KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

Similar documents
1/9. The B-Deduction

1/10. The A-Deduction

THESIS MIND AND WORLD IN KANT S THEORY OF SENSATION. Submitted by. Jessica Murski. Department of Philosophy

Conclusion. One way of characterizing the project Kant undertakes in the Critique of Pure Reason is by

1/8. The Third Paralogism and the Transcendental Unity of Apperception

1/8. Axioms of Intuition

The Pure Concepts of the Understanding and Synthetic A Priori Cognition: the Problem of Metaphysics in the Critique of Pure Reason and a Solution

that would join theoretical philosophy (metaphysics) and practical philosophy (ethics)?

Necessity in Kant; Subjective and Objective

Categories and Schemata

Immanuel Kant Critique of Pure Reason

Kant: Critique of Pure Reason

Kant IV The Analogies The Schematism updated: 2/2/12. Reading: 78-88, In General

ANALOGY, SCHEMATISM AND THE EXISTENCE OF GOD

Kant on Unity in Experience

KANT S THEORY OF KNOWLEDGE

KANT'S TRANSCENDENTAL DEDUCTION: AN ANALYTICAL-HISTORICAL COMMENTARY BY HENRY E. ALLISON

Kant and the Problem of Experience

Phenomenology Glossary

Self-Consciousness and Knowledge

The Case for Absolute Spontaneity in Kant s Critique of Pure Reason. La defensa de la espontaneidad absoluta en la Crítica de la razón pura de Kant

Kant and the Problem of Experience. Hannah Ginsborg. As most of its readers are aware, the Critique of Pure Reason is

Summary of the Transcendental Ideas

IMPORTANT QUOTATIONS

Imagination and Contingency: Overcoming the Problems of Kant s Transcendental Deduction

None DEREE COLLEGE SYLLABUS FOR: PH 4028 KANT AND GERMAN IDEALISM UK LEVEL 6 UK CREDITS: 15 US CREDITS: 3/0/3. (Updated SPRING 2016) PREREQUISITES:

Peirce and Semiotic an Introduction

Practical Action First Critique Foundations *

1/6. The Anticipations of Perception

Human Finitude and the Dialectics of Experience

On The Search for a Perfect Language

Chapter 5 The Categories of Understanding

Making Modal Distinctions: Kant on the possible, the actual, and the intuitive understanding.

Philosophical Foundations of Mathematical Universe Hypothesis Using Immanuel Kant

124 Philosophy of Mathematics

No Other Use than in Judgment? Kant on Concepts and Sensible Synthesis

Kant: Notes on the Critique of Judgment

1/9. Descartes on Simple Ideas (2)

Kant s Critique of Judgment

Kant Prolegomena to any Future Metaphysics, Preface, excerpts 1 Critique of Pure Reason, excerpts 2 PHIL101 Prof. Oakes updated: 9/19/13 12:13 PM

Universality and the Analytic Unity of Apperception in Kant: a reading of CPR B133-4n. Wayne Waxman

What is the Object of Thinking Differently?

Having the World in View: Essays on Kant, Hegel, and Sellars

SYSTEM-PURPOSE METHOD: THEORETICAL AND PRACTICAL ASPECTS Ramil Dursunov PhD in Law University of Fribourg, Faculty of Law ABSTRACT INTRODUCTION

FUNCTION AND EPIGENESIS IN KANT S CRITIQUE OF PURE REASON BRANDON W. SHAW. (Under the Direction of O. Bradley Bassler) ABSTRACT

The Role of Imagination in Kant's Theory of Reflective Judgment. Johannes Haag

Chapter 12 The Standard Gauge of Perfection

Immanuel Kant s Theory of Knowledge: Exploring the Relation between Sensibility and Understanding Wendell Allan Marinay

KANTIAN CONCEPTUALISM

E-LOGOS. Kant's Understanding Imagination in Critique of Pure Reason. Milos Rastovic ELECTRONIC JOURNAL FOR PHILOSOPHY ISSN /2013

The Aesthetic Idea and the Unity of Cognitive Faculties in Kant's Aesthetics

The Senses at first let in particular Ideas. (Essay Concerning Human Understanding I.II.15)

Doctoral Thesis in Ancient Philosophy. The Problem of Categories: Plotinus as Synthesis of Plato and Aristotle

Chapter 11 The Momenta of Practical Judgment

Intelligible Matter in Aristotle, Aquinas, and Lonergan. by Br. Dunstan Robidoux OSB

