with its particularizing perspective, universalism with its modernizing perspective, and the third way represented by the fast-developing intercultural perspective. With the enduring question of the status of ethno-philosophy in African philosophy constantly hovering in his mind, Mosima proceeds eloquently with his critique of philosophic sagacity. He notes the ethnophilosophical dependency of Oruka s philosophic sagacity, as argued by Kaphagawani (see MOSIMA, 2016, 103 104; cf AGADA 2015, 247 249). The ethnophilosophical underpinning of philosophic sagacity is hardly a problem for Mosima. The main weakness he identifies in philosophic sagacity, and which is important for his cherished intercultural project in African philosophy, is what he recognizes as Oruka s subservience to the hegemonic intent and character of the Western epistemological framework. For Mosima, Oruka s recourse to the Western epistemological framework, which hoists its own particularist concerns and content as the standard of universality, rationality, and objectivity represents the capitulation to Western intellectual hegemony (MOSIMA 2016, 108). Mosima can accuse Oruka of promoting the Western exclusivist claim to real rationality because Oruka wholeheartedly embraces the Western epistemological method as the truly authentic method in his

Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions elucidation of traditional knowledge-forms extracted from folk and philosophic sages. Consequently, it is easy to conclude, as Mosima does, that Oruka s sages did not have original views, their perspectives having been conditioned and coloured by modernism and the Western epistemological prism which Oruka set before the sages in the interviews he conducted (MOSIMA 2016, 117). Having identified the major flaw in philosophic sagacity, Mosima charts the way forward for this philosophical tendency in particular and African philosophy in general. Mosima s radical course is the call for African philosophy to embrace the project of interculturality and go global. The adoption of philosophical globalization for Mosima is integral to the counter-hegemonic project of African philosophers in the 21st century. The Cameroonian philosopher writes, still thinking of the great flaw of philosophic sagacity: When Oruka distinguishes the folk sage from the philosophic sages, is it not a subtle way of strengthening the very hegemony he sets out to challenge? His reaction is not counter-hegemonic enough but is based on a sameness with the West. This explains why he attempts to construct an African version of Western sagacity. (MOSIMA 2016, 109) Page111 Inspired by the work of Wim van Binsbergen in intercultural philosophy from the African standpoint, Mosima s solution to the West s philosophical hegemony consists in the globalization of African philosophy in the context of intercultural philosophy. According to the Cameroonian thinker, intercultural philosophy fundamentally demands dialogue with other dynamic, alternative logics than the North Atlantic one (MOSIMA 2016, 137). Thus, he talks of the globalization of sagacity in the context of cultural exchange and mutual contribution to a universal pool of knowledge. Mosima (2016, 144) asserts confidently: Since the world is becoming increasingly interconnected and interdependent, it makes sense to think of a globalized sagacity. Mosima soon goes into rhapsody for interculturality. On page 151 of his brilliant doctoral thesis, now published as a book, he writes: Philosophy should not escape by searching for fixed, universal, and immutable truth. Rather, it should be a problem-solving, pragmatic exercise. On page 152, Mosima uses the universal embrace of denim jeans to illustrate the necessity of interculturality and globalization. Denims are produced in the West, but humans everywhere appreciate them. It is reasonable, therefore, for African philosophy to go beyond particularist preoccupations and impediments and be useful to non- African cultures.

Vol. 6. No. 1. January-June, 2017 Page112 Mosima is of the opinion that if Oruka had taken adequate notice of certain theories expounded in the 1960s and 1970s notably the dynamic conception of culture by the Manchester School of Anthropology he would have directed philosophic sagacity towards interculturality. In Philosophic Sagacity and Intercultural Philosophy: Beyond Henry Odera Oruka, Pius Mosima has argued eloquently for the universalizing, transcontinental potentials of African philosophy, an optimistic perspective reminiscent of Jonathan Chimakonam s idea of the Global Expansion of Thought (CHIMAKONAM 2015, 35). Mosima infectiously envisions an African philosophy in dialogue with other philosophical traditions at the global level where every particular knowledge tradition contributes to the universal reservoir of knowledge as the equal of other particular knowledge traditions, thereby discrediting all hegemonic intentions and pretensions. But like every ambitious intellectual vision, Mosima s idealism is not completely convincing, persuasive as it is. He accuses Oruka of not moving radically in an anti-hegemonic direction. This charge of subservience to the Western intellectual hegemony is a masterful stroke delivered by Mosima. For long, African philosophers have neglected the task of developing philosophical methodologies rooted in the African knowledge-universe, preferring to blindly follow either the analytic method or the methods adopted by continental philosophers. Mosima appears to be calling for greater intellectual independence, without which intercultural philosophy will end up a futile exercise, indistinguishable from a crude and biased attempt at comparative philosophy. Mosima seems to be saying that a total rejection of Western methods of philosophizing may be impossible and even undesirable but that the complete acceptance of Western methodologies constitutes an endorsement of the very hegemony that threatens to condemn African philosophy to irrelevance. Nevertheless and ironically this very charge can be brought against Mosima to the extent that his globalist solution to the limitation of philosophic sagacity is not radical, not counter-hegemonic, enough. First, Mosima draws inspiration, and finds the justification for proposing the equality of divergent philosophical traditions, overwhelmingly from outside Africa a paradox noticeable in Valentin-Yves Mudimbe s works on the invention, or reinvention, of Africa. In other words, Mosima relies too heavily on philosophical theories and movements hatched by Western thinkers and in the Western world. I speak here of theories and movements like postmodernism and poststructuralism. Secondly, Mosima s persistent call for a philosophy of globalization that paternalistically endorses the project of intercultural philosophy assumes