REVIEW ARTICLE IDEAL EMBODIMENT: KANT S THEORY OF SENSIBILITY

A Consideration of Reciprocity: The Kantian and Hegelian Treatments

UNITY, OBJECTIVITY, AND THE PASSIVITY OF EXPERIENCE

4 Unity in Variety: Theoretical, Practical and Aesthetic Reason in Kant

What Can Experimental Philosophy Do? David Chalmers

The Place of Logic within Kant s Philosophy

Copyright 2011 Todd A. Kukla

KANT, SELF-AWARENESS AND SELF-REFERENCE

Ergo. Images and Kant s Theory of Perception. 1. Introduction. University of California, Santa Cruz

Ergo. Kant On Animal Minds. 1. Introduction. Clark University

SocioBrains THE INTEGRATED APPROACH TO THE STUDY OF ART

The Second Copernican Turn of Kant s Philosophy 1

Self-Consciousness and Music in the Late Enlightenment

Pure and Applied Geometry in Kant

Philosophy Pathways Issue th December 2016

Attention and Synthesis in Kant s Conception of Experience

Chapter Two. Absolute Identity: Hegel s Critique of Reflection

KANT S SUBJECTIVE DEDUCTION

The Strengths and Weaknesses of Frege's Critique of Locke By Tony Walton

Merleau-Ponty s Transcendental Project

Predication and Ontology: The Categories

Kęstas Kirtiklis Vilnius University Not by Communication Alone: The Importance of Epistemology in the Field of Communication Theory.

206 Metaphysics. Chapter 21. Universals

Hegel and Neurosis: Idealism, Phenomenology and Realism

Kant s Argument for the Apperception Principle

Existential Cause & Individual Experience

1 Objects and Logic. 1. Abstract objects

The Language Revolution Russell Marcus Fall Class #7 Final Thoughts on Frege on Sense and Reference

Michael Friedman The Prolegomena and Natural Science

Plato s work in the philosophy of mathematics contains a variety of influential claims and arguments.

du Châtelet s ontology: element, corpuscle, body

Georg W. F. Hegel ( ) Responding to Kant

RESEMBLANCE IN DAVID HUME S TREATISE Ezio Di Nucci

Reflections on Kant s concept (and intuition) of space

HEGEL S IDEALISM. Robert Stern

The topic of this Majors Seminar is Relativism how to formulate it, and how to evaluate arguments for and against it.

PHL 317K 1 Fall 2017 Overview of Weeks 1 5

THE CRITIQUE OF JUDGEMENT PART 1: CRITIQUE OF AESTHETIC JUDGEMENT

Jacek Surzyn University of Silesia Kant s Political Philosophy

Table of Contents. Table of Contents. A Note to the Teacher... v. Introduction... 1

Critique of Pure Reason: A Brief Outline

Immanuel Kant, the author of the Copernican revolution in philosophy,

PAUL REDDING S CONTINENTAL IDEALISM (AND DELEUZE S CONTINUATION OF THE IDEALIST TRADITION) Sean Bowden

Ingenium and the navigation metaphor: an examination of the power of metaphor as a manifestation of ingenium

Abstract: A Model for McDowell. James Hersh

Transcription:

KANT S TRANSCENDENTAL LOGIC

This part of the book deals with the conditions under which judgments can express truths about objects. Here Kant tries to explain how thought about objects given in space and time is possible. (It is unlike general logic, which deals with thoughts related to one another.) Just as space and time provide the structure for perceiving, logic provides the structure for thinking. Logic provides us with all the forms of possible judgments. The book is divided into two parts. In the Transcendental Analytic deals with legitimate uses of concepts, while the Transcendental Dialectic deals with illegitimate attempts to extend knowledge beyond experience.

THE TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC

PURPOSE

Thoughts without content are empty; intuitions without concepts are blind. The understanding cannot intuit anything, and the senses cannot think anything. Only from their union can cognition arise. Hence we distinguish the science of the rules of sensibility as such, i.e., aesthetics, from the science of the rules of the understanding, as such, i.e., logic. (p. 654) Unlike sensibility, which passively receives its objects (viz. intuitions), the understanding spontaneously generates its objects (viz. concepts). The concepts of cause, self, and substance for example, are not given in intuition. There is no impression corresponding to them. The mind creates them. In this respect Hume was right. But Hume concludes that they are a fantasy. Note: Unlike concepts like table and tree, the concepts of cause, self, etc., are referred to as pure concepts of the understanding because, as Hume has shown, they are not results of generalizations from intuition. Kant wants to show instead that they are necessary for human knowledge. He needs to show that although they are subjective conditions of thought, they have objective validity. Or, to express it differently, Kant needs to show how they relate to any experience in spite of the fact that they do not come from experience. The Transcendental Deduction is just a way of explaining this. It explains how the gap between subjectivity and objectivity can be filled. The Deduction explains why it is right for us to employ the subjective concepts when they don t come from any experience.

A FUNDAMENTAL ASSUMPTION

A fundamental assumption Kant makes here is that to know is to judge. Concepts get their meaning from the role they play in judgment, and judgment is irreducible. The cognizing mind is essentially a judging mind. the only use that the understanding can make of these concepts is to judge by means of them. And since all acts of the understanding can be reduced to judgments, the understanding as such can be represented as a faculty of judgment. (p. 655) This thesis is quite similar to Wittgenstein s, that meaning is determined by use. If, for example, you lack the grammar of If S then P, you can make no use of causality. Cf. Wittgenstein s claim that The limits of language are the limits of my world. Kant states that though all our knowledge begins in experience, it by no means follows that it arises out of experience. Transcendental knowledge is not of experience itself, but it cannot be true without experience.

THE STRUCTURE OF THE TRANSCENDENTAL ANALYTIC

The Analytic is subdivided into (i) The Analytic of Concepts and (ii) The Analytic of Principles. In the Analytic of Concepts Kant tries to show which pure concepts the understanding generates, and what right it has to employ them to objects. In the Analytic of Principles he tries to show how specific principles associated with the pure understanding are justified.

THE ANALYTIC OF CONCEPTS

The Guide for (Clue to) the Discovery of all Pure Concepts of the Understanding (i.e. The Metaphysical Deduction):

Kant argues that there must be an apprehension of unity in experience. But this can never come through the senses. So there must be at least one a priori concept, viz., unity, a synthetic unity. In this section he tries to provide a clue to explaining which concepts supply the conceptual conditions of human knowledge. He is going from formal logic to concepts with content. Following Aristotle, and this is partly why it is only a clue, since he doesn t justify Aristotle s list, he says there are 12 functions of unity in judgments. Their content can derive only from their role in pure intuition.

Judgments of Quantity: Universal ( All S is P e.g., All whales are mammals. ) Particular ( Some S is P e.g., Some whales are females. ) Singular ( x is P e.g., Socrates is wise. ) Judgments of Quality: Affirmative ( S is P e.g., Bill is moral. ) Negative ( S is not P e.g., Bill is not moral. ) Infinite (S is non-p e.g., Bill is amoral. ) Judgments of Relations: Categorical ( S is P. ) Hypothetical ( If S is P then S is Q. ) Disjunctive (S is P or Q. ) Judgments of Modality: Problematic ( S might be P. ) Assertoric ( S is P. ) Apodictic ( S must be P. )

Corresponding to each type of judgment is a category. The Table of the Categories lists them as follows: Unity, plurality, and totality are categories of quantity. Reality, negation, and limitation are categories of quality. Inherence and subsistence, causality and dependence, and reciprocity are categories of relation. Possibility and impossibility, existence and non-existence, necessity and contingency are categories of modality. On the weak interpretation of the Analytic, he thinks these are categories we do have; on the strong interpretation he thinks they are ones we must have. The categories are a priori concepts that apply not to objects in general, but objects of intuition in general, intuitions being the only objects of possible experience (A96) Though not derived from experience, the categories must apply to experience (A86/B119). Example: We apply the categories in the logical form of the judgment x is P (which is singular, affirmative, categorical, and assertoric) to the intuition to get This is a face. Kant s claim is that to get from subjectivity to objectivity there must be categories.