Filosofia Theoretica: Journal of African Philosophy, Culture and Religions Page113 that African philosophy as it exists today can effectively compete with Western philosophy on the world stage. Not only has Western philosophy existed for over two thousand years as a written tradition but Western philosophy also continues to enjoy the kind of financial backing which African philosophy can only dream about. Consequently, the African tradition has continued to struggle for its life. While it is true that intercultural philosophy regards divergent philosophical traditions as having an equal value, respect and acceptance cannot be imposed but can only be earned. There is nothing to indicate at this time that Western philosophers have embraced the African tradition as the equal of the Western tradition. The meeting of these two traditions on the global stage will not be a mutually respectful interactive meeting but rather a meeting of the strong and the weak, with the strong either crushing the weak or accommodating it with paternalistic condescension. This is another hegemony, exactly the fate Mosima is desperately trying to avoid. Additionally, there is a clear possibility of intercultural philosophy degenerating into a mere meta-philosophical enterprise. To all intents and purposes, contemporary Western philosophy is largely analytical and metaphilosophical rather than synthetic. The project of synthesis has been completed by the great thinkers in the history of Western philosophy, such that contemporary Western philosophers have few original contributions to make to the Western tradition outside criticism. Thus, Western philosophy can afford to be essentially metaphilosophical. African philosophy cannot afford this luxury given that there is hardly any robust intellectual foundation on which metaphilosophy can thrive. Mosina seems to be untroubled by the danger of African intercultural philosophy degenerating into meta-philosophy, for he believes that the one great role of philosophy is problem-solving, in the pragmatist sense of impacting social and political life (MOSIMA 2016, 151). In other words, African philosophy should be oriented towards practical philosophy. Thus, African philosophy should ask questions about how philosophy can prevent or reduce conflicts, poverty, economic development, etc. Asking such questions is just as metaphilosophical as the debate over what constitutes African philosophy and what African logic is, to mention but a few polemicsgenerating talking points. These questions are important, but they should not constitute the heart of African philosophy at this time because the tradition still lacks a solid synthetic foundation. Very few African philosophers have made original and outstanding contributions to African philosophy. We have mostly had scholarship but not original systems and outstanding intuitions.

Vol. 6. No. 1. January-June, 2017 Mosima s advocacy for interculturality and globalization can gain more plausibility if his call for a counter-hegemonic movement in African philosophy is taken seriously. To take Mosima seriously, we must be ready to undermine Western theories and movements and find inspiration within Africa. Instead of relying substantially on the postmodernist thinkers of the West (and the methods of the Anglo- American analytic philosophers), we can embrace emergent African methodologies like complementary reflection, conversationalism, conceptual decolonization, etc. In this way African philosophy can become sufficiently counter-hegemonic as eloquently expounded by Mosima in this brilliant work that charts the way forward for a universally applicable African philosophy which yet retains its authenticity on the global stage. Relevant Literature 1. AGADA, Ada. The Future Question in African Philosophy. [Atụolụ Omalu: Some Unanswered Questions in African Philosophy Jonathan Chimakonam Ed.], pp241 267, 2015. University Press of America: Lanham, MD. Paperback. 2. CHIMAKONAM, Jonathan. Conversational Philosophy as a New School of Thought in African Philosophy: Conversation with Bruce Janz on the Concept of Philosophical Space. [Confluence: Online Journal of World Philosophies], pp9 40, 2015. Vol. 3. Web. 3. MOSIMA, Pius Maija. [Philosophic Sagacity and Intercultural Philosophy: Beyond Henry Odera Oruka], 2016. African Studies Centre: Leiden, The Netherlands. Paperback. Page114