The Metaphysical Deduction: Kant s Formulation: The same function that gives unity to the various representations in a judgment also gives unity to the mere synthesis of various representations in an intuition. This unity speaking generally is called the pure concept of the understanding. Hence the same understanding and indeed through the same acts whereby it brought about, in concepts, the logical form of judgment by means of analytic unity also brings into its representations a transcendental content, by means of the synthetic unity of the manifold in intuition as such; and because of this, these representations are called pure concepts of the understanding which apply to objects a priori something that general logic cannot accomplish. (p. 657) Example: The Judgment: This is a face. The Form of Judgment: x is P. For Kant, the categories are the mechanisms through which we go from the mark to the face. I see the mark as a face. Note: Kant isn t a direct realist. (A direct realist claims to see the world as it is directly.) He is also not an indirect realist. (He doesn t think that he infers the world from his sense-data.) Finally, he isn t an idealist. He doesn t think ideas get their reality from other ideas. Rather, he is a representationalist.

But what he hasn t shown yet is that his view isn t just a form of conventionalism (viz., that convention generates linguistic meaning). He needs to show that some categories are necessary a priori. The form of judgment provides the form (i.e. the syntax) and the intuition provides the matter (i.e. the semantics). But this (viz. the metaphysical deduction) only provides a clue because he assumes Aristotle s categories. In the Transcendental Deduction he will show only that there must be some categories. Then, in the Analogies of Experience, he defends the categories we need. Why are the categories necessary? Because we have no other way of putting the concepts together to get knowledge of the world than via the logical forms.

The Deductions of the Pure Concepts of Understanding (i.e. The Transcendental Deduction): In this section Kant shows that these categories have justified application to what we intuit. The Transcendental Unity of Apperception is the fundamental condition of cognition. The A-Deduction: NKS, A95-A114; Not in Ariew. The B-Deduction: NKS, B130-B169; Ariew, pp. 662-672. The Problem: NKS, 104: The complex idea of an object is the totality of ideas about it (e.g., the redness, the squareness, the hardness, etc.). But besides these they also contain the confused idea of something to which they all belong. (It is a red square.) A substance is a body having all these qualities. But it is something having all of these qualities. It is something = x besides, but I know not what. What provides the unity? The Problem from a Temporal Perspective: There is an auditory bob impression followed by an auditory white impression, but how do they get linked up as impressions of the same object?

Two Interpretations of the A-Deduction: The Progressive Interpretation: Kant s ambition here is anti-skeptical. He wants to deduce from his self-awareness that he must be aware of himself as having objective knowledge. The Regressive Interpretation: Kant assumes that we have knowledge of the world. He only wants to show the legitimacy of the categories. The Copernican Turn (A105): The X relating subject and object is nothing to us because we can only deal with our representations. Hence, the object can be nothing but the formal unity of consciousness (i.e., the logical functions of judgment). Relation to an object is the unification of the manifold in accordance with a priori rules. The a priori rules give us the concept of an object. So the ground of world order is in the subject, not the object! This is the Transcendental Unity of Apperception. Our relation to the world comes through our activities of unification, and this we find in the forms of judgment.

But it is clear that, since we have to deal only with the manifold of our representations, and since that x (the object) which corresponds to them is nothing to us being, as it is, something that has to be distinct from all our representations the unity which the object makes necessary can be nothing else than the formal unity of consciousness in the synthesis of the manifold of representations. It is only when we have thus produced synthetic unity in the manifold of intuition that we are in a position to say that we know the object. But this unity is impossible if the intuition cannot be generated in accordance with a rule by means of such a function of synthesis, as it makes the reproduction of the manifold a priori necessary, and renders possible a concept in which it is united. The First Edition Deduction: The three fold synthesis in the understanding (A97- A104): 1. Apprehension in intuition: The act of running through and gathering together of what is in intuition. 2. Reproduction in imagination: The role of imagination in reproducing past representations to construct something more than mere fragmentary thoughts or images (A102). When the white impression occurs the bob impression is reproduced. This might be all that happens if we were suffering from extreme amnesia, but then no thought would be produced and no knowledge obtained. 3. Recognition in a concept: This involves recognizing present thought to be the same as, and continuous with, the immediately past thought (A103): the notion of a concept as a grasping, or gathering together.

2 Cases: Case 1: Suppose I have an impression of seeing (apprehending) a black blob and an impression of hearing (apprehending) caw. Spontaneously the impressions are unified and an act of recognition occurs Ah, a crow. But the two impressions weren t one impression. They were unified. (Compare this case with the case where one person has an impression of seeing a black blob and another has the impression of hearing caw.) Case 2: Suppose I have an impression of hearing bob, and then an impression of hearing white. When the impression of white occurs bob gets reproduced and they are unified in the recognition of a bob-white. (Compare this case with the case where one person has an impression of hearing bob and then another has an impression of hearing white.) In both of these cases and this is the Copernican Turn something else also happened; a self-awareness occurred. In the former case the same self that saw a black blob heard caw ; while in the latter case, the same self that heard bob, when it heard white reproduced bob and recognized a bob-white. This is what Hume missed! The next step in the argument involves pointing out that recognizing involves synthesizing in a judgment.

We are now in a position to formulate the argument: Premise 1: The Unity Premise: All representations of which I am aware have a unity of apperception. Premise 2: The Synthesis Premise: Representations can have such unity (i.e. can be recognized) only if synthesized in a judgment. Premise 3: The Category Premise: Syntheses in judgments requires categories. Conclusion: Categories apply to all representations of which I am aware. Kant says that Only in so far as I can unite a manifold of given representations in one consciousness, is it possible for me to represent to myself the identity of the consciousness in these representations. (B133; p. 663 in Ariew) Note: He is not saying here that in every judgment I make I must be able to ascribe that judgment to myself. The awareness of self is not something over and above the judgment. The self-awareness isn t isolatable from the judgment made. something as a crow or a bob-white is already being self-aware. Just being aware of However, he is saying that this is the only time self-awareness occurs. His view is not Descartes. The self isn t a thing. It is a function, a doing. The self is not isolatable from the judgments made.

Later, in the Transcendental Dialectic, where Kant discusses the problem of dialectic illusions, in the chapter on Paralogisms, which deals with the illusions that concern the self, he will argue that neither the Transcendental Unity of Apperception nor what we might call apperceptive self-awareness, tell us anything about the mind and the self s true structure. For Kant, function does not determine substance. The Second Edition Deduction: Consider the experience of listening to a piece of music. Only if there is a unity of the self across time, can I experience the music. I can experience the music. Therefore, there is a unity of the self across time. But I can experience the music only if I can put the notes together in a unified system. The connection must be by means of categories. Therefore the categories are necessary and objective.

The Argument: Representationalist Background (An Analysis of Discursive Cognation): Premise 1: All cognition occurs via the mind s immediate awareness of its own internal representational states. The alternatives are to be (i) a direct realist, or (ii) an indirect realist, or (iii) an idealist. Premise 2: These representations are not intrinsically available to the subject s awareness; that is, unconscious representations are logically possible. Here Kant agrees with Leibniz that unconscious representations (petite perceptions) can occur. But they are not cognition. To be able to make judgments we need to be aware of the representations we must apperceive them. I.e., the I think must be able to accompany all my representations for there to be a cognative claim. Conclusion 1: Therefore, cognition must involve a special reflexive act of bringing representations to awareness that is, it must involve the apperception of representations. (From 1 and 2) Premise 3: A discursive mind is a mind that is receptive in cognition to an independent reality. (Definition of discursive : A discursive mind can be contrasted with a mind that creates its own reality.)

Note: On this interpretation Kant is not trying to argue against skepticism. He takes it that what we need to do is cognize an independently existing reality, not create it. He isn t an idealist. He is a representationalist. Also, he is maintaining that we begin holistically. There is no lower level of cognition beneath judgment. Conclusion 2: Therefore, in cognition the discursive mind apperceives its own internal states as presenting an independent objective world to itself. (From Conclusion 1 and Premise 3.) I.e., what an apperceptive mind apperceives are its own internal states as representing an independent world. Premise 4: That is to say that discursive cognition is the apperception of sensible intuitions. (From Conclusion 2 and the definition of sensible intuition as a determination of the faculty of receptivity (or sensibility) which the subject grasps as presenting an object.) Since an independent world is a world capable of being sensed, all discursive cognition is apperception of sensible intuitions that is things in space and time. Premise 5: All objects of sensible intuitions are represented as complex. There is an Implicit assumption here--certainly valid in the case of human cognition-- that in representing objects in space and/or time one thereby represents them as complex. We never have an awareness of something absolutely simple.

Conclusion 3: Therefore, discursive cognition is the apperception of unified complex representations. (From 6 and 7) The Master Argument (#16): To apperceive unified complex representations is to apperceive all of the component representations as hanging together in a unity. (The principle of the necessary unity of apperception --an analytic truth.)

EXAM 3 STUDY QUESTIONS: 1. Discuss Kant s Aesthetics. 2. Discuss Kant s Metaphysical Deduction (i.e., Chapter I of the Analytic, pp. 653-658).